Select Committee on Environment, Food and Rural Affairs Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 780-799)

MR DAVID FURSDON, MR CHRISTOPHER PRICE, MR JOHN JACKSON AND MR GRAHAM DOWNING

13 OCTOBER 2004

  Q780 Paddy Tipping: I think you have got it wrong actually.

  Mr Price: No, the Director General of the RSPCA has said that she is opposed to game shooting.

  Q781 Paddy Tipping: I will accept that. Just sketch out for me—and perhaps Mr Jackson will help us with it—the kind of people that you would want to be inspectors. What is the ideal of inspector from your point of view?

  Mr Jackson: I think I would say two things. Firstly, they should plainly be people who are and can be seen to be knowledgeable. Secondly, and this is something we attach importance to, they should be publicly accountable. Public accountability is a very useful concept.

  Mr Fursdon: Can I say, coming back to the point I made, equally the drafting of the Bill is important, because the tighter that that is drafted the less opportunity there is going to be for everyone to fall out about it.

  Mr Downing: In order to clarify it, Christopher has raised the issue of game shooting and the RSPCA's attitude towards game shooting. We are entirely supportive of a proper inspection regime in relation to the Bill, but it must be a publicly accountable one and we would not, for example, have any difficulty if the State Veterinary Service were to inspect game farms. However, if an organisation which openly campaigned against game shooting were to be responsible for inspecting game farms, this could cause considerable difficulties for game farmers.

  Q782 Paddy Tipping: I am a bit rusty because we have not talked about this Bill for three weeks. Are you telling me that you would not want the RSPCA designated as inspectors? Is that a no, no, for both?

  Mr Price: I do not suppose that inspectors would be appointed on the basis of organisations; they would be appointed on the basis of individuals. We would have hoped the guidance would specify that someone who was active within a campaigning organisation would not be appointed. The point applies to both sides.

  Mr Jackson: Yes, in their interests as much as in everybody else's interest.

  Q783 Chairman: I would like to pursue with the Country Land and Business Association a point which occurs in paragraph one of your evidence under "cruelty", because you have welcomed the Bill in unequivocal terms and yet the second paragraph of paragraph one says, "We are concerned, though, at the proposal of extending the offence to acts and omissions which have not actually caused unnecessary suffering which are likely to do so." One of the merits of this measure as proposed is to use information in an anticipatory sense, that if you went on to a holding where, if you like, to my layman's eyes I could see things were not absolutely as they ought to be, and you might think there could be a problem, and then if a professional went in and said, "If they carry on like this these animal are going to die. I think we have to do something", what you are saying is that the animals have got to die before anything happens?

  Mr Price: No, I am sorry, I am not saying that. There are two points.

  Q784 Chairman: It says you are concerned about it here. That is why I asked the question.

  Mr Price: Yes, but the point I was making is not about not being able to do anything until the animal dies, the point I was making was about not being able to do anything until the animal suffers. The basic test of cruelty, which you have had in English law since 1849 I think I am right in saying, is that of unnecessary suffering. It appears in every substantive piece of legislation that is concerned with cruelty. It now appears in Council of Europe legislation and in EU legislation. It is fine. Everyone knows what it means. One of the good things about this Bill is that some of the tests or references to proportionality and things elaborate on the case law that has been used to explain what "unnecessary suffering" means. That is all good; we welcome that. The only—

  Q785 Chairman: Can I stop you there. You do not think that the way the Bill is currently constructed rules out the continuing use of that body of case law?

