Select Committee on Science and Technology Written Evidence


APPENDIX 81

Supplementary memorandum from the British Medical Association

1.  What effect has regulation had on clinical standards? What mechanisms could be used to drive up good practice?

  The HFEA sets standards in its code of practice and carries out inspections to ensure that these standards are met. The BMA does not have detailed information about how this has worked in practice and how much the standards set by the HFEA have changed practice within clinics—this question would be better directed towards clinics themselves. It is clear, however, from examples such as the reduction in the number of embryos to be replaced per cycle that the HFEA's decisions about good practice clearly impact on the way treatment is provided. The regulatory mechanism also provides reassurance to patients seeking treatment that certain minimum standards are adhered to and, for example, that the treating staff have the appropriate training and expertise.

2.  What action could be taken to improve the inspection and monitoring of clinics?

  We are not in a position to respond to this question as we do not have detailed or practical experience of the inspection process.

3.  Would you like to see a greater role for the professional bodies in drawing up technical and clinical guidelines?

  It is difficult for us to comment on this without detailed information about the current level of consultation with professional bodies in drawing up technical and clinical guidelines. It is clearly important that the HFEA is involved in drawing up guidance or, in some cases, endorsing that provided by other bodies. In doing so, views should be sought from all relevant bodies in order that the HFEA is able to make informed decisions based on the most up to date information available.

  The area in which the BMA has most input into the HFEA's work is on its ethical policy. In this area the HFEA frequently seeks the BMA's views to feed into its deliberations, both formally through public consultations and on a more informal basis on particular issues. We believe this works well.

4.  What ethical issues does reproductive cloning raise, other than safety?

  In 1999 the BMA produced a discussion paper for the World Medical Association on human "cloning" (covering both reproductive and "therapeutic" cloning) calling for a rational and informed debate about the issue. The document clarified the differences between the range of activities that had been covered by the general heading of "cloning" and also set out the ethical arguments in relation to reproductive cloning. A copy of this paper is attached; part 2 (on pages 2-7) is directly relevant to this question.

  The BMA recognises that many of the arguments expressed in opposition to human reproductive cloning are based on common misperceptions (see pages 1-2 of BMA paper) and instinct rather than clearly articulated robust and logical arguments. We have argued—for example in Medical Ethics Today—the BMA's handbook of ethics and law—that if we reached the stage where it was possible to say with a reasonable degree of certainty that human cloning was safe, it would be essential to explore in more detail the motives of those who wish to use this technology and to consider the benefits, harms and likely consequences of allowing it. In the absence of concerns about safety, it would be essential to ensure that continued opposition to cloning was based on careful analysis rather than relying on ill-defined notions of "human dignity" and to ensure that decisions are made on the strength of the arguments rather than simply on the strength of public opinion.

5.  What is your view of the effectiveness of local ethics committees? Could they take on some of the ethical oversight currently conducted by the HFEA?

  We have only anecdotal information about the effectiveness of local research ethics committees provided primarily by individual BMA members in relation to their particular experiences. Perhaps inevitably, when our members raise issues about ethics committees with us it tends to be because there is a problem or because they are unhappy about a decision that has been made or in relation to some problem connected with their membership of an ethics committee. Nevertheless, whilst recognising that the feedback we receive is neither representative nor comprehensive, our general perception reflects the widely held view that the quality of ethics committees around the country varies considerably. We are aware that for some time now, particularly following the adoption of the Medicines for Human Use (Clinical Trials) Regulations, work has been in hand to improve the quality and consistency of ethics committees.

  The BMA has, for many years, advocated the use of clinical ethics committees to help doctors working in assisted reproduction to consider difficult cases. Their use is now also supported by the HFEA. Although we are aware that the number of clinical ethics committees is increasing (and expanding to other areas of clinical practice) we do not have detailed information about how they operate although we know that many of our members find them useful. The Royal College of Physicians has, however, recently completed a review of ethics support in health care practice, which includes an assessment of clinical ethics committee. We understand the report of this work is due to be published shortly. You might also find it helpful to contact ETHOX (the Oxford Centre for Ethics and Communication in Health Care Practice—www.ethox.org.uk) which has undertaken a considerable amount of work in this area.

  We see the role of ethics committees in the area of assisted reproduction as being to provide advice on clinical cases within the broad framework permitted by the HFEA. We believe it is appropriate for the HFEA, rather than a local ethics committee, to consider individual cases where they raise new, or particularly controversial issues—such as the selection of embryos on the basis of tissue typing. We would not expect the HFEA to become involved, however, in individual decisions about whether a particular post-menopausal woman should be provided with treatment (although it might, during its inspection process, question the way in which the decision to treat was made and how the welfare of the child was assessed in the particular case).

  In relation to embryo research we believe that there is sufficient public concern to justify maintaining the current practice whereby every research project is considered and approved by the HFEA.

November 2004





 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 24 March 2005