Select Committee on Environmental Audit Written Evidence


APPENDIX 18

Memorandum by Professor David Pearce OBE, Professor of Environmental Economics, University College London, and Visiting Professor, Imperial College London

  Historical note: Professor Pearce was Special Advisor to the Secretary of State for the Environment 1989-92. He was the main author of the UK Government's response to the Brundtland Commission's 1987 report Our Common Future (Pearce et al 1989), and was one of the contributor's to the UK's first White Paper on environmental policy—This Common Inheritance released in 1990. He has written extensively on the economics of sustainable development

THE DEFINITION OF SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT

  A common confusion relates to the definition of sustainable development and the conditions necessary to achieve it. Sustainable development is simply development that lasts. How far into the future one should look is open to debate: most would probably agree that thinking 50 years hence is very sensible, and perhaps 100 years too. Thinking ahead 1,000 years or more hardly seems consistent with human preferences (our "coefficient of concern" declines with time) or the reliability of information, but see below. "Development" is a value word: it means whatever people want it to mean. But most people would accept that rising material standards of living (real GNP per capita) are important, as is good health, education, environmental quality and human freedoms. An almost endless list of indicators exists for measuring "development"—a virtual industry in producing them has emerged. But it can be argued that what has to be done to achieve sustainable development is largely invariant with the definition. If so, debating definitions is interesting but not particularly helpful. Nonetheless, it is clear that some people advocate, or imply, definitions of sustainable development that would require radically different actions—the issue is discussed shortly.

THE CONDITIONS FOR ACHIEVING SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT

  The economics literature on sustainable development is much further advanced than the literature from other disciplines. That literature emphasises the role of capital assets as the means for "producing" development, ie capital assets define our capabilities for development. Of course, any generation can fail to achieve this potential by mismanaging those assets, and there is plenty of evidence that many countries have done this. It is vital to understand what is meant by "capital assets". They comprise the conventional meaning—manufactured assets such as infrastructure and machinery (the old-fashioned definition of capital); the stock of skills and knowledge—human capital as it is now called; the stock of environmental assets and natural resources (oil, coal, water, water quality, the global atmosphere etc); and the set of trusting social relationships between people and between people and institutions—so-called "social capital". Human freedoms are usually regarded as part of social capital. There is an extensive literature in development economics showing how human wellbeing varies with the endowment of these assets. Technological change permits any of these assets, or all of them, to be more "productive"—just as we know workers are more productive the more manufactured capital they have, so we know that technological change has raised the productivity of natural resources, and so on. Whilst debated by some, population growth tends to dissipate capital resources—spreading them out over more and more people, and thus lowering the per capita endowment of those resources. Research shows that surprisingly low rates of population growth (around 1% per annum) are sufficient to place sustainable development at very serious risk. Political correctness has tended to downplay these findings, but nothing is gained by pretending that the chances of sustainable development are unaffected by population growth.

  Achieving sustainable development thus requires that we increase the endowment of the overall stock of assets per head of the population through time. At the very least, that per capita stock should not decline unless we are satisfied that the positive effects of technological change are outstripping the negative effects of population change.

THE BRUNDTLAND COMMISSION

  While sustainable development was discussed well before the Brundtland Commission's report of 1987, that Commission placed the concept "on the map". There are two features of that Report worth noticing. First, the Commission was as concerned, if not more so, about distribution of wellbeing across people now, as they were about distribution through time. Curiously, most of the subsequent literature has focused on the inter-temporal distribution, perhaps because the problems of poverty are well known, and the problems facing "future generations" are, for some reason, more attractive to debate. The phrase "sustainable development" obviously contributes to this asymmetry of treatment. But the challenges of dealing with distribution of wellbeing now are arguably greater than the challenges facing future generations, and this presents a problem for policies purporting to be in keeping with "sustainability". Resources devoted to avoiding or ameliorating future problems could well be at the expense of resources that could alleviate poverty problems now. The added puzzle is that future generations have a higher probability of being richer than the current poor than being poorer. If there is a trade-off—see below—it seems odd to allocate resources to the potentially richer than the actually poorer.

