Select Committee on Constitutional Affairs Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 66-79)

RT HON LORD JUSTICE MAURICE KAY

31 OCTOBER 2006

  Q66 Mr Beith: Sir Maurice, welcome to this unusual joint sitting of the Constitutional Affairs Committee and the Home Affairs Committee, in which we have been exploring, for our own benefit in part, the Human Rights Act and the way in which it has worked in practice. We are very grateful to you for agreeing to take part in this session. We well understand the position we place judges in when they appear before parliamentary committees—indeed, the Constitutional Affairs Committee now does this on a regular basis—and we quite understand your very proper reluctance to embark on issues of policy or, for that matter, to become embroiled in cases which you may have heard or may yet hear. If at any stage in the questioning you feel you are being pushed to one of those limits, you have only to say so and we will fully understand. I think you have an opening statement you want to give us.

  Lord Justice Kay: I have, thank you, yes. I prepared it yesterday. I think it has been circulated to you in draft. There is an addition to the sixth of the seven points that I made, so when I get to page 3, it will be longer than it is in the copy that you have. Would you like me to begin with it?

  Q67  Mr Beith: Please.

  Lord Justice Kay: I have been given an indication of the topics you would like me to address. I shall do my best but hope that you will not mind if I approach them in my own way. I would like to begin with some general observations which seem to me to be of fundamental significance, even if some of them are statements of the obvious. First, one of the hallmarks of a mature democracy is that political power must be exercised in accordance with the law. The expression "the rule of law" has a number of meanings but that one is, I hope, beyond dispute. When the expression was used by Parliament in Section 1 of the Constitutional Reform Act 2005, I assume that it was being used in that sense. Secondly, in any mature democracy, the judiciary has an important role in securing compliance by government and other public authorities with the law. There is nothing new about this. Thirdly, long before the Human Rights Act, the courts developed and expounded the scope of judicial review of the decisions of public authorities. They did so on a case-by-case basis, the centrepiece of the modern jurisprudence being the GCHQ case in 1985, which defined both the principles of modern judicial review and its limits. It made clear, amongst other things, that there were considered to be certain judicial no-go areas, including matters of national security and foreign relations. Indeed, that judicial self-restraint still exists at common law, as can be seen, for example, in the rejection in late 2002 of the application by CND for judicial review of the lawfulness or otherwise of the then contemplated invasion of Iraq. To some extent, by enacting the Human Rights Act, Parliament has drawn us into new areas. Fourthly, the Human Rights Act requires—and I emphasize that word—judges to approach a great deal of public law litigation in new ways. It requires us, if at all possible, to construe domestic legislation compatibly with Convention rights. It requires us to take account of Strasbourg case law. It enables, and, by implication, expects us to declare domestic legislation to be incompatible with Convention rights although, by its elegant approach, it does not empower us to strike down incompatible primary legislation. It also imposes on all public authorities the duty to act without contravention of the Convention rights of persons affected by their decisions and this, in turn, requires the courts to give effect to Convention rights in domestic litigation. All this we do, not because of the arrogation of power to ourselves but because of the obligations imposed on us by Parliament through the Human Rights Act. Fifthly, all this is leading the courts into new territory. Thus, in the case of A & Others, the Belmarsh detainees, the courts had to consider, amongst other things, the lawfulness of a derogation from this country's international obligations. The Convention test is one of "a public emergency threatening the life of the nation", the very sort of issue in which, by reference to the GCHQ case, judicial angels traditionally feared to tread. Now, however, as a result of the Human Rights Act and the anti-terrorism legislation, Parliament has required—that word again—the judiciary to engage with that test. I shall return to the subject of new territory when I deal with proportionality later. Sixthly, in this and other respects, the courts are doing no more and no less than carrying out their constitutional function of interpreting and applying the law—in this case, the law enacted by Parliament. It is at this point that I have an addition to the draft which was circulated in advance. I do not know what Lord Falconer will be saying to you later this afternoon. However, I anticipate that it may resemble what he said in an excellent lecture which he gave in Australia last month under the title "The Role of Judges in a Modern Democracy". It is a valuable contribution to the subject, and I and other judges would agree with most of it. Where I disagree with him is in his characterisation of judicial power in this area as an exercise of discretion. Whilst some judicial decision-making is discretionary, decision-making in most of the controversial cases on human rights is not. For example, whether a domestic statute is Convention-compliant, whether the terms of a control order amount to a lawful restriction of liberty or an unlawful deprivation of liberty, whether detention without trial of foreign terrorism suspects is disproportionate and/or discriminatory, whether the denial of asylum support to an applicant for asylum pending the determination of his claim amounts to inhuman and degrading treatment, are all issues requiring judicial decision by the application of the law to the facts of the case. That is a matter of judgment according to the law, not discretion. This is not just a lawyer's semantic quibble. The suggestion or implication that discretion is in play when in fact it is not tends to fuel the misconception that judges are somehow choosing to adopt an anti-Government line when, by being a little more "discreet", they could decide the same case more favourably to the Government. That is not so and, accordingly, I respectfully take issue with Lord Falconer's use of the word "discretion". Seventhly, the courts are not adopting a gung-ho approach, so when considering the question of "a public emergency threatening the life of the nation" in A, the majority of the Judicial Committee