  Mr Price: It will have to be interpreted. At the moment the way it works is that the courts will look at whether the animal has suffered, which is a clear enough thing to establish, you then look at whether what was being done was necessary, and necessary as a particular meaning in a sense, and you balance the two together. It is quite difficult, or can be quite difficult, to carry out that balancing exercise. There are problems with some of the case law because it is Victorian and relates to circumstances that do not apply now, but most people know what it means, and I imagine that the concept of "suffering" and the concept of "unnecessary" and the case law that explains "unnecessary suffering" will still apply under the present law. We now have the clearer use of proportionality, or explicit use of proportionality, so that people understand what we are talking about. But going back to your point about "likely to", the only point, the only animal welfare offence in which you get a "likely to" element is the element of the Abandonment of Animals Act 1960. To some extent I think it is reasonable for the courts to be able to ascertain whether, if an animal has been abandoned, it is likely to suffer—that is a fairly clear-cut thing—but if you are going to apply "likely to" to absolutely every aspect of cruelty, I think from a practical point, and it must be in the interests of justice to ensure that things are practical to enforce, it is going to be difficult working out at which point you are going beyond what might happen to what is likely to happen. The example I think I gave in the response was that of if you are riding a horse for the day. If you start off riding a horse, if you carry on for ever, you are likely to cause unnecessary suffering; if you just sat on it, you may cause unnecessary suffering. I find it very difficult to see at what point anyone can say you are going beyond "may" and become "likely". It seems too uncertain.

  Q786 Chairman: Sorry, Mr Fursdon, I wanted to ask Mr Price, how would you give certainty then?

  Mr Price: Just trying to finish off the point. If it is only likely to suffer or to be caused unnecessary suffering that means it is not yet suffering, so the animal is not in any harm as a result of not having a "likely to" test.

  Mr Fursdon: I just really wanted to clarify the fact that if suffering was taking place, and it is a question of degree, if it was already taking place, then we would not object to what is going on here; it is just the fact that you could presumably take somebody who everybody knew in the locality was a bit of a rogue and so you then say, "Right, well, because he is a bit of a rogue, I am going to take the animals away because he does not know how to look after them." In fact, that person could be looking after them perfectly okay. It is a question of where that "likely to" definition comes, and I think we are concerned that some people will be judged before they have even done anything, particularly if you lead it back to who is doing the judging and is there an agenda there. I think that is the point we are trying to make.

  Q787 Alan Simpson: Can I move on to the fines and punishment aspects of that in your submission. I think one of the points that particularly troubled me was your approach to the notion of fines and punishments. I almost find myself thinking: did you want the Committee to take seriously your suggestion that fines should be in line with the amount of profits that were likely to be made by the acts of cruelty? It seems a bizarre notion. We never say that about cruelty to kids: how much money would their parents make out of them? For you to suggest somehow the level of fines should be constrained by whether you were likely to be making a large profit or a small profit just seems ludicrous?

  Mr Price: I was saying take the thing the other way round. It seems to me if you are causing unnecessary suffering for a profit the penalty should be higher than if you are causing unnecessary suffering inadvertently. If you are a farmer who is a bad farmer who has not acted with any sort of malice or with any idea of benefiting themselves through their harm, it seems to me not unreasonable that the penalty you suffer should be less than someone who is running some animal torture show or something.

  Q788 Alan Simpson: I think that is what I am suggesting is ludicrous. It seems to me that you move from the notion of suffering. The idea that—

  Mr Price: No. You are still convicted of suffering. What I am saying is that you should be punished more if you are imposing suffering for profit.

  Q789 Alan Simpson: Why should the fine not just relate to the suffering? You would not do that in relation to children. Is not the issue quite simply whether people should be punished and whether there should be a fines regime for acts of cruelty?

  Mr Price: I do not know anything about child law, but I do know about environmental law, and for most environmental crimes the penalty is higher if you are acting for profit than if you are doing something inadvertently; and that was the parallel I was picking up on.

  Q790 Chairman: Just to follow Mr Simpson's line of questioning, that means that if somebody keeps an animal not for commercial purposes and, according to your line of logic, is cruel to that animal, they should not be hit as hard as if somebody is cruel but it so happens, coincidentally, that they are in business and they make a profit?