  Brundtland never resolved this issue because, excellent though it is in many ways, it was a political report that contained a message that any politician finds attractive: there are no trade-offs—we can have everything. This illusory message has fostered much of the subsequent "popular" literature on sustainable development. This literature argues that we can have economic growth, environmental quality, social justice for the poor now, limited life risks for future generations, and so on. The kind of picture thinking that results is typified by the endless triangle and other diagrams showing the "three pillars" of sustainable development: social, economic and environmental. That simply is not true, and it seems that only economists have faced the reality that there are, and always will be, trade-offs.

  At the domestic level even casual empiricism testifies to the trade-offs. The UK government's policies on housing and airport expansion alone are not consistent with maintaining environmental assets in their current form. Overall land-take and fragmentation of habitats means that biodiversity must decline. It is true that one can think of other policies—eg, the Water Framework Directive—which might actually increase biodiversity through improved water quality. But whether one environmental asset substitutes for another raises interesting issues of trade-offs within the "environmental account".

SUSTAINABLE CONSUMPTION

  Like "sustainable development", sustainable consumption is a much abused term. But it is possible to give it rigorous meaning. The simplest way is to think in terms of the following two arguments. First, we are used to the idea that income is made up of what we consume (consumption) and what we save (saving). This holds true regardless of the agent (household, government, company) doing the consuming and saving. Second, no agent is economically viable (sustainable) if he or she fails to put aside resources each year to cover the depreciation on assets. Restated, the rule for sustainability is that savings (what we put aside) must cover depreciation on all assets. But we know that assets consist for the four types of capital outlined above. So, the rule for a nation (it is more complex for a sector or even a corporation) is that the nation must save more than the depreciation on man-made assets, on the environment and on social trust. Human capital is probably in a "special" situation because although we lose wisdom and knowledge when (some) people die, "thers tend to replace them, and the stock of knowledge expands. National accountants are used to calculating depreciation on man-made assets ("capital consumption" in the accounts) and are increasingly understanding that they also have to calculate resource depreciation (extraction and use of resources which are not replenished) and environmental depreciation (pollution damage). Others (rightly in my view) also worry about "social depreciation" which shows up in increased lawlessness, social breakdown, disrespect and unruly behaviour.

  All this suggests that one can define a concept of "genuine savings" which is simply the difference between savings and asset depreciation. If savings exceed overall depreciation, "genuine" savings is positive. What this reduces to is a simple requirement—we can consume as much as we like so long as the capital base of the economy (the stock of assets) does not decline. Put another way, (maximum) sustainable consumption is that level of consumption consistent with genuine savings being zero.

  This is the essence of the economic analysis of sustainable consumption. It gets more complex once we allow for population change and technological change, but the basics are as set out above. It may be worth noting that, while the argumentation may look slightly complicated, it is all consistent with old fashioned views that one should not "sell the family silver". It does have considerable implications for policy, however. If one runs down North Sea oil and gas, it is necessary to use the proceeds (the "rents") to build up other capital assets. Many countries, including the UK in the past, have failed to do this—they "consume" the proceeds and because of the way national accounts are calculated, this fosters the illusion that they are growing "sustainably". Proper construction of capital accounts would show that they are not necessarily sustainable. Work at the World Bank, using these notions, has shown, for example, that under reasonable assumptions even an economy as large and powerful as the USA can fail a sustainability test.

