Select Committee on European Scrutiny Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 40-59)

PROFESSOR SIR DAVID EDWARD AND PROFESSOR EILEEN DENZA CMG

17 NOVEMBER 2004

Q40 Mr Cash: I am sure it is a very good example, but might it not also be dealt with by the harmonisation of criminal procedures which are now going through the treaty and directive system? Indeed, also I think the Nice Treaty made provision for the European Court to be able to prepare its own rules of procedure and it would seem to follow from that, that with the overarching jurisdiction of the European Court that would filter through in order to sort out discrepancies between the differing legal systems. I am completely against that, as you might imagine, but I am saying that I think the mechanisms for achieving these objectives certainly appear to be there.

  Professor Sir David Edward: The mechanisms certainly are there by which, if you are legislating, you could legislate in such a way as to overcome or displace the 110-day rule in Scottish procedure. That is certainly so. But my point is that what is important if you are legislating, is that you should be aware that there is a jurisdiction within the European Union which has this as a fundamental human right, that you cannot be held in prison for more than a certain period without being taken before a judge and tried. If legislation were put forward which ignored that—and it is quite possible that it would be—then it creates a serious problem for the administration of justice in Scotland. I gave evidence to a committee in France which was looking at the prosecution system in France, and I explained the 110-day rule, and they said, "You need not go any further. It would be totally impossible to operate that rule in France." It seems really surprising to people, but it would not seem surprising to the Scots if it were abolished.

  Chairman: Sir David, it would not be surprising to David Hamilton, the Member from Midlothian, if he were here, because I can remember David Hamilton being a victim of that same rule during the miners' strike.

Q41 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: Could I turn to the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights. When this was drawn up, it was of course not legally binding and we were assured as such by the Government. It is now, though, to be included in the Constitution itself and as such it will have primacy over the laws of Member States under Article 5 of the Constitution. However, certain safeguards have apparently been built in, in particular the explanations which purport to explain or limit the application of the charter are not to be in the Constitution itself but are appended to it. The courts are to have "due regard" to the explanations—and that phrase appears in the preamble to the Charter. What weight do you attach to those words "due regard"? What do they add to the fact that explanations exist anyway? Will they mandate the Court to pay particular attention or can they be ignored in certain cases?

  Professor Sir David Edward: It is the distinction between "have due regard to" and "shall be bound by" or "shall interpret in terms of the explanations." "Due regard" I think means first of all, you shall look at the explanations, and you shall look at them seriously but you are not bound by them if your interpretation of the principal text in a given situation leads you to a different conclusion.

Q42 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: As a limit on the expansion of the powers of the Court, you would therefore not put very much weight on those words. Would that be right?

  Professor Sir David Edward: In French it is "shall take duly into consideration" actually. It is perhaps even slightly weaker than in English. No, I do not say that you do not pay attention to it, but let me give you an example. Explanations distinguish at the end between rights and principles. They enumerate certain rights and say "These are rights" and then they say "There are also principles, for example . . . " but they do not say exhaustively which of the provisions of the Charter are rights and which are principles. Clearly the court would there pay due regard to the terms of the explanation in saying, "Well, this gives certain examples of principles, and this is like the ones they have identified as principles" but—

Q43 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: Is it clear to you which are the rights and which are the principles in the Charter as drafted?

  Professor Sir David Edward: It is not clear to me which are the principles. Indeed, the explanation tells us that in one case—and I cannot remember which—something is both a right and a principle.

Q44 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: That is a rather serious observation you have made because they are to be interpreted in different ways under Article II-52. They are treated quite differently in that article and yet you have just told me that the distinction is largely meaningless.

  Professor Sir David Edward: I do not say the distinction is meaningless because if you look at the explanation in relation to Article 52, it does enumerate which are the rights that come from the European Convention. The difficulty is that it does not make a clear distinction so as to identify those elements in the Charter which are to be regarded purely as principles and not to confer any rights at all.

Q45 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: So "Equality between men and women must be ensured in all areas" is that a right or a principle? That is Article 11-23.

