Select Committee on European Scrutiny Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 80-99)

PROFESSOR PIET EECKHOUT AND PROFESSOR GRINNE DE BÚRCA

8 DECEMBER 2004

Q80 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: Surely not?

  Professor de Búrca: What it is loaded with I do not know. One of the purposes of a constitution is to clarify and limit powers but there are many other purposes. I think this whole Constitution exercise is one which is serving many different masters and mistresses. For example, the UK placed a lot of emphasis on the fact that it was a consolidatory Constitution which was not introducing a lot of innovation. Obviously, there are some new elements but the emphasis was on consolidation and simplification. You cannot simplify without radically changing a system that is as complex and intricate as this, so if the idea is to incorporate and codify the existing body it could not be clear because it is very complex and even lawyers cannot agree on the meaning of things, let alone explain them to the ordinary person. That fundamental tension is not resolved by the Constitution. I think in some aspects it simplifies it a little if, for example, the listing of categories and competences at least gives you a list of five different types, even if we do not understand exactly what they are until we look at Part 3, but nonetheless you broadly get a sense of it. Similarly, the Charter on its face is clarifying because it gives you a list of certain rights. It is then made very complex by the horizontal clauses and the reason for that is that the horizontal clauses were designed to maintain as much of the status quo as possible and the status quo is very complicated. Yes, maybe you are right, but if you do not want a Constitution that changes things radically then I cannot see an alternative other than to maintain some of the complexity that characterises the EU.

Q81 Mr Cash: Professor Eeckhout, you made the point just now in passing, but it seemed rather an important point, that you thought that the Constitution clarified the issue of primacy. Could I ask you a simple question? Do you take the view that the European Constitution will take precedence over the laws of the United Kingdom Parliament and if the Constitution comes into effect the European Court of Justice will disapply any enactment which has been passed by the UK Parliament and is expressly inconsistent with EU law?

  Professor Eeckhout: Here again I would say that the Constitution clarifies in the sense of codifying the case law of the European Court of Justice, which in this area, of course, dates from 1964, the first case, Costa v ENEL, where the Court affirmed the primacy or the supremacy of EU law. I know there are different views on that but I see the Constitution merely as expressly confirming that principle which has been there for a very long time and which has been applied. The European Court of Justice technically cannot disapply national legislation, an act of parliament, because it can only interpret EU law, but it has clarified to national courts that if there is a conflict between a provision of EU law and a provision of national law, of whatever order, the national court is obliged to disapply, in a bad English term, the national legislation and I gather that the Constitution will be interpreted as simply confirming that. What I would like to add, and that is, I think, where you see the limit to that principle, is that it is a principle which only works within the scope of Union law and I think we come back to the same point as the Charter—and it is a rather difficult point because what is the scope of Union law?—because it is very much emphasised also in the provision Article I-5 that primacy applies within the limits of the powers of the European Union. It is only in so far as the Union acts within the limits of its powers that any law which it produces prevails over domestic law, but that is clearly the principle.

Q82 Mr Cash: If I may follow that up, the fact remains that under the I-5 principle, which is set out, it now says (and there were some amendments, as you recall, before the final text) that the laws of the Constitution will take precedence over the laws of the Member States, and the interpretation which is being placed on that by our Foreign Secretary is that that would include any Acts of Parliament which were passed by the United Kingdom Parliament itself. The fact remains that the issue of primacy is a central question for the United Kingdom Parliament and you have not quite answered my question, which is, if there were to be an expressly unambiguous, inconsistent enactment subsequent to the European Communities Act 1972 after the Constitution has gone through, do you not think that the Court under I-5 would be likely, if not bound, to say that such an enactment can now be struck down by the European Court? After all, so long as it is within the conferring of competences, it is then an issue which falls to the European Court under other provisions and the Treaty as well.

  Professor de Búrca: Just to add to what Professor Eeckhout has said, there are two things about that question. One is that it assumes that the European Court can directly strike down a domestic Act, which it cannot do—

Q83 Mr Cash: At the moment.

