Select Committee on Science and Technology Written Evidence


APPENDIX 8

Memorandum from Dr Neville Cobbe, University of Edinburgh

ABSTRACT

  The evidence described in this document details suggested priorities for revision of the HFEA Act, focusing on the interests of children whilst urging for caution in the application of technical advances, tackling causes of infertility, discussing the feasibility of adoption as a solution to childlessness following reform of abortion law and appraising experimentation on human embryos.

PRIORITISING THE INTERESTS OF CHILDREN

  (1.i)  A number of contributors to the online consultation have agreed that the welfare of children should be paramount. However, it has also become clear that some people are not prepared to give children conceived artificially the same entitlements as other children if this might interfere with their own reproductive freedom. Surely the greatest protection should be given to those with the least choice available? This is consistent with the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child, which affirms that "the child, by reason of his physical and mental immaturity, needs special safeguards and care, including appropriate legal protection". Similarly, Article 8 of the Declaration of the Rights of the Child has stated that children "shall in all circumstances be among the first to receive protection and relief".

  (1.ii)  In particular, all future reproductive practices (including gamete donation and surrogacy) should therefore defend the right of children to know their parents according to Article 7 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child, whilst respecting Recital 24 and Article 14 of the EU human tissue directive. In keeping with Article 24 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child, it is also vital that the health of children should never be compromised whilst seeking to satisfy desires for parenthood. Consequently, the use of any immature gametes in assisted reproduction should be prevented until we can guarantee that we are able to completely replicate in vitro all of the essential epigenetic modifications naturally acquired by gametes in vivo. Unless precautions are made to ensure such rights are upheld, the consequences will certainly include future litigation.

  (1.iii) In keeping with Articles 11 and 24 of the Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights, reproductive cloning and germline modification should remain illegal due to the impossibility of guaranteeing their safety and the potential negative social consequences for the individuals concerned. As embryo splitting with selective delayed implantation may place similar social pressures and expectations on new children as cloning by nuclear transfer, this practice should also be discouraged. Finally, the creation of embryos from unfertilised eggs for reproductive purposes should also be prohibited as this appears to be unfeasible without germline modification, in addition to the increased risks of both homozygosity for deleterious alleles and genomic imprinting defects.

THE NEED FOR GREATER ATTENTION TO THE CAUSES OF INFERTILITY

  (2.i)  The root causes of infertility have received far less attention than various technological innovations that try to circumvent the problem itself, resulting in unsubstantiated claims of infertility on the basis of essentially behavioural choices. If our society is genuinely interested in treating infertility, then proportionately more attention should be paid to both epidemiological studies of infertility and basic research aimed at better understanding the molecular basis of gametogenesis.

  (2.ii)  Meanwhile, considerable caution should be exercised in the current use of ICSI (and possibly IVF generally), based on possible associations with genomic imprinting disorders. However, it remains to be clarified whether any increased risks of these and other congenital defects are primarily due to IVF procedures or parental genetic backgrounds. In one study, it has been reported that the prevalence of aneuploidy and structural chromosome defects are more than tenfold higher among infertility patients compared to the general population. In particular, Y chromosomal microdeletions affecting the DAZ gene family are the most common known genetic cause of human male infertility and spermatogenic failure whilst disruption of either the Catsper gene or the Smcp gene has been shown to affect sperm motility. Consequently, the use of assisted reproduction without parental genetic screening may simply aggravate the incidence of low sperm counts or the lack of functional sperm and lead to increased male infertility in subsequent generations.

  (2.iii)  In addition to genetic factors, promiscuous sexual behaviour may also contribute to infertility by increasing the incidence of venereal disease. For example, between 1995 and 1999, there was a 73% increase in new reports of genital chlamydial infection among men in the United Kingdom. The risk of transmitting Chlamydia to women is particularly worrying as this can result in serious complications including infertility. In addition, the number of new cases of gonorrhoeal infection (another cause of infertility) appears to have risen every year since 1995, with a 27% increase in cases from England and Wales between 1999 and 2000. Therefore, any treatment of infertility must include promoting awareness of the risks of casual unprotected sex. Lastly, the potential impact of environmental pollutants on male and female reproductive health deserves further investigation. In conclusion, it is clear that greater understanding of both genetic and environmental contributors to infertility will be crucial to future treatment, with comprehensive counselling available to anyone trying to conceive.

THE NEGLECTION OF ADOPTION

  (3.i)  Although it would be foolish to claim that all infertile couples would consider adoption to be a satisfactory solution, it is nonetheless clear that adoption has been sorely neglected as a possible solution for many childless couples. Although adoption does not treat the problem of infertility itself, it could equally be argued that gamete donation does not really treat infertility but rather side steps around the problem. It would therefore appear inconsistent to place considerable emphasis on the use of gamete donation whilst failing to encourage adoption. In contrast to gamete donation, adoption also provides a practical and caring solution to children who are unwanted by their genetic parents.

