Further evidence submitted by the Refugee
Legal Centre in response to questions from the Committee (AIA
24C)
Question 1: Under the proposed Bill, only
the President of the Tribunal will have power to refer a point
of law to an appellate court, if it is of considerable complexity
or importance; or it relates to an earlier decision of the appellate
court which is binding on the Tribunal. How will this impact upon
the quality of legal authorities in asylum proceedings?
The proposal to restrict access to the appellate
court to referrals by the President of the Asylum and Immigration
Tribunal deprives individual appellants of the right to a full
independent review of decisions of the AIT except by application
to the European Court of Human Rights.
The current procedure is for an application
for permission to appeal to the Court of Appeal to be first submitted
to the Immigration Appeal Tribunal. In the event that application
is refused, the appellant can renew his application to the Court
of Appeal within strict time limits. The Tribunal has the power
to grant permission to appeal to the Court of Appeal on a point
of law. However, in the experience of the Refugee Legal Centre
a large majority of applications for permission to appeal are
refused by the Tribunal.
Since 2001 the RLC has brought 25 appeals from
determinations of the Immigration Appeal Tribunal in-house. Of
these, permission to appeal was granted by the Tribunal itself
on 3 occasions. In the other 22 cases, permission to appeal was
sought directly from the Court of Appeal. Of those leave to appeal
was granted by the Court of Appeal in 13 cases, 6 times on the
papers, and 7 times at an oral hearing. This corresponds to a
success rate in obtaining permission to appeal following a refusal
of permission by the Immigration Appeal Tribunal of 59%. The Committee
may infer from this that the Tribunal is inherently more likely
to lean towards supporting its own decisions rather than referring
to the Court of Appeal. Under the current procedures a further
application for permission to appeal can be made directly to the
Court of Appeal. The current proposals will remove this essential
safeguard.
It is of some concern that power of reference
is given solely to the President of the Tribunal. There is no
guidance as to what issues will be considered to be sufficiently
complex or important. Whilst the President of the Tribunal is
a highly qualified and experienced judge, to place such a degree
of decision making in the hands of one person is inherently unsatisfactory.
Without a mechanism for independent applications to the appellate
court it could unduly influence the direction of jurisprudence
according to the views of one individual, however eminent.
In Standing Committee the Government relied
on the fact that the Tribunal has a system of `starred' determinations
on points of law which were said to be "critical in setting
the tone and direction of policy and law".[199]The
Tribunal has in effect ceased to use this system of authority;
the last known `starred' determination was issued in December
2002. The current system has changed to a system of "reported"
determinations in which the IAT itself chooses which decisions
are to be made available for use as authority. The Refugee Legal
Centre has several concerns about the reliability of using AIT
determinations in lieu of authoritative Court of Appeal decisions.
Firstly, even if the proposed AIT were to continue
with a system of `starred' decisions, it is clear that such decisions
have, on several occasions, been found to be wrong in law, or
later criticised by higher courts. For example, Zenovics v SSHD
(01 TH 0631);[200]
Kacaj v SSHD [2001] INLR 354[201]and
Noruwa v SSHD (00 TH 2345).[202]
Secondly, unlike the "starred" determinations,
current reported determinations are cases that are not necessarily
heard by a full legal panel or by the President of the Tribunal.
Finally, the Leggatt Report found it to be inappropriate
for first tier Tribunals to set binding precedent.[203]
Although the report did support some form of system of binding
precedent, this was clearly only approved in the context of a
two tier Tribunal system. The AIT is proposed as a one-tier system
only. The suggested system of precedent would be contrary to the
recommendations made by Sir Andrew Leggatt in his comprehensive
report.
Question 2: What disadvantages will be caused
by the prohibition on appeals to the House of Lords contained
in the new Bill?
At present, the House of Lords only consider
appeals that either the Court of Appeal or the House of Lords
itself considers to be of public importance. The protection of
fundamental human rights lies at the core of immigration and asylum
law. It is no doubt for this reason that the House of Lords considers
it sufficiently important to hear several cases in this field
every year.