  Professor de Búrca: There is nothing in this Constitution that gives it power to do so either. The powers of the Court that are set out do not include a direct power of review of domestic law. The question would be more appropriate directed to what the British courts, the English, Welsh and Scottish courts, will do following that because until now the answer many people would have given to your question would be that probably, even if a statute of the British Parliament was in deliberate contravention of European Community law, the European Court of Justice would have said, "That violates EC Law, that should be disapplied". I do not think it would have had a problem in saying that despite the direct conflict, but a domestic court might well have justified it, saying, "We must apply the law of Parliament and not this because within the way in which this supremacy principle is understood in the 1972 Act we must follow the Act of Parliament which is very explicit". Now I think the question will be, "What would a court do in this jurisdiction in that case?", and I think you can say that the fact that the Foreign Secretary has said, "We intend by this Constitution to allow for the overriding of Acts of Parliament", might make a court more likely to say, "Okay, we will disapply it". On the other hand, the Foreign Secretary does not speak for Parliament and therefore a court might decide to follow the later act of Parliament. I think that question is one that is more appropriately addressed to the role of domestic courts than the European Court.

Q84 Mr Cash: So it is not really quite as clear as Professor Eeckhout may have suggested in his passing remarks?

  Professor de Búrca: I think I would agree with him as far as the European Court of Justice is concerned. The European Court of Justice would certainly say, "This violates EC Law. You as the domestic court ought to disapply or set aside the conflicting national law", but I do not know that a national court would necessarily agree. It depends on the stage that the courts have reached in this jurisdiction as to whether they feel honour bound to respect the Constitution as Jack Straw would have to or whether they feel that that is still not quite what the intention of Parliament is under the Constitution.

  Professor Eeckhout: In any event the authority for the UK courts to apply the constitutional treaty will be an Act of Parliament so, to the extent that there is agreement that the constitutional treaty within the UK domestic context does not in any way amend the sovereignty of Parliament compared to the current position, then I think it is agreed that nothing changes and then courts are likely to give effect to the Act of Parliament which overrides the act which approves of the constitutional treaty, as would be the same with the European Communities Act.

Q85 Mr Cash: Including striking down the Constitution itself?

  Professor Eeckhout: It would be giving no effect to the Constitution in the United Kingdom by virtue of the primacy of Parliament.

  Chairman: Thank you for clearing that matter up for us!

Q86 Angus Robertson: Professor Eeckhout, in your article on the EU Charter and the Federal Question you have argued that "the concept of European citizenship is likely to pull the Charter in the direction of an ever-expanding field of application, and to turn it into a Charter not merely directed towards the EU institutions but containing rights on which European citizens can more generally rely". Why do you think the concept of EU citizenship will ultimately prove more important in defining the scope of the Charter than the horizontal clauses?

  Professor Eeckhout: Can I just add that in the article I also identified another principle which I think could constrain the effect of the Charter, which is the principle of conferral, which the Constitution also very much confirms, and I think it was one of the starting points of the constitutional process to try to clarify and limit EU competences. In a sense I see in terms of the case law of the Court of Justice two kinds of legal principle having a potential effect on the case law of the court which is affecting fundamental rights. As we have got EU citizenship the reason I refer to that is that that is of course a concept which is already in the treaties and is already given effect to by the European Court it is one of the primary rights of a European Union citizen to reside freely in and to move freely to other Member States, and so we have cases concerning free movement coming before the Court, where I think there will indeed be pressure to bring in the fundamental rights issue and to some extent I think we have already seen that in the case law. There is a case which came from the UK, Carpenter, decided a couple of years ago, about the right to family life in the context of an immigration issue. The wife of a UK citizen came from the Philippines and was not a legal resident but because she was the wife of someone providing services in another Member State the Court felt that there was a fundamental right issue, namely, the right to family life, which it could not look into. That is my personal perception of what kinds of factors exercise an influence on the Court of Justice's case law with respect to fundamental rights. I do not think the Constitution as such really moves it in either direction. If anything, again, the fact that so much emphasis has been put on this debate about in which cases Member States are bound by fundamental rights, namely, only when implementing EU law, might make the Court a bit careful about not going too far in that respect.

