Select Committee on Foreign Affairs Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 300 - 319)

TUESDAY 8 FEBRUARY 2000

MR MARK LITTMAN, QC, PROFESSOR CHRISTOPHER GREENWOOD, QC AND PROFESSOR VAUGHAN LOWE

  300. If, at the point when the peaceful intervention was manifestly not working, and if it be your contention that in every case prior approval of the Security Council is needed before any intervention, this means in practice that in the many cases the international community would have to stand on the sidelines of a country at a time when the most awful humanitarian violations were taking place and be unable to do anything.
  (Mr Littman) What they could do is to use the wide range of peaceful methods which are open to them by negotiation, by economic sanctions, by embargoes, matters of that kind. They could use the whole of the moral resources and the peaceful resources of the United Nations, which is the only structure in the world which we have for this purpose. If the use of force is properly vetoed on the Security Council in the sense that it is legally vetoed by people who have the right to veto it, that is the position.

  301. Even if that veto is for extraneous, capricious reasons as in relation to UNPREDEP? Your contention is that only embargoes and sanctions, as in the case of Yugoslavia, would be appropriate and in the face of the most extreme humanitarian excesses the international community would still not be able to use force?
  (Mr Littman) In the second supplementary memorandum which I put in yesterday, I gave my reason for thinking not only that it was not a principle of international law that unilateral force could be used in such a case without the Security Council, but it would be contrary to public policy if it were. Would you allow me to remind you very briefly of my reasons for thinking that?

  302. Briefly, if you would.
  (Mr Littman) The first reason is that I think it will lead to more war. The dominant motive, but not the only motive, for the Charter of the United Nations which is so essential to us is to reduce the possibility of wars such as have been experienced in the previous 30 years prior to the Charter, where some 80 million people were killed.

  303. That was a matter of judgment and prudential reason rather than in itself a principle?
  (Mr Littman) Absolutely. I am addressing the question whether, assuming there is no such principle, it would be a good thing to have one. That, I agree, is not a question of law primarily; it is a question of politics, judgment and public policy for these reasons I am putting forward. That is one reason. The danger of there being an increase in the volume of violent conflict in the world is emphasised by the fact that, according to the material that I have seen, there are at any one time and have been in the last decade something like 30 or 40 armed conflicts going on in the world, in most of which issues of human rights can be said to have arisen. The second reason is one of the reasons that the Foreign Office gave for rejecting the principle which was that the principle was likely to be abused. Many of us remember that in the case of both Czechoslovakia and Poland Hitler used as one of his main reasons for justifying his invasion that the German minority in those two countries was suffering an abuse of its human rights. I agree with what one of my colleagues here has said in their paper. I agree that all rights in the field of international law can be abused but it seems to me that the Foreign Office was right in saying it is a very material factor to be taken into account.

  304. That is an absolutist view. You are saying that even in the most extreme cases the danger of precedent and abuse should rule out intervention.
  (Mr Littman) I am saying that because of the danger of abuse this principle should not be adopted and that the balance of public interest is against it. A third reason I give is that it is something which will only be used by powerful nations against smaller nations and never against a nation which has the nuclear weapon. I think this is likely to be resented by smaller nations and might drive them to seek to develop weapons to which even the most powerful nations in the world would be vulnerable.

  305. That is again a prudential reason rather than a legal reason.
  (Mr Littman) These are reasons of policy for not having the principle. The reason I am developing this is that I think, on the legal front, a number of people—and I think this is the position of Professor Vaughan Lowe—would like to see such a principle but they recognise there are at least difficulties in saying that such a principle has now been established. There are some other reasons which I have developed in my paper.

Ms Abbott

  306. The problem I have had with this all along is that I can see the argument that it would be desirable to have a legal right of humanitarian intervention, but it is not wholly clear to me that there is now a legal right of humanitarian intervention. The position of the British government in evidence to the Committee was that military intervention would normally be based on a Security Council resolution but "there may also be cases of overwhelming humanitarian necessity where, in the light of all the circumstances, the limited use of force is justifiable to avert humanitarian catastrophe". What I would like to ask Professor Vaughan Lowe is what is the statement you agree with? Is this actually a statement of law?
  (Professor Lowe) They did not use the words "legal right" in the bit you read out; they used the word "right", which makes it difficult to argue with.

  307. Is it a statement of law? I am trying to get back to what does the law say rather than what do we want the law to say.
  (Professor Lowe) I think your representation is right. There is as yet no established right of humanitarian intervention in international law. I am one of the people who thinks that there should be.