The House of Lords has given a number of important
judgments in the last few years which are essential in giving
guidance and certainty to the law. For example, in the landmark
decision of Islam v SSHD; Shah v IAT & SSHD [1999] Imm AR
283 the House of Lords found that persecuted women in Pakistan
could constitute a "social group" for the purposes of
the Refugee Convention. Mrs Shah had been refused permission to
appeal to the Tribunal but this decision was quashed on Judicial
Review then appealed to the Court of Appeal by the Secretary of
State. In Mrs Islam's case, the previous decisions of the Immigration
Tribunal and the Court of Appeal were both overturned. Under the
current proposals to deny asylum seekers access to review by the
House of Lords and the Administrative Court, neither women would
have succeeded in their claims for refugee status.
Major decisions of the House of Lords and the
Court of Appeal are given due regard by other jurisdictions in
the development of international refugee law. If jurisprudence
is reduced to a small number of Tribunal decisions made with the
guidance of the Court of Appeal, the standing of UK jurisprudence
on these issues is likely to be severely diminished. The House
of Lords quite properly considers jurisprudence from higher courts
in other jurisdictions when coming to its decisions. The abolition
of the House of Lords' jurisdiction will lead to a greater reliance
on decisions made by higher courts in other jurisdictions, such
as Canada and Australia, and inherently diminish the authority
of our own higher courts.
Decisions made by the European Court of Human
Rights on the effect of the ECHR on UK immigration law would be
deprived of the learning of the House of Lords, but would have
to be given effect in UK courts through the Human Rights Act 1998,
s3.
Unlike the House of Lords, the Court of Appeal
can only review its previous decisions if a decision can be shown
to be demonstrably wrong or if it conflicts with an earlier decision.
The scope of the Court of Appeal to review earlier decisions is
therefore considerably less than that of the House of Lords. The
fact that decisions of the Court of Appeal will not be subject
to review in respect of a certain category of cases, will diminish
its standing.
The Refugee Legal Centre is unaware of any other
major European jurisdiction in which access to higher courts has
been restricted in such a way. This would be an unusual precedent
that undermines the authority the House of Lords.
With one hand the Government is establishing
an independent Supreme Court. With the other, it seeks to remove
that court's scrutiny of one of the most fast moving, complex
and controversial areas of law and public policy. The Refugee
Legal Centre considers that this attempt to limit the jurisdiction
of the new Supreme Court before its institution does not bode
well for that body's future.
Question 3: What do you believe would be the
result of a reduction of Legal Help in asylum cases?
In summary, the reduction of Legal Help and
Controlled Legal Representation (CLR) in asylum cases will only
reduce the quality of preparation and presentation of asylum applications
and appeals and will exacerbate existing problems of poor Home
Office decision-making.
The need for quality representation is paramount
in the light of the seriousness of the issues raised in an asylum
application. If anything, this is to become more imperative in
view of the following pressures on asylum decision-making:
(i) The Home Office itself recognises that
the quality of initial decision-making is poor and needs improvement.
Amnesty International has recently highlighted this as a serious
concern.[204]
Ministerial statements during the recent Standing Committee debates
confirmed, "the government accepted the need for high quality
at all stages of the asylum process".[205]However,
restrictions in the ability of legal representatives to properly
put forward a case at an early stage is likely to lead to even
poorer initial decisions.
(ii) There is a dearth of good quality legal
representation. The proposals to reduce Legal Help has already
led to leading firms, such as Winstanley Burgess Solicitors, to
close. A number of other leading firms are considering their position
in the light of the cuts to legal aid. The Refugee Legal Centre
runs a regular drop-in advice surgery. In our recent experience,
it is becoming increasingly difficult to refer or signpost asylum
seekers at appeal stage to good quality representatives. This
is normally because the best providers have limited capacity and
some of their immigration departments in firms are not taking
on any new clients due to the fears in respect of legal aid cuts.
A reduction in Legal Help will only exacerbate this situation.
(iii) The extension of the non-suspensive
appeals provisions makes initial preparation and representation
absolutely vital if there is to be no in country review of a negative
asylum decision. Poor decision-making at this stage could lead
to the return of genuine applicants to their countries of origin
with no meaningful review.
(iv) The proposed AIT will effectively be
the only remedy available to an applicant. A reduction in the
provision of Legal Help and CLR can only reduce the quality of
preparation of appeals at a time when such an appeal will play
an even more vital role as a safeguard to poor decision-making.