  Mr Price: No, not inadvertently. If what you are doing is, I suppose, celebrating cruelty for its own sake or providing cruelty as entertainment—I accept there is no right or wrong, it is a value judgment, but it just seems to me that if you are exploiting animals in this way for profit then you ought to penalised more for it than if you have just made a mistake. After all, you if you have just made a mistake you are still convicted, you are still fined.

  Q791 Joan Ruddock: I was trying to follow through what you were actually saying, and it did seem to me that the distinction is between doing something advertently and doing something deliberately. You are equating making profits with deliberate actions and I think there is a distinction between inadvertent action and deliberate action, which is separate from the amount of profit that you might make?

  Mr Price: I take your point. When I was talking about making a profit it was in the sense that you would . . . I am sorry, when I was talking about this making a profit it was on the basis you were doing . . . I think we are saying the same thing but you are saying it better than I did, but you are right.

  Q792 Joan Ruddock: I could be on your side by my own definition, but not on the one that you originally offered?

  Mr Price: Sorry, I should have been clearer. I was not thinking that anybody would do something deliberately cruel other than for profit, and that seems a reasonable basis on which to impose a heavier penalty, but I think the basic point is good.

  Q793 Joan Ruddock: You must accept and you must have known of cases where there would be no profit involved but there was deliberate cruelty. That is the important distinction that we would accept?

  Mr Price: I take your point.

  Chairman: Alan, do you want to follow this up?

  Q794 Alan Simpson: Yes, in a sense I would echo the point that Joan Ruddock has just made, but I would also go on and ask you whether, as a consequence of that, you follow it with the point you make about the deprivation of the animal, the ownership of the animal. I want to know: do you object to that as a penalty in principle? Because it seems to me that you describe it, your sentence is: "Being prohibited from keeping a dog in the absence of any welfare considerations is merely oppressive", but you are saying that fines and prison are an acceptable form of punishment?

  Mr Price: Yes.

  Q795 Alan Simpson: But that it should not be within the remit of the law to extend that and to remove your right to own or to be responsible for the animal?

  Mr Price: The purpose of this legislation is to promote animal welfare. If there are no welfare implications for the animal staying with its owner, then I cannot see any reason to deprive the owner of that animal, but you can penalise them under the fines/imprisonment point.

  Q796 Alan Simpson: There would be animal welfare implications if there were fines and imprisonment—I think that is the starting point—but what you seem to be saying is that that should be the finite limit?

  Mr Price: Yes.

  Q797 Alan Simpson: And we have had people giving us evidence that say, "What if you have patterns of neglect, what if you have patterns in which the solicitors who gave evidence to us from the local authority yesterday were saying, under the existing law, people simply transferred the ownership of animals to their girlfriends, to other family members, so you have a succession of abuses that take place? Really what you have to do is have the right to remove the animals from that person's stewardship?

  Mr Price: Yes, that is what . . . You can do that. You can remove the animal if there are welfare implications, but if the animal is not going to suffer any harm as a result of staying with the owner and the owner is also punished through fines or imprisonment, then I do not see what is unacceptable about the situation.

  Q798 Mr Wiggin: Can I just clarify this. So if somebody is running a puppy farm in an appalling manner and also keeps a horse, you take away the dogs but leave them with the horse. Is that what you are saying?

  Mr Price: No. What is being proposed in the Bill, as I understood it, was that, in addition to a fine and/or imprisonment, you can deprive the owner of the animal as a form of punishment, and I think the explanatory notes use the word "punishment". I am saying it is wrong, as a matter of principle, to deprive the owner of the animal when there are no welfare implications.

  Q799 Alan Simpson: I must be being obtuse. Could you perhaps give me a practical example of the circumstances in which you believe that someone would be fined and sent to prison but there were not animal welfare implications for the offence that they committed?

  Mr Price: I cannot, but that is a matter for the courts and not for us. If the court finds that there are no welfare implications involved in leaving the animal with its owner then I cannot see any reason why the court should deprive him of the owner. I agree, it is not a situation that is going to arise at all often, which is why we did not mention it as a prime concern at the outset.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2004
Prepared 9 December 2004