Select Committee on Constitutional Affairs Written Evidence


Written evidence submitted by Lord Norton of Louth

THE PROPOSAL FOR A SUPREME COURT

Our present system of government should be seen in a positive light and not a negative one. It rests on the different components fulfilling their respective—and separate—roles but doing so on the basis of mutual respect and understanding for one another.[1] The judicial branch is separate in terms of functions—and exercising independence of judgement—to that of government. The fact that the highest domestic court of appeal resides in the Palace of Westminster does not undermine the independence of judgement or the integrity of the judicial branch but it does facilitate respect and understanding between the judiciary and Parliament. It facilitates co-operation between the judiciary and the executive branch, not in terms of conduct and judicial decision making, but in terms of facilitating the administration of the courts and the judicial system.[2]

That mutual respect and understanding is arguably all the more important at a time when there is greater judicial activism and with the constitution acquiring a new judicial dimension as a consequence of membership of the European Community/Union, the passage of the Human Rights Act 1998, and the devolution of powers to elected bodies in different parts of the United Kingdom. The need is exacerbated by clashes between successive Home Secretaries and the Courts. There is a problem at the moment in the relationship between ministers and the courts—the mutual respect and understanding is under challenge. That problem is likely to be all the greater if the Law Lords are removed from the House of Lords and established in a distinct—physically separate—building. Increasingly, as new appointments to the Court were made—and those members with previous service in the House of Lords disappear—the greater the lack of understanding on the part of judges as to the nature of the parliamentary process. Equally, and perhaps more importantly, the more exposed they would be, detached from a body that would be in a position to help protect them when under pressure from the executive. Paradoxically, therefore one has the potential for a physical independence of the highest court to undermine the capacity of that court to remain independent in the face of challenge from a powerful executive. The presence of lawyers in the House of Lords may be helpful to the House in understanding the law. The presence of the Law Lords is significant in terms of appreciating the role—and the need to protect the integrity—of the courts. Thus, it is arguable that the independence of the courts—maintaining their integrity in the face of executive challenge—is best protected by leaving the Law Lords in the Palace of Westminster rather than removing them from it.

There is thus a case for leaving the Law Lords where they are. What are the arguments for removing them, and creating a new Supreme Court? The core arguments appear to be those of (a) maintaining independence and (b) being seen to be independent. The first argument—that the highest court needs to be independent—is undermined by the recognition on the part of Government that the present system has served us well and that the Law Lords have demonstrated independence of judgement. The second argument is undermined by the absence of any hard evidence to demonstrate that the House of Lords in its judicial capacity is not seen as independent.

Constitutional Affairs minister, Lord Filkin, has said he does not believe that "because Law Lords have always acted with integrity and independence that reform should not take place."[3]

He bases his claim for change on Article 6 of the European Convention on Human Rights, various case law (as in Findlay v United Kingdom and Locabail (UK) Ltd v Bayfield Properties Ltd and others) and on the assertion that "the general public do not perceive that the Law Lords acted differently from the other Lords". And perception, he argues, matters as much as reality.[4]

There are a number of points to be made in response.

First, even if there was a misperception on the part of the public, that does not necessarily affect the delivery of a sound and effective system of justice or lead citizens to believe that there is a problem in such delivery. Lord Filkin appears to equate confusion (as to the role of the House of Lords) with doubt (as to impartiality). The fact that people may not grasp the distinction between the House of Lords in its legislative capacity and the House in its judicial capacity does not necessarily raise a doubt as to the capacity, or the perceived capacity, of the Law Lords to remain unbiased.

Second, the Government's claims as to the public perceptions themselves rest on presumptions: we are offered the Government's perception of perception. There are no hard data presented for its claims as to the public confusion and certainly none to sustain the claim of any perception of bias. Given the weight resting on the Government's claims, it is difficult to see how the Government can proceed with its proposals without putting some evidence for its assertion in the public domain. No empirical support can be found in the Consultation Document, Constitutional reform: A Supreme Court for the United Kingdom (CP 11/03, July 2003). See, for example, paragraph 3 on page 11 for the nature of unsubstantiated assertions as to perceptions: "The fact that the Lord Chancellor, as the Head of the Judiciary, was entitled to site in the Appellate and Judicial Committees and did so as Chairman, added to the perception that their independence might be compromised by the arrangements". Whose perception? It may have added to someone's perception, but we are offered no evidence for the claim.

