Select Committee on Science and Technology Written Evidence


APPENDIX 85

Memorandum from Professor Donna L Dickenson, Birkbeck College, University of London

  I have been asked to make a written submission of evidence, based on my recent research on the French national bioethics committee, my current membership of the Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists Ethics Committee, and my past membership of several clinical ethics committees in Oxford and London. I am also the author of some 60 articles and seven books concerning reproductive ethics and other issues in medical law. In addition I have led six European Commission projects in medical ethics and law, including the current EC-funded project PropEur: Property Regulation in European Science, Ethics and Law, which examines and compares regimes of property in human tissue across Eastern and Western Europe. I was asked by the Retained Organs Commission to submit an expert opinion on personal and property rights in tissue and have submitted consultation opinions to the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, the Law Commission and other policy-making bodies.

  Whilst I have sometimes disagreed with individual Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority decisions, I am strongly opposed to proposals to replace the statutory regulatory powers of the HFEA with a national ethics committee having merely consultative powers. The HFEA is widely respected throughout Europe and greatly envied in the United States. It is a valuable counterweight to a system of research governance which is regarded in the rest of Europe as quite permissive enough, indeed possibly too lax. I therefore disagree with the recent claims by Robert Winston and the submission of the British Fertility Society, both of whom assert that the HFEA has inhibited research progress. In point of fact, in such areas as stem cell technologies the UK is a research leader, with a far more liberal and market-oriented regime than its competitors within Europe and indeed than the United States. There is no need to move further down that road, and many reasons to think that an updated regulatory authority, accompanied by a national bioethics committee but not replaced by it, is absolutely essential to deal with the rapid evolution of new reproductive technologies. Even with the advent of the Human Tissue Authority, and the ethics governance framework of UK Biobank, the HFEA's statutory authority will still remain necessary, and its 15 years of decision-making experience will help to guide the new bodies.

  While the UK debates setting up a national ethics committee to replace the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, France is doing the reverse: creating a new statutory national biomedicine regulatory authority, in addition to the 20-year-old national ethics committee. After January 2005 the CCNE (Comite Consultatif National d'Ethique) will be joined, or perhaps outranked, by a new agency, L'Agence de la Biomedicine, created by legislation passed this past summer. To date the CCNE has delivered 85 opinions; since 1997 it has had the power to select its own topics, but contrary to the stereotypical view of French thought as deductive, most represent current practical dilemmas and are heavily weighted towards clinical relevance.

  Established in 1983 by the decree of 23 February, and given a formal statutory basis by the "lois bioethiques" of 1994[306] and 2004,[307] the French CCNE has a total membership of 39 persons, plus a chairman appointed by the President of the Republic. Within the full group, there are three separate methods of appointment. The first "college" consists of five members likewise appointed by the President, "belonging to the principal philosophical and spiritual families";[308] the second of 19 persons with particular competence in ethics, appointed by the National Assembly, the Senate, the Conseil d'Etat, the Cour de Cassation, and the ministries of Justice, Health, Research and Communication. The final "college" of 15 members is selected from nominations by the major professional and research bodies, such as the national academies of medicine and science, the Institut Pasteur, the College de France, and the nationally funded research bodies INSERM and CNRS. Although this third group is meant to be particularly expert in research, it is not necessarily limited to scientists and physicians; nor is the second group heavily weighted to philosophers. Jurists carry considerable authority and are well represented in most working groups, with a tendency to conflate ethical and legal thinking by referring to existing law in order to derive ethical principles.[309]

  The 2004 law sets up a new "Agence de la Biomedicine"[310] with functions similar to (but wider than) those of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. Much of the 2004 legislation seems at first glance to rely on this agency to ensure that no ill is done by the numerous relaxations of principle elsewhere in the statute, such as the greatly expanded list of purposes for which tissue can be taken as a gift from a living person. (For example, no tissues or cells can be transferred to any other establishment without authorisation from the new agency, which may help to inhibit totally free global markets in biomaterial.) This is a good measure, in my view, because the new French agency will encounter a much more commodified situation at its inception in 2005 than the HFEA did when it began operations 15 years ago.

  We already face a situation in which a globalised trade in oocytes is developing, their shortage for IVF purposes being aggravated by their current indispensability in the stem cell technologies.[311] Amounts of up to $50,000 per cycle have been reported for oocyte sale, with up to 70 ova being extracted in some cases.[312] It seems highly likely that poor women in the Third World and in Eastern Europe will be the targets of this globalised trade,[313] which is not presently overseen by any international regulatory agency. In that threatening and troublesome context, two regulatory heads are probably better than one: both the CCNE and the new Agence de la Biomedicine for France, and for the UK, both the HFEA and a national bioethics committee with something more than merely consultative powers. The HFEA has already taken some steps towards attempting to regulate this international trade—for example, by overseeing procedures under which ova are imported from Romania.