  308. I am glad we have made that distinction. There is no right, but you are arguing there should be. It could be that the Committee might agree with you. I think it is important to establish that there is no right of humanitarian intervention but, Professor Greenwood, do you believe that as the law presently stands there is a legal right of humanitarian intervention?
  (Professor Greenwood) I certainly do believe that there is a legal right of humanitarian intervention as the law stands. I would also strongly disagree with Mr Littman in terms of the policy question that underlies it. It seems to me that there is an extremely powerful policy case to be made for intervention in extreme cases like this.

  309. The point I want to stress—and this is why we have a particular session on the legal side—is that there are two threads to this argument. One is the desirability of a right of humanitarian intervention and one is whether one actually exists now. You are saying there is. How do you explain that? Where does it lie?
  (Professor Greenwood) It lies, in my opinion, in customary international law. It evolved on the basis of state practice but it is state practice which has taken place largely in the space of the last ten years for this very practical reason. A central element in the legal right and the way in which that right was presented by British ministers is that the Security Council here have identified that there was a serious threat to international peace, that there was an impending humanitarian catastrophe. Those words I think are taken verbatim from resolution 1199. You would not have had that type of practice back in the 1970s and 1980s because the Security Council simply was not in a position to take decisions of that kind. All of this has been unlocked since the end of the Cold War. If you look at the cases of state practice, you find there are quite a number of them in the last ten years. It is not just the powerful states. You have the west African countries'—

Chairman

  310. ECOWAS.
  (Professor Greenwood)—intervention in Liberia. With the greatest of respect, nobody would suggest that any of the ECOWAS players were the major military powers of the world. You have the intervention first in northern Iraq in the late spring of 1991; then the intervention in southern Iraq, the no fly zone, in 1992, this time by the British, the Americans, the French and the Dutch. That of course was justified on the basis of humanitarian intervention. Then we can see what sort of reaction those claims got. If the law was as straightforward as Mr Littman and Professor Brownlie have suggested, I would expect to find an overwhelming chorus of disapproval of state practice and it is not there.

Ms Abbott

  311. What you are saying is because states have been doing it that makes it legal.
  (Professor Greenwood) That is how customary international law develops, yes.

Dr Starkey

  312. Is it not just that states have done it but that states have done it and the international community at large has not put its hand up and said, "This is appalling"?
  (Professor Greenwood) Yes. With state practice, you have to look at a number of different strands. You have to look at what is done, at the justifications put forward for that and at the reaction of other states to it, which is why it is quite striking in the case of Kosovo that, when the matter went to the Security Council a few days after the intervention started, when the Russians put down a proposal to condemn the NATO action as illegal, it was defeated by 12 votes to three. It is not a case of the British, the Americans and the French having to rely upon a veto or the NATO members that are on the Security Council blocking something. You have a very solid chorus of opposition to that Russian motion from states in the third world, states that were not in any way directly involved in this operation.

Mr Illsley

  313. Do you think we are missing an opportunity to clarify a form for the precedent in objecting to the International Court of Justice case and the procedural motion rather than arguing the whole principle there and then, or is that precedent not necessary?
  (Professor Greenwood) I am sorry; I am in considerable difficulty about this because I am one of the counsel in the case in the International Court. I am not therefore allowed to deal with the ongoing proceedings.