  Professor Sir David Edward: If I remember rightly, that is one that is both. This is in the commentary on Article 52: "In some cases an article of the Charter may contain both elements of a right and of a principle; eg, Articles 23, 33 and 34." Article 33 is family and professional life and 34 is social security and social assistance.

Q46 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: So equality between men and women can be either a right or a principle depending on the circumstances. That does not seem to advance the case at all. This whole Constitution is supposed to bring clarity and finality and certainty to who does what and what our rights are. Everything you have said recently rather disappoints me. We are in a fog here about what our rights are and what our principles are.

  Professor Sir David Edward: I am not going to suggest that this is a simple document.

  Mr Heathcoat-Amory: No.

Q47 Mr Tynan: Obviously I am not a legal person. Article II-52(3) states that the rights in the Charter which correspond to European Convention rights are to be given the same scope and meaning as the latter.

  Professor Sir David Edward: Yes.

Q48 Mr Tynan: On the other hand, the Article adds that this requirement "shall not prevent Union law providing more extensive protection." How can a Charter right have both the same meaning and be more extensive than the same right under the EHCR?

  Professor Sir David Edward: It is slightly difficult for us to understand this because we have no charter of rights in a written constitution, but the German constitution contains rights and these in some respects go further than the provisions of the European Convention, so it is perfectly possible for a Member State to give greater protection. The point about the European Convention is that that is minimum protection. As I understand it, as I would interpret it, what this means is you are not to go below the level of protection provided by the European Convention but you may go beyond it.

Q49 Mr Tynan: What would be the position if the Union were to favour, say, Article 8 rights over those under Article 10? Would this favouring of the Article 8 rights have to be read down so as to comply with European Convention on Human Rights jurisprudence or would the ECJ say that this was a case providing more extensive protection?

  Professor Sir David Edward: Article 8 is not one which corresponds to a European Convention on Human Rights right. Article 8 is new, the protection of data—although there is a directive on protection of data. In fact the explanation explains it. Article 10 is based on the European Convention, so you could not go below the European Convention in Article 10 and you could not use 8 to go below it.

Q50 Chairman: I think, Sir David, Mr Tynan has asked the question about European Convention on Human Rights.

  Professor Sir David Edward: I am sorry.

  Professor Denza: You really have these conflicts within the European Convention. One of the analyses of the Charter recently published goes under the title "The European Constitution: Bringing Europe Close to its Lawyers."

  Mr Cash: I saw an interesting article referred to in the Civil Contingencies Bill which I have just been debating downstairs, and it says that in the latest issue of Public Law Keith Ewing has an essay entitled "The Futility of the Human Rights Act 1998" which goes pretty close to the question of the European Convention. I am worried about the impact on habeas corpus, for example.

  Chairman: That is a problem for Mr Heathcoat-Amory to ask his next question.

Q51 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: Could we develop ideas about the jurisdiction of the European Court of Justice, which some people are already referring to as "the real Supreme Court" under this Constitution. Under Article 274 of part 3 of the Constitution the Court has powers to rule on the interpretation of the Constitution and therefore the allocation of competences. Some of us find the allocation of competences very vague, using words like "shared competences" and it is not clear what the powers of the Union will be over things like employment law and economic co-ordination or foreign and defence policy. Professor Denza, you have given evidence elsewhere about this. Do you have any observations about how the powers of the Court shift under the proposed Constitution and in particular in these areas like foreign policy that do not immediately fit into the shared or exclusive competences laid down in the Constitution. In an area of, of course, the Court, with its supreme powers, will finally decide without any appeal. Am I correct on that?

  Professor Denza: It might not be entirely without challenge on the question of who has the ultimate fiat on questions of the division of powers. At the moment you really have a situation where the Court takes the view that they are the ultimate arbiter and a number of constitutional courts have stated that their mandate comes from their own constitutions, and, as long as the nation states remain independent sovereign states—and I am a little bit concerned that some changes might call that into question—I do not think that position will be changed by anything on the face of the Constitution. That said, I agree that the Court will inevitably tend not only to regard itself as a constitutional court but to be generally regarded as a constitutional court, and I think there will be a greater level of deference and perhaps greater reluctance to challenge on issues of primacy and supremacy in particular.

