Select Committee on Science and Technology Written Evidence


APPENDIX 70

Memorandum from Professor J K Mason, University of Edinburgh

RANDOM OBSERVATIONS ON THE 1990 ACT

  There are three aspects of the 1990 Act that I would pick out as meriting special consideration.

The place of the Code of Practice

  The Code of Practice always raises concern in my classes, particular emphasis being laid on Part 3—dealing with the welfare of the child and the assessment of those seeking treatment.

  An argument can be raised—based on the fact that we do not undertake any assessment of those who intend to reproduce naturally—that any regulation of assisted reproduction represents discrimination against the disabled. I do not, in fact subscribe to this; some regulation—particularly of gamete donors—is clearly necessary.

  Nevertheless, it seems to me that regulation should be uniform. As things stand, assessment designed, primarily, to protect any resulting children is left to the treatment centre (para 3.1); regulation by way of a Code of Practice is, essentially, advisory rather than directive and is certainly open to interpretation. This is bound to lead to inequality and, as a consequence, to "shopping around", a situation that is compounded by the fact that the majority of treatments are given via the private sector—thus, even such unifying influence as might be imposed through the NHS is lacking.

  I suggest that the great majority of persons would find this unsatisfactory and, while I think that the subject is worthy of a paper to itself, one might start looking at it from three basic viewpoints:

    (a)  That the clinic's power to reject applicants for treatment should be restricted to purely medical, including medico-economic, reasons—eg the physical ability of the woman to carry children and age.

    (b)  That the very arbitrary "selection process" as regards social suitability of patients should be reconsidered on ethical grounds and should, in general, be confined to steps designed to protect the childless woman—eg to counselling and understanding.

    (c)  That such part of Part 4 as concerns the medical screening of donors and is, essentially, a matter of protection of the public, should be incorporated within the Act and, therefore, clearly divorced from the discretion of the clinic.

Surrogate motherhood

  It seems to me that surrogate motherhood is just as much a treatment of particular forms of childlessness as is, say, ovum donation or standard IVF. Two consequences follow from this. First, surrogate motherhood should, ideally, only be available as medical treatment and, second, that it should be subject to a form of regulation that is comparable to the regulation of any other treatment of childlessness.

  The situation is further complicated by the fact that there are two forms of surrogacy—partial, or standard, surrogacy which is currently unregulated and full surrogacy, or "womb leasing", which is regulated—not per se, but because it involves the production of an embryo outside the body. It is illogical that two techniques, both of which have the same intended end of neonatal transfer, should be treated differently—particularly when, first, the medical indications for the unregulated partial surrogacy are very much les common than are those for full surrogacy and, second, the genetic end-result of the former is far less satisfactory than is that of the latter. The case for uniformity seems overwhelming.

  Without having researched the matter thoroughly, it seems to me that there are two options to explore:

    (a)  To accept that the regulation of partial surrogacy is, in practice, impossible. The logical conclusion is, then, to release, as a specific exception, full surrogacy from the licensing strictures of the 1990 Act and to regard it as a medical treatment subject only to the ethico-legal constraints of good medical practice and to the total prohibitions now embodied in section 3 of the 1990 Act.

    (b)  To control partial surrogacy by what seems to be the only practical method—that is, to restrict parental orders to those treatments carried out in licensed clinics. This option, of course, involves disabling children who are conceived and born outside such regulation. It would have to be resolved by Parliamentary decision as to whether this was or was not an acceptable price to pay for restructuring an area of medical law which is particularly unsatisfactory.

THE CNR "EMBRYO"

  It is, in my opinion, inappropriate that the truly massive ethical decision as to what constitutes an embryo should be left to a pragmatic decision by the Courts—albeit by the House of Lords. The definition of the organism resulting from somatic cell nuclear replacement, rather than its legal control, is a fundamental task which, for want of anything better, must be undertaken by Parliament.

  CNR is a wholly unnatural technique and it is, in my view, morally—and, indeed, semantically—wrong to assume that the CNR "embryo" and the natural embryo are comparable in every way. The former is a laboratory artefact and, whatever, the end result of the technique, it must be regarded as such.

  It is, of course, an unavoidable fact that a CNR produced embryo that proceeded to maturity would be indistinguishable from its natural counterpart. For this reason, the Human Reproductive Cloning Act 2001 must be regarded as essential legislation and, in my view, every effort should be made to extend its status to that of an instrument of the United Nations. Something more is, however, needed and it seems to me that, in the present state of the debate, this can only be effected by way of restrictive legislation. The difficulty of the task is compounded by the corresponding difficulty of finding a suitable name for the CNR "embryo"; I admit to being at a loss although I very much favour using the concept of propagation. I, therefore, suggest that any new Act should include a section along the lines:

    "A maturing human zygote that is the product of a propagative technique shall not be regarded as a human embryo for any purpose except as prescribed by regulation"

  and regulations would then set limits on its use, survival and disposal.

  Again, I admit to not having given sufficient time to elaborating this proposal. Even so, it does seem to have positive as well as negative benefits. The former derive from the fundamental objection to the "use" of human embryos—a matter which was a main consideration of the Warnock Committee. The concept of an affront to the "dignity" of the human embryo is largely dissipated if one clearly distinguishes the unnatural from the natural embryo and regards the former as a creation of the laboratory, comparable to that of a cell culture. The major ethical objection to the use of embryos as a source of therapeutic stem cells is, thereby, eliminated—and this, it is contended, is based on justifiable moral grounds rather than sophistry.

October 2004





 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 24 March 2005