Q87 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: Could I continue with the issue of the horizontal clauses? We are constantly told that the EU law will effectively limit and closely define the Charter rights and their application. Professor de Búrca, you have written that you think they may have some effect but in time will be overridden by other considerations. Certainly I as a layman cannot make head nor tail of, for instance, the distinction between rights and principles. Perhaps you can throw some light on that. In general terms is this simply window dressing to satisfy politicians and will they in any sense constrain what is obviously a highly activist court in this area?

  Professor De Búrca: I would be tempted to say yes, they are just window-dressing, but I do not think that would be quite fair. I would say that there is a certain amount of satisfying or mollifying of the British and the Irish contingent within the Charter working-group, undoubtedly because that was the real crux issue during that working-group on the Charter. Certain members of the working-group would not agree to the Charter being incorporated in the constitutional text unless some distinctions were introduced between the language of rights and principles. I think I tried to explain in my written evidence that distinction was seen as corresponding broadly to what people see as more programmatic rights requiring positive action on social expenditure, which are usually grouped under the name "economic and social rights" and rights which mainly require restraint from interference by the State, which we usually refer to as "civil and political rights". The problem is even that distinction is a very hazy one in international human rights law and in domestic human rights law, but I think the idea was certainly, on the part of those arguing for this clause, to try to say that the Court of Justice cannot directly enforce rights which were intended to require further action before they crystallised, and economic and social rights are very often seen in that category. In other words, the right to health does not mean anything in itself because it calls into question so many complex distributive questions until there is further implementation of that guarantee. What the Charter says—in what was Article 52(5), it is now Article 112(5)—is those provisions of the Charter which contain principles will not be judiciably cognisable until they are implemented in some Act of a Member State or of the EU. I would find it extremely difficult going through the Charter to know which of the provisions will be treated as principles and which will be treated as rights, although I have a sense of what the aim was of putting that provision in. I can take some examples, like environmental protection or consumer protection, which are phrased in an extremely weak way in the Charter and say, "Clearly those could not give rise to any justiciable rights without further implementation". I find it more difficult with some of the others, even the examples given in the Explanatory Memorandum like the rights of the elderly and so on. I can imagine circumstances in which interpreting a piece of secondary legislation that was not intended to implement the rights of the elderly but nonetheless is relevant to it. The idea that the right of the elderly to respect and so on—I cannot remember the language—could be used in judicial proceedings to say that should influence the interpretation of another piece of legislation. I do not find the distinction helpful and I do not find it clear as between rights and principles, although I can see what was broadly intended by it. I think it will give rise to complex litigation and to a lot of debate.

Q88 Mr Heathcoat-Amory: It was intended to make the whole thing palatable and from what you are saying, it is just a smoke screen. The rights of the elderly are described as a principle, but in fact is an enforceable right if the EU legislates in this area. This seems to me to be a highly regressive move, we are simply confusing the issue and of course the Court will then do what it likes.

  Professor De Búrca: I think it is really confusing. I do not think it is entirely a smoke screen because if the Court is acting responsibly, in the same way that Professor Eeckhout suggested, it will know that that distinction was intended to demarcate certain rights as insufficiently sharply crystallised in international and domestic law to give rise directly to judicial application without some implementing measure. To my mind it is a guide that is not a very clear one. It is an indication of something which the Court should take into account without saying rights A,B,C,D and E are principles and rights and F,G and H are enforceable rights. In the end it does not give a sharp clarification, it gives an indication, a signpost of the kinds of concerns the Court of Justice should have when rights are invoked before it. It should be very careful about directly applying rights which are expressed in a way that does not seem to have any clearly understood content, but that is something which requires further implementation before it can have an agreed content.

Q89 Mr David: I think it is fairly clear what you are explaining there. Also, can you explain to us how what you have just said squares with the statement you have made in one of your articles, that the Charter expresses " . . . the clear values of Europe . . . "? It does not seem to me that clear and as straightforward as your answer just suggested. Secondly, I wonder if you can explain to us what you mean by this phrase "constitutional patriotism"? It seems quite an all-embracing and significant term which I have not come across before.

  Professor De Búrca: On the first one—you can correct me if I am wrong—I would be surprised if I said that the Charter expresses "the clear values", maybe I have forgotten what I wrote.

Q90 Chairman: The "shared values" of Europe?