Third, it is not clear why the existing arrangements do not meet the criteria enunciated in recent case law. In Findlay. the Court held that any element of doubt as to the impartiality of any tribunal must be eradicated, otherwise there may be the possibility of perceived bias. The Court said "In order to establish whether a tribunal can be considered `independent', regard must be had inter alia to the manner of appointment of its members and their term of office, the existence of guarantees against outside pressures and the question of whether the body presents an appearance of independence". It went on to say that there were two aspects to the question of impartiality: the tribunal must be subjectively free of personal prejudice or bias, and it must also be impartial from an objective viewpoint, that is, it must offer sufficient guarantees to exclude any legitimate doubt. In Locabail, the Court of Appeal held that when a judge has to consider whether to exclude himself from sitting, apparent bias was as important as real bias. It held that "The most effective protection of the right is in practice afforded by a rule which provides for the disqualification of a judge, and the setting aside of a decision, if on examination of all the relevant circumstances the court concludes that there was a real danger (or possibility) of bias".

These extracts are supplied, in correspondence, by Lord Filkin.[5] He also cites the words of Sir William McPherson in his Report of the Inquiry into the death of Stephen Lawrence: "Just as justice needs to be `seen to be done', so fairness must be `seen to be demonstrated'". Lord Filkin concluded: "If an institution is not perceived to be independent, impartial and fair, then trust in that institution will falter no matter what internal procedures are put in place to ensure that it is impartial and independent."[6]

I quote from my response to Lord Filkin:

        As for the "independence" of the Law Lords, I cannot see in what respect they do not fulfill the criteria detailed in Findlay v United Kingdom. Any doubt would arguably have been eradicated by the decision of the Law Lords conveyed in the House in June 2000 by Lord Bingham. Sir William MacPherson was obviously right to state that "just as justice needs to be `seen to be done', so fairness must be `seen to be demonstrated'." His statement can only be adduced in support of your case if you can show that the House of Lords is neither seen to dispense justice nor seen to demonstrate fairness. It would be interesting to know on what basis you are claiming that the Law Lords are not seen to demonstrate fairness. I also revert to my previous letter in asking what is the evidence for claiming that the Law Lords are not perceived to be "independent, impartial and fair"? Judicial assertions that they must be seen to be independent, impartial and fair is not evidence that the House of Lords is not perceived in those terms.

        The assertion that the Law Lords need to limit their participation in debates in the House in order to avoid perceptions of bias is hardly a basis for saying that it will be increasingly hard to meet the tests set out in Findlay. What is the evidence for saying it will be increasingly hard? And what is the evidence that the "general public" do not make a distinction between the Law Lords as judges and the Law Lords as members of the legislature? You say that the Government's approach is one of principle. To proceed, you need to demonstrate that the principle is not being met by the existing arrangements. A plurality of Law Lords clearly believes that current arrangements do meet the principle.

One might add that, if there was a perception that the Law Lords were not independent, impartial and fair then—on Lord Filkin's own argument—trust in the House of Lords as the highest court would have faltered by now. The logic of the Government's case rests on such trust faltering—not in the future, but now. Lord Filkin believes there is a problem of trust faltering in the future but rests his claim on existing—not future—public perceptions. That position is simply not tenable.

In my most recent (and so far unanswered) letter to Lord Filkin, I conclude:

        In short, where is the evidence? Recounting what is said by jurists, be it in reports or judicial proceedings, serves merely to reinforce a principle that is not in dispute. As I said in my letter, the Government's consultation paper embodies no hard evidence. Neither, I fear, does your letter. I venture to suggest that you need not only to produce evidence but to be seen to do so.

There is a persuasive case to be made for existing arrangements. The case for doing away with those arrangements is based largely on supposition. Furthermore, part of the Government's proposals for change may themselves fall foul of the very case law they cite in their support. In Findlay, it was held that in determining "independence", regard had to be had, inter alia, to "the manner of appointment" of members. Are the Government's proposals for the appointment of judges (Constitutional reform: a new way of appointing judges, CP 10/03, July 2003, p 9) demonstrably Findlay-proof? There would appear to be doubt on the part of judges as to whether they are.

In short, what we are presently presented with is no basis for undertaking significant constitutional change. The onus is on those advocating change to make their case and they have not done so.

Lord Norton of Louth

26 November 2003



1   See P Norton, "Governing Alone", Parliamentary Affairs, September 2003 Back

2   The importance of co-operation was stressed in a debate in the House of Lords earlier this year by both the Lord Chief Justice, Lord Woolf, and Law Lord, Lord Hope of Craighead Back

3   Lord Filkin to Lord Norton of Louth, 26 September 2003 Back

4   Ibid Back

5   Lord Filkin to Lord Norton of Louth, 27 October 2003 Back

6   Ibid Back


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2004
Prepared 10 February 2004