In addition to the pressurised workload of adjudicators and the
presumption against adjournments, the safety of decisions made
by the AIT would be seriously impaired.
(v) Under the proposed system, the AIT's
review of its own decision becomes a crucial procedural safeguard.
If the amount of time representatives can spend on drafting an
application for a review is limited to a maximum of 3 hours, with
no possibility for extension, as is the case for applications
for permission to the Tribunal, injustices will be done. The applications
risk being of insufficient quality to allow the AIT to make quality
reviews of its own decision.
The pressures that will be placed on the safety
and integrity of the asylum decision-making system by the proposals
in the Bill, in conjunction with a reduction in Legal Help, is
likely to increase the number of fresh applications made by applicants.
If an applicant is not provided with the resources to fully put
forward an initial application or a subsequent appeal, it is inevitable
that further evidence and information may come to light at a later
stage in the process. Compelling fresh evidence would have to
be considered by the Secretary of State. The proposals are therefore
likely to reduce the effectiveness and quality of the asylum decision-making
system.
Refugee Legal Centre
11 February 2004
Annex A
ASYLUM AND IMMIGRATION BILL OUSTING JUDICIAL
REVIEW: COMMON LAW
OPINION
1. I have been asked by the Refugee Legal
Centre whether I am able to identify and outline any viable argument,
using the common law, by which a statutory ouster of judicial
review could be regarded as legally questionable. That issue arises
because of clause 10 of the new Asylum and Immigration Bill.
2. I will not set out here an analysis of
the provisions of the Bill themselves, the nature and effect of
the proposed statutory ouster, or the proposed power of limited
referral to the appellate court. I will start from the premise
that there would be a new Act involving a clear and unambiguous
exclusion, in primary legislation, of the right which an asylum-seeker
would otherwise have, to seek judicial review of asylum decisions
made by public authorities. I also think it wise to assume that
the Court, whether on a direct challenge to the new legislation
or collaterally by being invited to disapply it, would focus on
the Act head-on rather than, say, its implementation by the Executive
(cf. R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p Fire
Brigades Union [1995] 2 AC 513; R v Secretary of State for Education
and Employment, ex p Liverpool Hope University College [2001]
EWCA Civ 362 [2001] ELR 552). I will leave to one side particular
arguments which may arise by reference to the ECHR (and the Human
Rights Act), international law (including international refugee
law) and EC law. My focus is on the common law.
3. It is necessary to recognise that conventional
principles, as traditionally applied by the domestic courts, would
not question the legality of clear and unambiguous primary legislation
ousting judicial review. The starting-point is the supremacy of
Parliament. As has been said (R (on the application of Anderson)
v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2002] UKHL 46 [2003]
1 AC 837 at [39] per Lord Steyn):
the supremacy of Parliament is the paramount
principle of our constitution.
The supremacy of Parliament means of course
that the Courts' role is to interpret primary legislation, not
to question its content. There is a "constitutional imperative
that the courts stick to their interpretative role and do not
assume the mantle of legislators" (R (on the application
of Quintavalle) v Secretary of State for Health [2003] UKHL 13
[2003] 2 WLR 692 at [15] (Lord Bingham)), it being "impermissible
. . . to develop the law in a direction which is contrary to the
expressed will of Parliament" (R v Chief Constable of the
Royal Ulster Constabulary, ex p Begley [1997] 1 WLR 1475, 1480H).
As Lord Diplock famously said in Duport Steels Ltd v Sirs [1980]
1 WLR 142, 157B-158C:
it cannot be too strongly emphasised that the
British constitution, though largely unwritten, is firmly based
upon the separation of powers; Parliament makes the laws, the
judiciary interpret them . . . Where the meaning of the statutory
words is plain and unambiguous it is not for the judges to invent
fancied ambiguities as an excuse for failing to give effect to
its plain meaning because they themselves consider that the consequences
of doing so would be inexpedient, or even unjust or immoral. In
controversial matters . . . there is room for differences of opinion
as to what is expedient, what is just and what is morally justifiable.
Under our constitution it is Parliament's opinion on these matters
that is paramount.