  Two questions arise about the remit and composition of a possible national ethics committee. One concerns the recruitment of interest groups. Here I would advise caution: the US replaced its excellent and representative national bioethics advisory committee with a panel deliberately chosen to be "pro-life", and thereby lost all credibility in the medical and bioethics community. We must also bear in mind that our legislation and case law takes a very different position from the American one on such questions as abortion and therapeutic cloning, and the members of the group must presumably adhere to the spirit of our law. This caution should not be confined to "pro-life" interest groups, but as the pro-life issues are among the most intractable, their representation does create the gravest problems in terms of consensus and effectiveness. We risk creating a situation such as that in Germany, where research is hampered much more seriously than in the UK by the implacable strength of the pro-life lobby.

  Here again the French experience is instructive, since the debate over the start of life is if anything more bitter there than in the UK, with the pronounced division between Catholic and secular opinion. Each of the three CCNE presidents to date has laid a different level of stress on attaining unanimity and on presenting a definite opinion to the government, rather than elucidating the pros and cons of the argument so that ministers and legislators can then make up their own minds. Thus, for example, the second president, Jean-Pierre Changeux, explicitly rejected the view that the task of the committee was merely to state possible arguments. That agreement was possible in the 29 opinions over which he presided was due, he believes, to concentration on practical regulation rather than foundational debate on concepts such as the status of the embryo.[314]

  Second, there is the question of a referral function for difficult cases as being within the possible remit of a national committee. I have served on several local clinical ethics committees, in London and Oxford, and would say that the difficulty is speed of response. Many cases require judgements to be made quite quickly; having to wait for an opinion from a national committee might be problematic. For example, when I was on the clinical ethics committee at St Mary's Hospital, London, we were asked to approve the application for the world's first hand transplant to be done at the hospital. Having reviewed the documentation, we had some doubts about the mental capacity of the patient, and asked for a psychiatric referral before saying yea or nay. The clinical team decided to bypass this requirement by having the procedure done quickly in France. Six months later, it transpired that the patient was indeed psychotic, believed that the cadaveric hand that had been transplanted was his own hand, and therefore saw no need to take his immunosuppressives. The hand had to be amputated. I mention this story to show the sorts of pressures to make quick decisions which clinical ethics committees already face from clinicians.

  Although the profession understandably and predictably wishes to regulate itself on ethical matters, medical and scientific competence is not the same as legal or ethical expertise. There has always been a certain degree of conflict between the HFEA and some of the IVF clinics—by no means all—and that this is only to be expected if the regulator has any power. In fact the HFEA does have a number of IVF professionals on its board, and its expertise is further enhanced by the very systematic manner of its consultations, which have earned it great respect among most medical ethicists, lawyers, scientists and clinicians.

December 2004






306   (1) Loi no 94-548 du 1 juillet 1994 relative au traitement de donnees nominatives ayant pour fin la recherche dans le domaine de la sante; (2) Loi no 94-654 du 29 juillet 1994 relative au don et a l'utilisation des elements et produits du corps humain, a l'assistance medicale a la procreation et au diagnostique prenatal; (3) Loi no 94-653 du 29 juillet 1994 relative au respect du corps humain. Back

307   Articles L 1412-1, -2, -3, -4, -5, -6. Back

308   Article L 1412-2. Back

309   I am grateful to Simone Bateman, member of the committee from 1992-96, for this insight. Back

310   Article L 1418-1. Back

311   Donna Dickenson, "The threatened trade in human ova," Nature Reviews Genetics, vol 5 (March 2004), p 167. Back

312   Susan Weidman Schneider (2001) "Jewish women's eggs: a hot commodity in the IVF marketplace," Lllith, vol 26, no 3, p 22; Allen Jacobs, James Dwyer and Peter Lee, "Seventy ova," Hastings Center Report, vol 31, no 4 (2001), pp 12-14. Back

313   Donna Dickenson, "Commodification of human tissue: implications for feminist and development ethics," Developing World Bioethics, vol 2, no 1 (2002), pp 55-63. Back

314   Introduction by Jean-Pierre Changeux, in Didier Sicard (ed), Travaux du Comite Consultatif National d'Ethique (Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 2003). Back


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005
Prepared 24 March 2005