  One could make this sustainability test stricter. Some people believe that environmental assets are so "special" that, not only should we insist on the overall stock of assets growing, we should add a further requirement that environmental assets should not decline. This is sometimes called "strong sustainability". It contrasts with the notion of sustainability introduced above because it would not allow a decline in environmental assets to be offset by an increase in other assets. Thus, extracting North Sea oil cannot be compensated for by building more universities, say. The loss of oil assets must be compensated by some other environmental asset—perhaps more renewable energy. This notion has many problems and space forbids a discussion here, but it is easy to see why it is attractive. We know far less about what environmental destruction will do to future wellbeing than we know about man-made assets. We can also build and "unbuild" roads and houses: we can't recreate many environmental assets when they have gone.

  Changing the notion of sustainable consumption to allow for this view is quite easy. What happens is that the added constraint—keeping environmental capital constant (whatever that means)—means that some resources must be devoted to honouring that constraint when they might have yielded a higher social return by being invested in, say, education or health. There is an "opportunity cost" of the constraint on using natural resources and this will lower the maximum sustainable consumption level. Simply put, in a world where strong sustainability ruled, there would still be a sustainable consumption level but it would be less (per capita) than in the world where all assets are substitutable for each other. (It is important to avoid another confusion which pervades the literature: no-one is suggesting one can substitute for all natural resources. The issue is substitution "at the margin". Moreover, substitution is never one-way: it could be the case that it is better to invest in natural resources than more universities. It is an empirical matter, not one of faith or dogma).

OTHER NOTIONS OF SUSTAINABLE CONSUMPTION

  Both the above notions of sustainable consumption have rigorous content. The same cannot be said for other notions which are, nonetheless, quite popular. Confusion is again generated by a failure to define terms properly: consumption is income not saved. Call this final consumption. The consumption of materials and energy is an input to this concept of consumption. It makes a lot of difference if one is arguing about the former or the latter, or both.

  The first alternative notion has no real definition of what is and what is not "sustainable" consumption. Instead, it simply requires that consumption levels be reduced. There are two meanings to this.

  One is (presumably) totally uncontroversial. It requires that we consume less materials and energy per unit of final consumption. This is resource efficiency or resource productivity, and the UK government has a modest programme of work on this notion. We know that, in terms of technological potential, resource productivity gains could be enormous (the so-called "factor Four" argument). The debate then shifts to the costs and benefits of securing this potential and the means of achieving it (market-based environmental policies seemingly being particularly effective in this context).

  The second meaning of "reduced consumption" is that final consumption is reduced. We simply "consume less" by spending less money on consumer goods. One reason for doing this is that someone may think it is "wrong" to spend money on "frivolous" goods or even goods they consider to be harmful. Such a view, quite widespread among the more "evangelical" of environmentalists, raises all kinds of issues about who decides, and whether overriding human preferences is itself consistent with any sensible notion of sustainable development. My own view, for the record, is that such an approach to sustainable development is both undemocratic and self-defeating (which does not mean that the viewpoint should not be aired!).

  Another reason for reducing final consumption, relevant to sustainable consumption, is that if we reduce consumption we will also reduce the use of energy and materials. This second argument might have some merit if the ratio of energy and materials used to consumption is fixed in some way. The resource productivity argument tells us that these ratios are not at all fixed. Initially, it seems perverse to argue for reduced consumption on environmental grounds if we can secure the same end by resource productivity without interfering with what people want.

  The reality is that this alternative view of "sustainable consumption" is a weakly disguised version of the 1970s anti-growth literature. Some of its advocates are honest enough to say so, some are not. As noted, it has major, and I would say, insuperable problems. It does not appear to be consistent with what people want, it could not be usefully implemented on a unilateral basis, it would harm those supplying us with goods and services (including poor countries) and it would raise a myriad social problems. But suppose all these were regarded as an acceptable trade-off for the environmental returns. How would one implement an anti-growth (anti high consumption) policy? One could tax consumption and subsidies savings. But savings are simply tomorrow's consumption so nothing is achieved by this. One could have campaigns telling people they should not consume this or that. One could reduce expenditure on education and health and on technological change, because these are the things we believe generate higher consumption possibilities. A moment's reflection shows that "sustainable consumption" on this approach is not a feasible goal.