  (3.ii)  Similarly, viable excess embryos generated through IVF could provide a possible solution to many childless couples incapable of producing functioning gametes themselves. At the very least, it would seem unreasonable to suggest that any excess embryos resulting from IVF should be preferentially used in experimentation and destroyed rather than used to directly help others to conceive. Obviously the children born to infertile couples in this way would not be their genetic offspring in the same way that adopted children do not usually carry half the genes of each of their adoptive parents. However, at least one of the individuals bringing up a child also does not contribute any of their genes in the case of gamete donation.

  (3.iii)  Given that current practices such as ICSI may actually select for infertility if sperm motility defects are due to genetic factors, it would seem that infertile couples might have an increased chance of also becoming grandparents if adoption was more readily available as an alternative, since infertility is evidently not such an issue where unwanted progeny are concerned.

  However, the increased use of abortion for essentially social reasons has unfortunately resulted in a dramatic decrease in the number of children available for adoption. By examining the available national statistics, it can be shown that there is a strong negative correlation between the total number of adoption orders and the number of legal abortions registered. For example, the Spearmann coefficient of correlation between these two data sets during the period from 1974 to 2001 is -0.814 (±sr = 0.079). It is therefore clear that in order for adoption to become more feasible as a solution to childlessness, then it must be encouraged in preference to abortion.

THE NEED TO REFORM ABORTION LAW

  (4.i)  It is clear from the online consultation that people hold different views regarding the rights of the unborn, arguably based on the extent to which one's viewpoint is influenced primarily by an understanding of basic biology or personal interests. However, many people (whether disabled, homosexual or members of an ethnic minority) find the suggestion that they should be selected against as a group to be completely unacceptable. It is also clear from various comments submitted during the online consultation that some people find abortion acceptable either on supposedly medical grounds or because a child may be unwanted by their genetic parents, yet find it unacceptable that anyone like themselves might also be denied the right to life on the basis of the same criteria. At present, the alarmingly relaxed criteria for abortion seem to have created a precedent for all manner of selection against various "unwanted" groups and minorities.

  (4.ii)  For example, it appears that well over 99% of abortions in Britain since the millennium were performed for essentially social reasons, under the grounds that a pregnancy may pose any sort of increased potential risk to one's mental or physical health, with less than one in a thousand abortions being performed to directly save the life of the mother. Moreover, in the case of a pregnancy which has exceeded its twenty-fourth week, the loose criterion for abortion where there is a risk of "physical or mental abnormalities" apparently results in both the killing of foetuses with potentially treatable or less threatening medical complaints and a society more willing to dispose of its disabled than meet the cost of caring. Unless a group of people unanimously inform us that they themselves believe it would have been better if they had never been born, what grounds do we have to deny anyone the opportunity to experience life, whether they might be disabled or whether they are likely to be of a particular gender, race, stature or sexual orientation? We have no authority to assert that a particular condition is so debilitating that abortion is justified without the consent and opinion of all affected individuals regarding the value of their lives. If we really want to live in a fair society in which prejudice is not tolerated, then surely we should seek to ensure that the use of abortion is limited to those rare cases where lives are irrevocably endangered, in keeping with the constraints of Articles 3, 7 and 25 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights as well as Article 6 of the Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights. Unless we do so, we completely fail to recognise the fundamental equality and rights of all fellow humans.

  (4.iii)  The Convention on the Rights of the Child affirms the need for "special safeguards and care, including appropriate legal protection, before as well as after birth" and states in Article 6 that "every child has the inherent right to life" and we should "ensure to the maximum extent possible the survival and development of the child", whilst Article 1 defines a child as "every human being below the age of eighteen years". Unless we radically change our definition of human being to mean something other than a member of the species "Homo sapiens" (as defined by the Oxford English Dictionary), then it is clear that the vast majority of abortions currently performed fail to comply with universally recognised rights.

RE-EVALUATING HUMAN EMBRYO EXPERIMENTATION

  (5.i)  No completely convincing argument has been made regarding why human embryos should be considered as anything other than human. Although it has been argued that the blastocyst would die anyway if not transferred to the womb, the same principle could be applied to the survival of children deprived of nourishment or nurture. Similarly, low rates of natural implantation do not justify deliberate destruction of embryos any more than high mortality rates in developing countries justify genocide. The argument that an embryo is temporarily unaware of its own existence and feels no pain could equally be applied to anyone in a coma or under general anaesthesia. To deliberately deny experience to an embryo simply because it won't yet know what it's missing is inconsistent with the desire of most people to experience what life can offer and further application of the same principle would suggest that one could deny any future educational, marital or voting rights to today's infants. The notion of using emotional links with others as a basis for denying the humanity of embryos inevitably devalues anyone who lives alone or has difficulty forming relationships. Lastly, the assumption that the right to life and all consequent human rights are dependent on one's stage of development is simply a form of discrimination against the young. In conclusion, none of the above criteria can be applied consistently to embryos alone, so the only discernible reasons for denying human rights from the outset are self-interest and prejudice.