Sir John Stanley

  314. I would like to ask a question to each of our three witnesses, please, and that is the relationship as they see it legally between the use of force by NATO in Kosovo and the UN Charter. The Committee is aware that there is a general prohibition under the UN Charter on the use of force. The Committee is also aware that there are certainly at least two exceptions in the Charter to it, the exception provided in Article 42 in which the Security Council is authorised to use force "to maintain or restore international peace and security", and the exception in Article 51 which recognises the right of self-defence. However, the key general prohibition on the use of force in most circumstances is of course enshrined in Article 2.4 which reads: "All members shall refrain in their international relations from the threat or use of force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any state or in any other manner inconsistent with the purposes of the United Nations". The question I would like each of our three witnesses to answer is whether they take the view that the use of force by NATO in Kosovo was in breach or not of the UN Charter.
  (Mr Littman) In my opinion, it plainly was in breach. I have no doubt at all upon the true construction of the Charter and this is supported by a vast range of authorities cited by Professor Brownlie, citations going back 30 or 40 years, which include three former Presidents of the International Court of Justice at The Hague. The effect of the Charter is that the only occasions on which force is permitted to resolve disputes between states is either in self-defence—that means individual or collective self-defence—or upon the authority of the Security Council, neither of which applied here.
  (Professor Lowe) It is a breach of the Charter as it was drafted more than half a century ago but it is consonant with the way that international customary law is developing at the moment. There is no clear moment in time at which it can be said that the rule of customary law has emerged. There is very much less between Professor Greenwood and me than might be supposed on this matter, in terms of the appraisal of the legality of it. I think international law is plainly moving in the direction of supporting limited humanitarian intervention. I do not think it has got there yet. The difference between us is over the weight that we attach to the limited number of episodes in the short period of time that we have seen so far.
  (Professor Greenwood) I think one has to read Article 2.4, which was drafted more than 50 years ago, in the light of the way that the law and practice have evolved since. For example, Article 51 of the Charter on self-defence preserves the right of self-defence if an armed attack occurs against a Member State. For more than 30 years, it has been the almost universal practice of states, supported by a majority of the scholars who write on this area, to describe that provision as encompassing a right of anticipatory self-defence where a state believes that it is about to be subject to an imminent armed attack. That, for example, has been the position of this country since longer than I can remember. Article 2.4 has to be read in the same sort of way. If one looks at a use of force that is designed to prevent very large scale loss of life—we are not talking here about the use of force to deal with every day violations of human rights; we are looking at the use of force to try and prevent the most serious human rights abuses of them all—in those circumstances, I cannot see that that is inconsistent with the purposes of the UN. If it is used in such a way as to deal with a human rights emergency but not in order to make territorial gains at the expense of another state, I do not see it myself as being a use of force contrary to the territorial integrity or political independence of the state. Nobody would suggest today that Yugoslavia's political independence includes an independent right to massacre a large proportion of its own population.

  315. I have a further one flowing from that which we have briefly touched on in Mr Littman's earlier remarks. I think Professor Lowe also made a brief reference to it. This is a very important point on which it would be helpful to have a view from all three of you. Do you believe that it would be desirable in international law terms that a clear right of intervention within a sovereign state should be created on extreme humanitarian need grounds?
  (Mr Littman) May I enquire whether that is without the authority of the Security Council?

  316. With the authority of the United Nations.
  (Mr Littman) With the authority of the Security Council? Under the Charter of the United Nations, the Security Council can authorise the use of force in certain circumstances. I have not been addressing myself to that question. It may cover the case which has been put to me. What we are here dealing with is a case which was admittedly without the authority of the Security Council. What I am concerned about is the existence of a principle other than arising in self-defence that force can be used without the authority of the Security Council. On that, for the reasons I gave earlier on and some additional reasons, if I could just give you the reference briefly, I do not think it would be at all a good idea to have such a principle. Here I venture to disagree with my colleague, Professor Lowe. I have mentioned certain reasons and I would like to add a couple of others. They are referred to in my first supplementary memorandum at paragraph 16. "In my view there are strong reasons why the introduction of the humanitarian exception . . .". Ms Abbott, this is the second question which you were putting on one side for the moment. I would like to perhaps just reinforce my view on that because I think it is assumed by a lot of people, who defend the decision in the present case, that it is desirable there should be such a principle. I agree it is an entirely separate question. I have already referred to the danger that it would lead to more violent conflict. In support of that I do argue that one thing that can be predicated with certainty by war is that no one can be sure what will happen or indeed that it will improve the observance of civil rights. "In Kosovo, for example, ethnic cleansing has not been stopped. It has only been reversed, the persecuted becoming the persecutors." The second reason I give that I have not mentioned yet is that it would involve the sidelining of the Security Council, for it would introduce a potentially large class of cases where states could start wars without the authority of the Security Council. Professor Lowe disapproves any sidelining of the United Nations. He suggests however that this could be avoided by restricting the new exception to cases where the Security Council had already passed resolutions criticising the target state but without authorising the use of force. This might be, for example, because the use of force might be vetoed by one or more permanent members of the Security Council for whatever reason, good or bad. It seems to me that this solution would be counter productive, for once it was established that the passing of the non-force resolution would legally open the door to forceful intervention the states that were opposed to the latter would veto the former. This might be unfortunate for the non-force resolution might introduce other measures, short of force, which might nevertheless be quite effective. My third reason I have not mentioned yet but it is perhaps the most important. "The sidelining of the Security Council would strike at the very heart of the United Nations and might even destroy it, in my opinion. As Professor Lowe says in a powerful passage on page eight, the Security Council is the only body charged with worldwide responsibility for the maintenance of peace and security and to sideline it would be foolish especially at the present time when, he says, it is beginning to prove itself. In my view, it could not only be foolish; it could be fatal to the United Nations for although the United Nations has many other functions—for example, in the field of education, civil rights and economic welfare—its central function is . . ." undoubtedly in the field of the maintenance of peace.