Q52 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: I am aware that a number of national constitutional courts do not accept the unrestricted primacy of the Court, but the Constitution in Article 5 asserts without any qualification that the Constitution and the laws emanating from it shall have primacy over the laws of Member States. Is it not rather difficult, if we all agree to that, to hold a simultaneous doctrine against that, that actually that is not true and that in extremis a national court should prevail? Surely this unresolved tension, a kind of standoff of have the Convention, will be decided on the terms of the Union if this Constitution is enacted voluntarily by the Member States.

  Professor Denza: The very last words you said I think were very important. If there has been a nationally endorsed acceptance of this primacy—endorsed by all the national parliaments through their national constitutions and in a great many cases by referendums—then I think this political balance does tip to the centre. I think it is difficult perhaps to say it categorically changes it. It does not purport to change it, but I think under the surface there is a sea shift, if you like, in the centre of gravity.

Q53 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: You would not agree with the Government that all we are doing here is simply restating case law in the European Court of Justice. You think we are going beyond that now and doing something much more important which will give a greater status to the European Court's primacy.

  Professor Denza: Yes. The other limb of why I have reservations about what the Government say is that they imply that the primacy has been accepted law before the UK joined. Although that is true for the First Pillar, it was certainly not true for the intergovernmental aspects, which have never been part of UK law. They are not a part of the European Communities Act. So, as soon as there is a Bill, these parts will not be separated and, simply a matter of international law, this will bring it to the fore. Equally, it is very likely that there will have to be litigation before the German Constitutional Court. The Court made a number of qualifications in the Brunner case, which was about the Maastricht Treaty, saying that it was very important that foreign policy remained intergovernmental and it was not brought within this international community procedure, and I think they will be asked, and possibly a number of other courts, as to whether that remains true when the strong version of primacy—which is usually shorthanded by the case name of Koster v Ennal—goes right across the Third Pillar, which is beyond argument, on the text of the Constitution, but also to the Second Pillar, where you still have left a lot of argument, because the situation is left unclear by the Constitution. You have the Government saying that it will remain intergovernmental but it is extremely difficult to deduce that from the actual wording of the text.

Q54 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: So we have that awful combination of uncertainty plus an assumed primacy of the European Court of Justice—the worst of all worlds.

  Professor Denza: That is my fear.

  Professor Sir David Edward: I do not wholly agree with what Professor Denza has said. For me, the word "primacy" means nothing unless it is read in the context of the European Court's case law. I have argued with people who were at the Convention: "Why did you not say that, where there is a conflict between a rule of Union law and a rule of national law, the law of the Union shall be applied to the extent necessary and the rule of national law shall not be applied?" I have been told it sounded much nicer to say "primacy". But that is what I understand it to mean: it simply means that you cannot have two incompatible rules applied at the same time. There are two points. First of all, the Court of Justice has already had an enormous amount of experience of saying what are the competences of the Union. There have been many cases on competences, common commercial policy and so on. So it is not a new function for the Court of Justice to be determining that, and, indeed, it is a characteristic of that kind of court that it has to do that. Where the document says you shall have power to do this, that or the other and not to do something else, then somebody has to decide whether in the specific case you have the power or not, and that is given to the Court. It is not my personal experience that the Court has tended to enlarge the competences of the Union. On the contrary, while I was there I would have said that the Court was rather cautious about that. But, apart from that, as far as the German Constitutional Court is concerned, the decision of the German Constitutional Court in relation to the Maastricht Treaty was specifically in the context of the Maastricht Treaty. If Germany ratifies this Constitution and therefore adopts it, the Constitutional Court's position will, I think, be that that has become part of the constitutional law of Germany. Of course the Constitutional Court has said, "We reserve the right to say, that is not what we signed up to," but I am not sure that is a tenable position, because if every Member State ultimately reserved the right to say, "We did not sign up to that," then the reciprocity of the Treaty disappears, and the whole notion of primacy of course is based on the idea of reciprocity.