4. Thus, conventional and well-established
doctrine has it that Parliament can enact whatever legislation
it pleases, including restricting fundamental rights (including
access to the courts), by plain words in primary legislation.
Viscount Simonds referred in Pyx Granite Co Ltd v Ministry of
Housing and Local Government [1960] AC 260 at 286 to "the
subject's recourse to Her Majesty's courts for the determination
of his rights" as being capable of being "excluded .
. . by clear words"; and Lord Sumner had referred in R v
Nat Bell Liquors Ltd [1922] 2 AC 128 at 162 to legislation "limiting
the jurisdiction by way of certiorari . . . where explicit language
is used for that purpose". Likewise, orthodoxy holds that,
leaving aside EC law (as to which see R v Secretary of State for
Employment, ex p Equal Opportunities Commission [1995] 1 AC 1),
the Court will not strike down, declare to be invalid, or disapply,
primary legislation. As the Court of Appeal explained in R (on
the application of Southall) v Secretary of State for Foreign
and Commonwealth Affairs [2003] EWCA Civ 1002 14th July 2003 unrep.
at [10]:
The fact is that so far no court in the last
century and more has set aside any provision of an Act of Parliament
as being unlawful save in the circumstances set out in the European
Communities Act.
5. It can be seen how conventional principles,
based on legislative supremacy, could readily and understandably
be treated as the beginning and end of the question. Especially
when it is seen that the conventional principles are reflected
and reinforced in the Human Rights Act 1998, by which Parliamentary
supremacy is retained, with the Courts' role (even under the special
duty in s.3) being an interpretative one, and under which there
is a tailored and expressly-conferred power to make declarations
of compatibility. They are also reflected in discussion of the
pre-HRA (common law) approach to fundamental rights, it being
said that Parliament can, provided it does so by clear words,
take away fundamental rights. As Lord Hoffmann explained the position
in R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p Simms
[2000] 2 AC 115 at 131E-G:
in a constitution which, like ours, acknowledges
the sovereignty of Parliament . . . Parliament can, if it chooses,
legislate contrary to fundamental principles of human rights .
. . But the principle of legality means that Parliament must squarely
confront what it is doing . . . [by] express language or necessary
implication ...
6. The HRA (and the European Communities
Act 1972) reflects Parliament's answer to a question of constitutional
balance, concerning the extent to which the Court can review,
impeach or disapply a provision of primary legislation. Lord Hoffmann's
comments in Simms reflect the common law's answer, given by the
Courts. The law does not stand still. As Lord Mackay said in Kuddus
v Chief Constable of Leicestershire Constabulary [2001] UKHL 29
[2002] 2 AC 122 at [33]:
The genius of the common law is its capacity
to develop.
And as Steyn LJ said in R v Panel on Take-overs
and Mergers, ex p Fayed [1992] BCC 524 at 536C:
In the developing field of judicial review it
is usually unwise to say "never".
7. There are a number of features which
link and support the argument for taking a more radical approach.
The first feature is the overarching legal concept of the rule
of law. This is a core value at the heart of our unwritten Constitution.
Lord Bridge expressed it in this way (R v Horseferry Road Magistrates'
Court, ex p Bennett [1994] 1 AC 42, 67F):
There is, I think, no principle more basic to
any proper system of law than the maintenance of the rule of law
itself.
More recently, Lord Steyn has referred (R (on
the application of Anufrijeva) v Secretary of State for the Home
Department [2003] UKHL 36 [2003] 3 WLR 252 at [28]) to:
the constitutional principle requiring the rule
of law to be observed.
8. The second feature is the protection
of fundamental, "constitutional" rights, including the
right of access to law, and the development of "principles
of legality". Independently of the ECHR, and the HRA, the
common law has increasingly come to recognise the existence and
implications of basic human rights. Most importantly, such rights
are capable of being characterised as "constitutional rights"
(see eg. R v Lord Chancellor, ex p Lightfoot [2000] QB 597, 609B),
a concept traced back at least as far as R v Secretary of State
for the Home Department, ex p Leech [1994] QB 198, 210A. As was
said in Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [2002] EWHC 195 (Admin)
[2003] QB 151 at [62]:
In the present state of its maturity the common
law has come to recognise that there exist rights which should
properly be classified as constitutional . . .