  There is a sustainable consumption literature that shows how many resources are used by the "rich" compared to the "poor" and this is used to argue that the rich should be less rich and the poor less poor. But several muddles are involved in this argument. The aim of development is, in part, to make people "rich", so it seems illogical to complain that the policy should not be successful. It also tends to imply that if we take $1 away from, say, an American citizen, this $1 will magically reappear as $1 for a poor person. It will only do this if the $1 actually materialises and is then taxed away and given to the poor. But this sustainable consumption literature says that the $1 should not have been generated in the first place. If so, it simply never appears for rich or poor: it is, to paraphrase Monty Python's parrot sketch, a "non-dollar". If what this "iterature is complaining about is the high volume of materials and energy used per person in rich countries (interestingly, not per dollar, because resource efficiency tends to be higher in rich countries than in poor countries) then we can have sympathy. But this is an argument about resource productivity, not reducing consumption.

  Finally, there is a notion of sustainable consumption which argues that we should consume less because that will reduce environment pollution and resource use and hence what resources we have will last longer and we can hence have more future generations than we otherwise would have done. The idea here is to maximise human survival time on Earth. It has a kind of evolutionary arrogance about it as a goal, but no doubt some people would find another, perhaps religious, rationale for it. But if maximising survival term did make any sense, its implications are formidable. The easiest way to bring it about would be to lower the consumption level of every generation (except the last one ever to exist!) to subsistence levels. This hardly has any appeal to any generation, save the last one to exist.

CONCLUSIONS

    —  Clarity in arguing about sustainable development can be aided by differentiating definitions of sustainable development from conditions for sustainable development.

    —  The definition involves defining a value word—"development"—but this definition may not matter if the conditions for achieving whatever the goal is, are similar.

    —  While most of the discussion about sustainable development is about inter-temporal development, the Brundtland Commission was clear in giving priority to development for the poor now.

    —  Allocating resource to inter-temporal concerns involves using resources that could be used to help the poor now. The result could be perverse, with resources being allocated to people in the future who will probably be richer than the poor now.

    —  The correct context for policy is one of trade-offs. The popular literature, aided by the Brundtland Report, has given the impression that sustainable development is about having everything at the same time. This is an illusion.

    —  Actual policy proceeds with trade-offs that are often ill-informed. Housing and other land use policy in the UK might be an example. It is certainly not an example of "development" that protects environmental assets.

    —  "Sustainable consumption" can be defined rigorously, although this is not how it is treated in the major part of the popular literature.

    —  The first rigorous notion defines sustainable consumption as that level of consumption that is consistent with not running the nation's overall capital assets down. This is equivalent to saying that "genuine savings" must not be negative.

    —  The second rigorous notion of sustainable consumption is that level of consumption consistent with maintaining all capital assets, and, maintaining environmental assets at their existing level as well. If investing in resource conservation has a lower rate of return than investing in, say, education, this definition implies a lower level of maximum sustainable consumption than the previous definition.

    —  Other notions of sustainable consumption are usually muddled or infeasible. One popular notion is simply that consumption levels should be reduced in order to save resources and the environment. If so, one would want to know why this cannot be better achieved by resource productivity than by reducing consumption. There are also problems in terms of thinking what the policies are that would reduce consumption. Most would be infeasible because they would be politically suicidal, but there are also questions about whether such policies could ever be implemented without sacrificing the means of development—education, health, and technological change—which are regarded as good in themselves.

    —  Much of the "sustainable consumption" literature is actually a rebirth and restatement of the 1970s anti-growth literature. The idea that the rich should be less rich and the poor less poor is muddled. Certainly the poor should be richer, but making the rich less rich is simply a gratuitous loss of wellbeing—it does not make the poor any less poor. But it is correct to insist that we do all we can to make the rich more resource productive per capita, just as they are already more resource productive per dollar or pound.

May 2004





 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2004
Prepared 8 November 2004