  (5.ii)  During the online consultation, no unbiased statistical evidence could be produced to support the view that most scientists and physicians favour either therapeutic cloning or stem cell research involving human embryos. By contrast, a recent survey in the U.S.A. to explore public opinion on stem cell research is particularly revealing. The participants were asked if they felt they had heard much about research involving embryonic stem cells but no prior attempt was made to objectively evaluate awareness of the issues concerned. Indeed, it is doubtful how informed the participants really were, as the assertion that "support grows with more information" was based on changes in voting after hearing information that highlighted only the potential of embryonic stem cells but made no reference to current therapeutic obstacles (such as teratoma formation) or additional concerns specific to therapeutic cloning such as the source of donor eggs. Another critical assumption inherent in the information presented to participants was that such research would not lead to any further destruction of embryos than is currently the case in IVF, whilst the current need to generate excess embryos remained unchallenged. In Britain, the success rate of IVF between 1986 and 2001 rose from 9% to 22% of treatment cycles leading to a live birth, such that the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority revised its guidelines to reduce the number of embryos used in IVF from three to two in order to decrease the likelihood of multiple births. Increased success rates have been partially attributed to improved culture conditions for early embryos or their transfer to the Fallopian tube rather than uterus. As pregnancy rates over 30% have been reported following single embryo transfer, this raises serious questions regarding the continued need to generate so many excess embryos.

  (5.iii)  Nevertheless, one can agree that research should be pursued on both stem cells from adult or extraembryonic sources and some embryonic stem cells. Whilst trials with various mesenchymal cells have shown particular therapeutic promise, widespread clinical use and understanding of any stem cells is still in its infancy. It is therefore highly questionable that current basic research should necessarily require human embryos. In particular, given that we now have sequenced genomes for both the rat and the mouse, this should greatly facilitate the transfer of insights from stem cell research in model organisms to our own species. Indeed, it has been shown that the overall expression of markers of the pluripotent state is essentially similar in mouse and human embryonic stem cell lines, with most identifiable differences thought to reflect different stages at which stem cells had been harvested from the inner cell mass in different organisms or contamination with differentiated human cells. Most observed differences are consistent with the reported ability of human embryonic stem cells (unlike their mouse counterparts) to differentiate into trophoblast-like cells and to propagate in a pluripotent state even in the absence of LIF, whilst the greater resistance of human embryonic stem cells to apoptosis indicates that their application in a clinical context may pose an even greater risk of cancer than observed with mouse cell lines. As mouse stem cells provide a convenient model for studying differentiation requirements, one must conclude that the urgency to use human embryos at this stage in the search for therapies arguably contrary to the Nuremberg code and the Declaration of Helsinki is motivated primarily by quests for fame or fortune, whilst downplaying recognised risks and ethical concerns.

  (5.iv)  The grave risks currently associated with any therapeutic use of embryonic stem cells are nevertheless acknowledged even by proponents of research involving human embryos and are referred to in Recital 11 of the EU human tissue directive. One should therefore be concerned not only by the questionable morality of destroying potentially viable human lives but also that the rush to apply preliminary embryonic stem cell data in a clinical setting may result in patients being subjected to premature trials, placing them at risk of complications such as teratocarcinomas. Regardless of the moral status of human embryos themselves, the feasibility of any research necessitating their destruction needs to be critically assessed in relation to practical alternatives. By contrast, such complications in the use of adult stem cells have so far only been reported as a consequence of forced telomerase expression, whilst the risks of cell fusion in vivo have been grossly exaggerated without challenging the established use of bone marrow transplants and umbilical cord blood to treat leukaemia patients. Moreover, it should be noted that adult stem cells rarely acquire oncogenic mutations due to propagation of replication errors as the original DNA templates are selectively segregated into daughter stem cells, whilst their propagation by treatment with xanthosine (to reversibly suppress asymmetric cell division) does not appear to result in either senescence or tumorigenic properties.

  (5.v)  Regarding the naïve proposal to create interspecific chimeras for therapeutic cloning, it would appear that host mitochondrial function is not properly supported by donor nuclei from more distantly related species. Although reports differ regarding the preferential replication of donor or host mitochondria, it is nonetheless possible that supplying more donor mitochondria may alleviate some incompatibility problems. However, preliminary data from comparative cloning experiments and interspecific crosses also suggest that nuclear reprogramming in ova from other species would lead to even greater epigenetic dysregulation than previously observed with nuclear transfer. Given the association with cancer of both global DNA hypomethylation and hypermethylation of tumour suppressor gene promoters, this should surely be avoided.

May 2004





 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 24 March 2005