Access to law is at the fore of these constitutional
rights, so that (R (on the application of Anufrijeva) v Secretary
of State for the Home Department [2003] UKHL 36 [2003] 3 WLR 252
at [26] per Lord Steyn):
the right of access to justice . . . is a fundamental
and constitutional principle of our legal system.
Access to law is crucially important in the
refugee context, hence the importance of judicial review, because
of (R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p Bugdaycay
[1987] AC 514, 531E-G per Lord Bridge) "the gravity of the
issue" since "the most fundamental of all human rights
is the individual's right to life" and the asylum decision
"may put the [individual]'s life at risk".
9. The third feature, alongside the recognition
of "constitutional rights", is the developing law as
to what has been called the "principle of legality":
see especially R v Secretary of State for the Home Department,
ex p Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, 130D-G; and R v Secretary of State
for the Home Department, ex p Pierson [1998] AC 539, 573G-575D,
587C-590A. Thus far, Courts have said (or assumed) that even "constitutional"
rights are embedded in the law only insofar as not excluded by
plain words in primary legislation. But it is crucial to appreciate
that this is not because such restraint is imposed by the Court,
still less because commanded by Parliament itself (eg. in the
HRA). Rather, it constitutes a present choice on the part of the
common law, recognising the point which the common law has so
far reached. As Laws LJ has commented (respectively, in R v Lord
Chancellor, ex p Witham [1998] QB 575, 581E and then in R (on
the application of International Transport Roth GmbH) v Secretary
of State for the Home Department [2002] EWCA Civ 158 [2003] QB
728 at [71]):
at a time when the common law continues to accord
a legislative supremacy to Parliament, the notion of a constitutional
right can in my judgment inhere only in this proposition, that
the right in question cannot be abrogated by the state save by
specific provision in an Act of Parliament, or by regulations
whose vires in main legislation specifically confers the power
to abrogate. General words will not suffice.
In its present state of evolution, the British
system may be said to stand at an intermediate stage between parliamentary
sovereignty and constitutional supremacy.
The potential of the "principle of legality"
as establishing constitutional primacy even for Acts of Parliament
can be seen to be evident from this passage (B (A Minor) v Director
of Public Prosecutions [2000] 2 WLR 452, 463H per Lord Steyn):
Parliament does not write on a blank sheet. The
sovereignty of Parliament is the paramount principle of our constitution.
But Parliament legislates against the background of the principle
of legality.
10. The fourth feature is the nature of
judicial review itself. Judicial review is not simply a form of
legal proceeding, interference with which impacts on access to
law. It is much more than that. Judicial review involves the Court
recognising and asserting its constitutional function of scrutinising
the legality of administrative action. As many academics have
pointed out, there is more to judicial review than "ultra
vires" theory and the enforcement of the will of Parliament.
Byles J famously recognised "the justice of the common law"
(Cooper v Wandsworth Board of Works (1863) 14 CBNS 180 at 194)
and Laws LJ has referred to "abuse of power" as a root
concept governing judicial review (R v Department for Education
and Employment, ex p Begbie [2000] 1 WLR 1115, 1129F-G). Judicial
review was invented by the Courts, so as to ensure that the Executive
is not above the law. As Lord Templeman said (respectively, in
R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p Brind [1991]
1 AC 696 at 751B and Mercury Energy Ltd v Electricity Corporation
of New Zealand Ltd [1994] 1 WLR 521, 526A):
judicial review [is] a remedy invented by the
judges to restrain the excess or abuse of power.
Judicial review was a judicial invention to secure
that decisions are made by the executive or by a public body according
to law . . .
Judicial review therefore has a constitutional
role (see R v Ministry of Defence, ex p Smith [1996] QB 517 at
556D-E per Sir Thomas Bingham MR):
[The court] has the constitutional role and duty
of ensuring that the rights of citizens are not abused by the
unlawful exercise of executive power.
So, there is a clear and strong link between
judicial review and the rule of law. Lord Hoffmann described the
position in this way in R (on the application of Alconbury Developments
Ltd) v Secretary of State for the Environment Transport and the
Regions [2001] UKHL 23 [2001] 2 WLR 1389 at [73]:
The principles of judicial review give effect
to the rule of law. They ensure that administrative decisions
will be taken rationally, in accordance with a fair procedure
and within the powers conferred by Parliament.