  Professor De Búrca: Okay. Certainly, I think the Charter expresses values that those who signed the Charter and who drafted it wanted to express as shared values, the values which are contained in the European Convention and in the European social charter. These are all texts which all of the States have long signed and many of them have similar provisions in their Constitution. The fact that people can agree on values does not necessarily mean that in conflict situations they can agree on the outcome of that particular dispute, that is the nature of life as we all know it. Broadly speaking, I do think yes, there was a high degree of consensus behind the actual drafting of the Charter itself. I have never heard a seriously strong sense of opposition expressed to it other than in the sense that it may give too much power to a particular institution, like the Court of Justice, for example. As an expression of values, I have not heard anyone say: "This is ludicrous", apart from maybe the right to a paid vacation, which comes from the International Labour Organisation. In any case there are some provisions which have been criticised, but it is more that they are trivial rather than objectionable in value terms. I would maintain that yes, it does express common values in so far as we can agree on those. The other point was about "constitutional patriotism". "Constitutional patriotism" is not my phrase, it is the phrase of a German philosopher called Jürgen Habermas. It is an interesting idea, but it is an idea that it is possible in a Europe that is very culturally, nationally and territorially diverse to create a sense of loyalty to political principles and values which do not require any commitment to a common culture or to ethnic, linguistic or other pre-political categories like that, the sort of social communities that people strongly belong to which are expressed by nationhood and common language and so on. It is possible to imagine a thin sense of what he calls "constitutional patriotism", that is thick enough to support a constitutional document which is more than just a Treaty, through the idea of commitment to these common principles. In that sense it links with the question you asked about the Charter which is that something like a commitment, at its broadest, to democracy, the Rule of Law or the protection of human rights, but in a slightly more elaborate version expressed in the objectives of the Treaty and the values in the Charter, over time might emerge through a debate in each country over the meaning of the Constitution itself.

Q91 Mr Tynan: Professor De Búrca, you argued that the Charter may strengthen the political legitimacy of the EU. Can you explain your reasons for this view when many of the Charter rights fall outside the scope of EU law, even as defined by the Constitutional Treaty? Bearing in mind that the ECJ judges interpreting the Charter could be said to lack both legitimacy and the social and political support enjoyed by the US Supreme Court and the German Constitutional Court?

  Professor De Búrca: Firstly, one thing I want to say, which hopefully will not complicate matters further, but I suspect it will—it is not that I see my role as complicating things, it is a complicated system—is it is true that many of the rights contained in the Charter fall outside the scope of EU law in so far as the legislative power and political power of the institutions or the adjudicating power of the Court is concerned. But, currently there is a provision existing in the Treaty of the European Union which is justicable in procedural terms and allows for the institutions to respond to a serious violation of human rights by any Member State regardless of the area, whether it falls inside or outside the scope of EU law. This was in part a response to what was known as the Jörg Haider affair in Austria, when the rise of the extreme right gave rise to a sense on the part of the EU that it should be able to respond to a serious violation of fundamental rights in a Member State. Most recently, Members of the European Parliament have begun to try to invoke this in relation to Italy because of the concentration of media power in the hands a certain powerful political figure in Italy. I think for all that the EU's competence is limited, the EU has clearly staked a claim in extreme situations to be able to interest itself politically in the human rights system in any area of social and political life of a Member State. There was clear political agreement to that and I think that is something which has to be taken into account alongside the Charter and the express powers of law-making and the judicial powers of the Court. Your other question was about in what sense can the Charter be said to strengthen political legitimacy. There are many different factors that affect the lack of legitimacy of the EU, especially social legitimacy. One of them has been expressed quite often as "its emphasis on the market" in that it enshrines and constitutionalises market freedoms, pursuing a kind of neo-liberal agenda. Economic and Monitory Union restrains the power of States to pursue certain kinds of social welfare policies or even economic policies domestically. This emphasis of the EU on the market is one of the factors that has been cited often as a reason why citizens would not identify with it and would not see it as a protector of their welfare. In that sense, the Charter, when it was drafted, was explicitly drafted as a kind of counter-balance when the European Council in Cologne asked for the Charter to be drafted, to show that the EU does concern itself with other aspects of social life, with public welfare and so on and that it is not simply a Charter for businessmen. Obviously it raises a whole series of other legitimacy questions which you have pointed to, but in the sense of what ordinary citizens who are not interested in legal intricacies would think about, the idea that there is a Bill of Rights which protects their rights at all levels of government, including at the EU level, in my view would be more inclined to endear them to this level of government than for example, being told that abortion is a market service, a commercial service, under EC law. This was one of the most criticised aspects of the Court of Justice's case law, that even fundamental social issues like the choice to terminate a pregnancy are considered as market values because the only language the EU has is the language of the market, the only way it can conceive of citizens is as consumers and the only way it can conceive of rights is as commercial services. In that sense I think the Charter does redress that particular aspect of the legitimacy deficit.