  317. Could Professor Greenwood and Professor Lowe reply to my original question? Could they also reply to the two alternatives which have now emerged? Do you believe there should be a right created in international law of humanitarian intervention within a sovereign state, both with the authority of the Security Council and without the authority of the Security Council?
  (Professor Greenwood) So far as the intervention with the authority of the Security Council is concerned, that I think is unequivocally part of international law today. It does not require any further reinforcement as a proposition of law. The Security Council, for example, has authorised military intervention in the last ten years in Somalia, in Haiti and eventually in Liberia after the initial action in East Timor. That I think is a point of common ground between the three of us. So far as the second question is concerned, what about intervention without an explicit mandate from the Security Council, in relation to the first question that Ms Abbott asked me, I stand by what I said earlier: that that right is already part of customary international law. It does not need to be written into a text. If I could perhaps pick up what Mr Littman has just said about it being dangerous on policy grounds, which I accept is an entirely different matter, yes, any right is open to abuse but let us have a look also at the effect of not intervening. If you want an example of that, just look at the effects of what happened in Rwanda in 1994 when the international community did not take action, either through the Security Council or without the Security Council authority. We could probably have saved the lives, at a conservative estimate, of at least half a million people if we had done. As for intervention being something which would spark off more war, what happened in Rwanda when there was no intervention was not only a tragedy within that country; it has now had the knock-on effect of creating a war which has taken in most of central Africa. An area about three or four times the size of the European Community is now in a condition of warfare, sucking in over a dozen states. The risks of not intervening are something that have to be taken very carefully into account as well as the possibility that a right of intervention could be abused.
  (Professor Lowe) That is almost the only important question that is left: what we should do. The intervention has taken place. It took place in the face of overwhelming moral imperatives and all the NATO states sought desperately to articulate the legal justification which would encapsulate that moral imperative. We have to do it and it is much more important to get that right for the future than it is to make some retrospective judgment on the legality of the action that took place last year. I am wholly in favour of it. I think the policy reasons that my colleague has put out against it are wrong. I do not accept the argument that an increase in the use of violence is even necessarily wrong. It may be that there are circumstances where it is necessary to use force, and if that is one extra instance then so be it. I am one of the people who happens to think that the use of military force is, in many circumstances, a much more discriminating weapon than the use of economic sanctions and other measures, which I think often impose hardship on people who are not the targets of the action against them. I am quite prepared to see an increase in the use of force for limited humanitarian purposes. Of course there is a danger of abuse; there is also a danger of abuse in not adopting the principle. The result of preserving the duty of non-intervention would be to allow people like Milosevic to carry on massacring their civilians under the shield of their sovereignty. That is not something that anyone would tolerate. I do not accept the argument that it is something which would be limited to a right to be enjoyed by the powerful for the reasons that Professor Greenwood has said. History shows that to be wrong. Nor do I accept that it would undermine the Security Council and the United Nations. What signs there are point in exactly the opposite direction. Far from states wanting to veto Security Council involvement in these exercises, the experience of the Timor operation seems to me to suggest that states are now more keen to keep the Security Council seized of the matter and keep effective control over it, because they see that the alternative is to allow groups of states to take action unilaterally. Perversely, stepping outside of the Security Council action in Kosovo may have strengthened the Security Council in this respect. The final point on eating the heart out of the United Nations again I simply do not accept because the United Nations' bases 50 years ago on suppositions about the way in which the Security Council would be able to draw on armed force for its purposes have not been proved right. It is simply a case of the international community adjusting to the realities of military and political life.

Mr Rowlands

  318. Professor Greenwood, if we accept the government's case that there was an overwhelming humanitarian necessity which justified the use of force, who has or should have the right to define that that situation exists? Is it the right of one state to say that that exists in a neighbouring state and therefore take appropriate action, or would it require a group of states? Who is going to do the defining? If we accept this principle, who has at this moment the right to define that such a situation exists and that intervention is justified?
  (Professor Greenwood) Obviously, it is very much more desirable if that determination is made by an independent and authoritative body. In the case of Kosovo, that is exactly what you did have because the Security Council took that decision.

  319. They did not adopt force. They accepted there was a serious situation and a breach of peace.
  (Professor Greenwood) I may have misunderstood your question. What the Security Council did do was to decide that there was an imminent humanitarian catastrophe, which I thought was the point you were raising with me, who decides whether that is there. In this case, the Security Council said so in September 1998 and then it repeated its view through a presidential statement in January 1999.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2000
Prepared 11 May 2000