And as Lord Griffiths memorably pointed out
in R v Horseferry Road Magistrates' Court, ex p Bennett [1994]
1 AC 42 at 62A-B:
the judiciary accept a responsibility for the
maintenance of the rule of law that embraces a willingness to
oversee executive action and to refuse to countenance behaviour
that threatens either basic human rights or the rule of law.
In the words of Simon Brown J (R v HM the Queen
in Council, ex p Vijayatunga [1988] QB 322, 343E-F):
Judicial review is the exercise of the court's
inherent power at common law to determine whether action is lawful
or not; in a word to uphold the rule of law.
Judicial review protects and applies the rule
of law. For Parliament to purport to exclude judicial review therefore
strikes at a constitutional right (access to law), but furthermore
at a constitutional protection (judicial review) supported by
a constitutional imperative (the rule of law).
11. The fifth feature is that the logic
of "constitutional" legality can be seen as calling
the Court to recognise the potential, in a sufficiently extreme
case, to scrutinise the constitutional propriety of even a source
of primary legislation. The conventional approach is for the Courts
to recognise and uphold the constitutional propriety of primary
legislation by reference to the constitutional principle of legislative
supremacy. But even that approach is compatible with the idea
that the Court is entitled to ask the question of constitutional
legality. It is part of the logic of legislating against a backcloth
of "higher authority", that such legislation be measured
against that higher authority. As Laws LJ has explained (R (on
the application of Bancoult) v Secretary of State for the Foreign
and Commonwealth Office [2001] QB 1067 at [46]):
a legislature created by a measure passed by
a body which is legally prior to it must act within the confines
of the power thereby conferred . . . [N]othing could be more elementary.
Written constitutions, of course, are enforced
by judges throughout the world by scrutinising the constitutional
legality of primary legislation. That includes the Privy Council,
sitting in London, hearing final appeals from jurisdictions having
a written Constitution. This is an area where comparative jurisprudence
can bring what Lord Goff's Child Lecture called an unparalleled
"enrichment of our legal culture" (see Markesinis in
The Clifford Chance Millennium Lectures: The Coming Together of
the Common Law and the Civil Law at p.66). There is no necessary
or inherent reason why protection under an "unwritten"
Constitution should be less real than protection under a written
Constitution. Neither involves overriding legislative supremacy,
nor the separation of powers, but rather recognising the proper
place of each within a Constitution based on the rule of law.
It should be remembered that, even in the case of a written Constitution,
the judicial role of scrutinising the constitutional legality
of primary legislation may not be contained within the constitutional
instrument itself. That was the position in the United States,
where the Supreme Court had to (and did) decide for itself that
the logic of constitutional legality meant that the Court should
assume the responsibility for ruling on the constitutionality
of primary legislation: see Marbury v Madison (1803) 5 US 137,
176-178. Thus, there is an answer here to the principle that the
Court cannot question the wisdom or expediency of primary legislation
(Duport Steels, above). The answer is that the Court would be
questioning only constitutionality. This is an important step
on from Lord Hoffmann's approach in Simms. That involved what
Lord Hoffmann called the application of "principles of constitutionality
little different from those which exist in countries where the
power of the legislature is expressly limited by a constitutional
document". This would involve applying "the same"
principles of constitutionality.
12. The sixth feature is the existence of
judicial building blocks. Strong and previously unquestioned may
be the conventional approach to legislative supremacy and Parliament's
untrammelled right to enact any provision by plain words. But
there are strands in the case-law which should not be overlooked,
in weaving the argument on this historic issue. As I have illustrated,
there is support in the domestic case-law for features mentioned
above: the rule of law, constitutional rights and the principle
of legality, the constitutional function of judicial review. There
are also particular areas which could profitably be revisited.
