Select Committee on Science and Technology Written Evidence


APPENDIX 59

Memorandum from Professor Len Doyal, University of London

  I am Len Doyal, Professor of Medical Ethics at Queen Mary, University of London. I have published widely on moral philosophy in general and ethics and law applied to medicine in particular.

  On a variety of issues, I have been a consultant to the General Medical Council, the Department of Health, the Royal Colleges of Surgery and Medicine and the Medical Research Council. I am a member of the ethics committee of the British Medical Association (BMA).

  1.  I would argue that procreative freedom should be maximised in relation to reproductive technologies and that with one exception, legal constraints on reproductive choice should generally be abolished. This includes current constraints on termination of pregnancy, at least up to 24 weeks. The exception is the use of reproductive technology to produce rather than to prevent children who are physically harmed in relation to their future potential for successful participation in any form of social life they may wish to choose, including choices that their parents may not anticipate.

  2.  Thus, for example, I think that the deliberate use of IVF to produce children who are deaf or blind (or both!) should not be allowed and that licensed clinics should be prohibited from facilitating it or anything like it. For the same reason, although no other, I would also oppose cloning for reproductive purposes until its safety is ensured. The corollary of this is that clinics employing reproductive technology should be allowed to do anything necessary medically to comply with the wishes of parents to facilitate the birth of children without physical harm, even when their birth is intended to help other children or adults to avoid such harm. The latter case of course assumes that children born will not be physically harmed as a result of the help that they give others. There is no good evidence to suggest that such children would be otherwise harmed in such circumstances.

  3.  This is not to suggest that children born through reproductive technology might not face other forms of foreseeable non-physical harm. For example, children born in a socio-economic background of poverty and poor education may also be seriously disabled in their capacity for social participation. However, this will be no more or less than children who are born without reproductive technology into the same social environments. Equally, human history is replete with narratives of adults who have totally overcome the socio-economic constraints of their childhoods. So long as the regulation of "normal" birth is rightly prohibited on the grounds of human rights and civil liberty, the same should apply to the use of reproductive technology to constrain parental choice—unless the aim of the intervention is to produce a child who will be physically harmed.

  4.  I recognise that parents who, say, wish a deaf child with the help of IVF and other technology, might argue that they can now try to have one without such technology. This is true but in my view when serious physical harm is foreseeable with certainty and it can be avoided, it should be. I equally recognise that it may be argued that since children who are not expected to be physically harmed may overcome socio-economic disadvantage, such potential children should not be aborted. This statement is not the place to debate the ethics of abortion. What is relevant is to underline the fundamental importance of the human right of women to choose what happens to themselves in the course of their pregnancies, always remembering that they will probably remain the best judges of the quality of lives of future children they choose to terminate.

  5.  Three consequences follow:

    (i)  The HFEA (or something like it) should continue to have two functions: a) to protect the safety of the use of reproductive technologies by clinics and b) to ensure that this use is not abused by the deliberate creation of children who are harmed in terms of their future capacity for successful social participation and choice of type of such participation.

    (ii)  The HFEA (or something like it) should have no further control over the reproductive choices of parents. They should be regarded as the best judges of when it is best to have children, and to the degree that it is safe, what kind of children they should have through the use of reproductive technology. For example, if they wish to choose the sex of their child then this should be as acceptable as their choosing that their child not inherit a genetic disease. It is the parents who must be judged to have the final decision about so-called positive as well as negative physical attributes, both on the grounds of civil liberty and because they will have a better understanding of the psycho-social environment in which their child will evolve into an adult and the potential harm to which this environment might lead.

    (iii)  If the first two consequences are correct, it follows that any use of reproductive technology should be allowed that has the goal of adding value—increasing and not decreasing potential for successful social participation—to the lives of future children or future adults. Further research into such uses is essential and should only be regulated to the degree that other medical research is already successfully regulated. I realize that such a view presupposes that it is morally acceptable to sacrifice human embryos with the goal of furthering the physical health of already existing or potentially existing children and adults. It would be inappropriate to defend this belief here, although it should be noted that with some exceptions (eg reproductive cloning) it appears to be acceptable to the general public.

  6.  To conclude, therefore, I have argued that the use of reproductive technology should be broadly deregulated in ways that optimise the civil liberties of parents, particularly women. The same goes for research into and employing reproductive technology, provided that it, like other medical research, is regulated by the application of the principles of the Helsinki Declaration. To the degree that continued regulation is justified, it is to ensure the quality and safety of the delivery of reproductive technology and that this technology is not deliberately used to create children who are physically harmed in ways that will foreclose future types of social participation that they may choose.

October 2005





 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 24 March 2005