  Mr Cash: It seems to me—and I have argued this for some time—that effectively what is going on is the subsuming by the use of the internal parliamentary processes in each of the Member States, of a higher order which then becomes the ultimate jurisdiction. The Komptenz-Kompetenz issue, that you and Professor Denza have just described in relation to the Brunner case, has that effect. Indeed, you have probably read—in fact I think I can see it on your desk—some part of the Lords' scrutiny committee assessment of the issue of primacy, which I put to the Prime Minister some months ago, pointing out that the Lords' committee said that this question of division of competences was a completely new feature, it was a fundamental change, contrary to what he was saying, and that it was not just a drafting exercise because there was a revocation and a re-application of all the treaties, laws and rulings of the Court of Justice, and a re-application of all those under review primacy, which is contained in Article 1-5(a) I think it is. The question I put to you is the one which I put to Jack Straw in the House of Commons on 9 September, when I asked him if he agreed that the effect of Article 1-5(a), which states that the Constitution shall have primacy over the Constitutions and laws of the Member States, had the effect of imposing the Constitution over our own constitution and, indeed, our Parliament, to which he replied, "Yes, of course it does."

  Chairman: He gave you the answer there, Sir David!

Q55 Mr Cash: It is a preamble with a lot of meat in it, I may say so.

  Professor Sir David Edward: The other way of looking at it is: "The law adopted by the institutions of the Union, in exercising the competences conferred on it, shall have primacy . . ." The first point about this document is that for the first time it clearly goes into the question of conferred competences—which is new. Part of the criticism of the Court of Justice in the early days was that it was inferred competences, particularly in the line of the common commercial policy, so this is an attempt to delineate competences.

Q56 Mr Cash: They are pretty extensive competences, are they not?

  Professor Sir David Edward: Certainly. That is a matter for Member State choice.

  Mr Heathcoat-Amory: But they are not clear either. That is the point we have been making earlier: they are not clear. They are shared or they are—

  Chairman: I am sure we are not going to have any barracking of our witnesses.

  Mr Cash: Certainly not.

Q57 Chairman: Carry on, Sir David.

  Professor Sir David Edward: And then you said: "shall have primacy over the constitutional law of the Member States." The last text does not include the word "Constitution" of the Member States; it simply says "shall have primacy over the . . . law of the Member States."

Q58 Mr Cash: That is the point I put to Jack Straw and he said it still had the same effect.

  Professor Sir David Edward: If I may say so, it must do so, because the reciprocity of treaties cannot depend on whether Member State A says, "I can't fulfil that obligation because it is in my constitution" and Member State B has no written constitution and says, "Well, I can do it", or Member State C has a written constitution which does not include that provision. Reciprocity of Member State obligations cannot allow for a situation—and this is a basic principle of international law—where a Member State signs up to an obligation and then says, "Yes, but actually I had my fingers crossed behind my back because my constitution says I cannot do that."

  Mr Cash: That is unthinkable.

Q59 Mr David: You will be pleased to know I am not a lawyer but it seems to me that there is a basic difference between the way the European Court of Human Rights has traditionally functioned, dealing with human rights issues by definition, whereas the ECJ has been primarily concerned about economic issues. It seems to me that a fundamental difference is now taking shape and the European Court of Justice will, for the first time, be dealing with human rights issues and Member States have a wide variety, as we have noted earlier, of policies and principles underlining their social issues. I am told that the European Court of Human Rights, when dealing with this contradiction, has developed the doctrine of the "margin of appreciation". Do you see a similar sort of thing happening in the European Court of Justice, because for the first time it will be dealing with those kinds of issues?

  Professor Sir David Edward: First of all, this will not be the first time, if you look at some of the cases on asylum, the rights of third country nationals, the expulsion of members of families and so on. Even when I was there, the court was dealing with those kinds of issues—and that goes back some time, so it is not totally new. But I am fairly sure that "margin of appreciation" was an expression used by the Luxembourg Court before it was used by the Strasbourg Court.

  Chairman: The Committee stands suspended and we will reconvene as soon as we have a quorum back in the room.

The Committee was suspended from 3.31 pm to 3.38 pm for a division in the House


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 6 April 2005