13. One such case is Anisminic, already
recognised as introducing judicial review for error of law, but
able to be revisited on the question of statutory ouster. It can
powerfully be said that, in truth and on reflection, the statutory
provision in that case was a plain and unqualified ouster extending
to judicial review. The result, however, would be the same on
a modern constitutional approach because the so-called "presumption"
that Parliament "cannot be taken" to have ousted judicial
review is in truth not so much a presumption as a "principle
of legality", underpinned by the rule of law. It is a recognised
step for what starts life as a "presumption" to become
viewed as a constitutional principle of legality, as Lord Steyn
has pointed out (B (A Minor) v Director of Public Prosecutions
[2000] 2 WLR 452 at 464D, endorsing the analysis by Sir Rupert
Cross):
such presumptions "not only supplement the
text, they also operate at a higher level as expressions of fundamental
principles governing both civil liberties and the relations between
Parliament, the executive and the courts. They operate as constitutional
principles which are not easily displaced by a statutory text".
The question becomes whether the constitutional
principle is capable, in some contexts, of being displaced by
a statutory text.
14. Alongside Anisminic, a similar explanation
can be given to the case-law by which Courts have declined to
apply the statutory restriction found in s.29(3) of the Supreme
Court Act 1981, which on its face would prevent judicial review
of matters relating to trial on indictment, but which the Courts
have declined to apply to cases of jurisdictional error/nullity:
see R v Maidstone Crown Court, ex p Harrow London Borough Council
[2000] QB 719; R v Leicester Crown Court, ex p Commissioners for
Customs and Excise [2001] EWHC Admin 33 at [22]; R (on the application
of Kenneally) v Snaresbrook Crown Court [2001] EWHC Admin 968
[2002] QB 1169 at [38]-[40]. Even legal history can assist, for
it is possible to trace back an ancient tradition recognising
that even an Act of Parliament could be questioned in the Courts
were it to run counter to "higher authority". There
are echoes here of the notion that inherent in the concept of
"law" is compatibility with constitutional rights or
fundamental constitutional norms: cf. Chuan v Public Prosecutor
[1981] AC 648, 670G ("law" meaning "a system of
law which incorporates those fundamental rules of natural justice").
Certainly, the Courts are aware that there is an open question.
As the Court of Appeal said in R (on the application of Southall)
v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs [2003]
EWCA Civ 1002 14th July 2003 unrep. at [11]:
we say nothing, because we need say nothing,
about what has been much discussed in the legal literature, namely,
whether the courts could in some circumstances refuse to enforce
an Act of Parliament which said that all babies under two years
of age should be slaughtered. That is not this case.
15. The seventh feature is, as indicated
in Southall, academic commentary. Alongside comparative case-law,
it is not difficult to find commentary which could assist. For
example, as Professor Geoffrey Wilson put it in The Courts, Law
and Convention in The Making and Remaking of the British Constitution
(1997) at p.116:
Nobody should be surprised if in a real case
of legislative enormity the courts did not discover a higher principle
of law by which they felt free or even obliged to ignore the current
version of the doctrine [of Parliamentary sovereignty] not only
in the name of constitutional convention but also in the name
of law.
The point cannot surely have been better expressed
than in Lord Woolf's 1994 F.A.Mann lecture (published in [1995]
PL 57, 68-69):
My approach . . . involves a proper recognition
of both the pillars of the rule of law and the equal responsibility
that Parliament and the courts are under to respect the other's
burdens and to play their proper role in upholding the rule of
law. I see the courts and Parliament as being partners both engaged
in a common enterprise involving the upholding of the rule of
law . . .
There are however situations where already, in upholding
the rule of law, the courts have had to take a stand. The example
which springs to mind is the Anisminic case. In that case even
the statement in an Act of Parliament that the Commission's decision
"shall not be called in question in any court of law"
did not succeed in excluding the jurisdiction of the court. Since
that case Parliament has not again mounted such a challenge to
the reviewing power of the High Court. There has been, and I am
confident that there will continue to be, mutual respect for each
other's roles.
However, if Parliament did the unthinkable, then
I would say that the courts would also be required to act in a
manner which would be without precedent. Some judges might choose
to do so by saying that it was an unrebuttable presumption that
Parliament could never intend such a result. I myself would consider
there were advantages in making it clear that ultimately there
are even limits on the supremacy of Parliament which it is the
courts' inalienable responsibility to identify and uphold. They
are limits of the most modest dimensions which I believe any democrat
would accept. They are no more than are necessary to enable the
rule of law to be preserved.