Q92 Mr Tynan: Your view is that the Charter will strengthen the human face, if you like, of the European Union?

  Professor De Búrca: Yes. That is a much nicer way of putting it.

Q93 Mr Tynan: And because of that there will be closer identification as regards the people of the European Union at the present time because, as I say, it is not just the market forces, it is about doing a job for the people it is representing?

  Professor De Búrca: I think that is right. The Charter is more likely to appeal to the ordinary person than to know that there is a Stability and Growth Pact or that there are rules contained in the Maastricht Treaty relating to some other aspect of Economic and Monetary Union.

Q94 Mr Tynan: Do you think we will get that message across to the people in the European Union?

  Professor De Búrca: It depends on how well the job is done.

Q95 Mr Bacon: When we were in Brussels with the European Commission, they all looked at us in astonishment—and they were the ones cooking this stuff up—and said: "It is your job to get it across", as if it was nothing to do with them. I will pass on because that was not my question. My question is, Professor De Búrca, where do you think political legitimacy comes from?

  Professor De Búrca: Political legitimacy in general?

Q96 Mr Bacon: Yes. Where does it come from?

  Professor De Búrca: I suppose political legitimacy in the modern democratic systems lies in the fact of self-government, the idea that government is accountable and ultimately people themselves can in some way affect, if not control, the system that governs their lives. I would say that is where political legitimacy resides ultimately.

Q97 Mr Bacon: What do you think about the shared values of Europe?

  Professor De Búrca: I think the shared values of Europe include a commitment to democracy. For example, democracy and the rule of law are fundamental elements of a system that ensures self-government. Beyond that, in the more substantive sense of the shared values, there are fundamental rights and the various rights contained in the Charter. That is a very important commitment, and the hope is that in a system where people are involved in governing themselves, those are the fundamental values they would express.

Q98 Mr Bacon: When you referred to the shared values of Europe and the Charter being a potential vehicle for, and an expression of "constitutional patriotism"—and I have only got the quote from your book that you wrote and contributed to on the EU Charter—were you simply quoting Habermas or were you agreeing with him?

  Professor De Búrca: I am trying to figure out how this constitutes evidence on the Constitution, but I will come around to that.

Q99 Mr Bacon: I thought it was directly related to it because, as far as I understand it, the whole concept of a Verfassungspatriotismus is very much a German one because after certain events in the middle of the century they decided they probably could not have the traditional nationalism and patriotism that most nation states have had. When I was in Germany in September, I found a rather unwilling audience for the idea that that nation perhaps needed just a soupçon more nationalism. It is a message they find very difficult, to this day, for obvious reasons. Therefore, I understand the whole concept of "constitutional patriotism" to be very much a German one and not one that necessarily has application more widely, but he and possibly you appear to be saying it does. I am merely asking you are you merely quoting Habermas or is it also your view that the Charter is a potential vehicle for "constitutional patriotism"?

  Professor De Búrca: A bit of both, in the sense that Habermas's views on "constitutional patriotism" have been picked up and are very much a part of the academic discourse on Europeanisation and globalisation. More generally on the idea of constitutional patriotism outside the context of the nation state—which has been the shared political community for centuries—how one would create some sense of community beyond the nation state is difficult to imagine. Particularly within market-based systems as the EU was when it began, and as the WTO and various other systems seem now to be, it is very difficult to see how they can ever engage the citizen in a way that could lead to a political Community.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 6 April 2005