16. The eighth and final feature is the
concept of "dual sovereignty". The modern view of the
constitution is not that Parliament has sole supreme power, but
that it and the Courts each has constitutional sovereignty, based
on a separation of powers involving mutual respect each for the
other. The idea of dual sovereignty can be seen reflected in Lord
Bridge's observation in X Ltd v Morgan-Gampian Ltd [1991] 1 AC
1 at 48E that:
The maintenance of the rule of law is in every
way as important in a free society as the democratic franchise.
In our society the rule of law rests upon twin foundations: the
sovereignty of the Queen in Parliament in making the law and the
sovereignty of the Queen's courts in interpreting and applying
the law.
As Sedley J put it in In re F (Adult: Court's
Jurisdiction) [2001] Fam 38 at 56D, the relationship between Parliament
and the courts is:
a working relationship between two constitutional
sovereignties
Sir John Donaldson MR put it in this way (R
v HM Treasury, ex p Smedley [1985] QB 657, 666C-D):
Although the United Kingdom has no written constitution,
it is a constitutional convention of the highest importance that
the legislature and the judicature are separate and independent
of one another, subject to certain ultimate rights of Parliament
over the judicature which are immaterial for present purposes.
It therefore behoves the courts to be ever sensitive to the paramount
need to refrain from trespassing upon the province of Parliament
or, so far as this can be avoided, even appearing to do so.
He continued:
. . . I would hope and expect that Parliament
would be similarly sensitive to the need to refrain from trespassing
upon the province of the courts.
A statutory ouster of judicial review would
trespass on the duality, separation and mutual respect. It would
raise a constitutional conundrum which ultimately the Courts themselves
would have to resolve. One way of putting it is as follows. It
would certainly be said that the constitutional function of the
Court is to judicially review the legality of administrative action,
not to review and disapply a provision of primary legislation.
But to that powerful submission there is an extremely powerful
response: in reviewing and disapplying a statutory ouster of judicial
review, the Court is not extending and stepping outside its constitutional
function of reviewing administrative action, but rather it is
acting precisely to preserve and therefore discharge that constitutional
function. Put another way, it would have been Parliament, and
not the Courts, which would have failed to respect the dual sovereignty
and mutual respect between legislature and judiciary, and the
Court would be doing no more than restoring the proper division
of labour reflected in the separation of powers on which "the
British constitution, though largely unwritten, is firmly based"
(Duport Steels Ltd v Sirs [1980] 1 WLR 142, 157B-C (Lord Diplock)).
17. Putting these features together, a cogent
case for impugning the constitutional legality of a statutory
ouster of judicial review can be made. Such a legislative choice
would place Parliament and the Courts on a collision course. It
would be an historic legislative step raising a constitutional
law issue of huge significance, and which could lead to a historic
judicial response. Certainly, it would seem highly dangerous for
Government to assume that conventional approach to legislative
supremacy would provide the answer. Such a case would require
a fresh look and would ultimately need to be answered by reference
to fundamental constitutional considerations. Speaking for myself,
as with the writings of Professor Wilson and Lord Woolf, I would
not be at all surprised if the House of Lords, in the exceptional
circumstances of an ouster of judicial review, recognised it as
the role and responsibility of the Court to strike down such an
enactment as unconstitutional. To do so would be to re-establish
the required mutual respect in a situation of dual sovereignty,
by preserving the function of judicial review of administrative
action, and so ensure the upholding of the rule of law. There
is indeed a viable and cogent argument, supportable by powerful
strands of authority, whose acceptance would see the Court recognising
its responsibility to take that important step.
Michael Fordham
Blackstone Chambers
8 January 2004
199 Hansard Col 242 Back
200
Overturned by the Court of Appeal in Zenovics v SSHD [2002] EWCA
Civ 273 Back
201
Criticised by the Court of Appeal in R (on the application of
Razgar) v SSHD [2003] EWCA Civ 840 Back
202
Described as a difficult decision and alternative authorities
were preferred by the Court of Appeal in Edore v SSHD [2003] INLR
361 Back
203
Para 103 Back
204
Get it Right: How Home Office Decision-making Fails Refugees,
Amnesty International 9 February 2004 Back
205
Hansard Col 241 Back
|