of the House of Lords made it clear that, whilst the legislation requires the courts to review a derogation on such a subject involving national security, they will show great deference to the political decision-makers. Similarly, in immigration law, when considering whether removal from the United Kingdom will contravene a person's rights under Article 8, the issue of proportionality is approached on the basis that our domestic law is the primary evidence of what is proportionate and it is only in "truly exceptional" cases that a person will be able to rely successfully on Article 8. One sees a similar approach in cases where successful reliance on other Articles has been limited to "flagrant" breaches. I believe these examples—and there are many others—are more illustrative of self-restraint on the part of the judiciary than the sort of militant activism that is sometimes caricatured in the media. Much of what I wanted to say and to emphasise is contained in those seven general observations. I hope that they also deal with some of the questions you have raised. I shall now try to answer some of them in a little more detail. Proportionality is an issue raised by you. Domestic judicial review has traditionally been limited to considerations of illegality, irrationality and procedural impropriety. The interference with Convention rights often has to be tested for its proportionality. Although the application of the domestic test of irrationality (or the Wednesbury test, as it is often called) will often produce the same result as the proportionality test, the tests are not the same. Proportionality can require the judge to come to his own view of, for example, the least intrusive solution rather than simply asking whether a decision-maker has reached one of a number of permissible decisions. This is a more interventionist approach. It is what the law requires. It was explained by Lord Steyn in the Daly case but it has taken time for everybody to adjust to it. So, for example, immigration adjudicators continued to apply the Wednesbury test to decisions of the Home Secretary in Article 8 cases before the House of Lords and the Court of Appeal reminded them to make their own decisions, albeit against the "truly exceptional" criterion. The proportionality test calls for a novel judicial technique but its demands vary according to the subject matter. We recognise those areas which, in Lord Bingham's words, lie more at the political than the judicial end of the spectrum. Thus, whilst we are deferential novices on issues of national security, we can draw on centuries of experience in relation to the protection of individual liberty. Next, the judicialisation of decision-making. Section 6 of the Human Rights Act makes it unlawful for a public authority, including a court or tribunal, to act in a way which is incompatible with a Convention right. To the extent that the decisions of public officials are now reviewable not only on domestic public law grounds but also by reference to Convention rights, decision-makers are more constrained. Decisions are more susceptible to litigation. However, it cannot be said that the courts have been inundated with arguable human rights cases. In many cases, human rights grounds are simply added to traditional grounds and quite often both succeed or both fail. Statistics are distorted by the fact that large numbers of unrepresented litigants often think, quite unrealistically, that the Human Rights Act is the answer to all their prayers. On the other hand, there are undoubtedly areas in which the Act has transformed decision-making. A good example is in relation to parole and minimum terms of imprisonment but the previous politicisation of decision-making in that area was never justifiable by international standards or elementary considerations of the separation of powers. Unfortunately, almost any issue relating to the sentencing and release of prisoners attracts more heat than light. If decision-makers have sometimes been over-anxious about the impact of the Human Rights Act upon their decisions, I do not think that actual judicial decisions can be said to have caused that over-anxiety, if indeed it exists. Privacy: you have asked me to comment on the relationship between privacy in Article 8 and freedom of expression in Article 10. That the Act is having an impact is obvious. It was bound to, in view of the previous under-development of the English law of privacy. This is an area in which I have little experience. Obviously, it is a matter of balance. Both interests have had their successes. Judges are well versed in the balancing of competing interests. At the moment, I have no more to say on this subject. I would like to complete this opening statement with two unrelated observations. The first is that the legal landscape has been significantly changed by the Human Rights Act. The judiciary received admirable training in preparation for their work under the Act. Even so, the work involves much that is novel and difficult. Perhaps the difficulties can be appreciated by noting the unusual number of cases in which the House of Lords has been divided or has overturned decisions of the Court of Appeal. There are many marginal cases. I believe that history will give credit to the judiciary for the careful and restrained way in which it has dealt with the legislation. But for the events of 9/11, the process would probably have been more leisurely and gradual. However, subsequent legislation had obvious and dramatic human rights implications and we have had to adapt quickly in very difficult circumstances. To those who are critical of the decisions in the leading cases I pose the question: do you consider it likely that the decisions would have been different if the issues had been litigated in Strasbourg rather than in our domestic courts? Secondly, and finally, I would like to pay tribute to the way in which the legal profession has responded to the challenge. The expertise of many of those who represent claimants and defendants has been a great resource. It should also be remembered that much of the litigation is financed on both sides by public funds. I am not alone in regretting the erosion of Legal Aid. However, it is a matter for satisfaction that, notwithstanding the cuts, in this country the state still provides more funding for litigation against central government and other public authorities than is available in any comparable country. That is how the professional expertise has been able to develop and to assist the courts in cutting-edge cases.

  Q68  Mr Beith: Thank you very much indeed for that very clear and quite forthright opening statement. If I can just put one question to you to start with, how, as a judge, would you set out the answer to the conundrum as it is put by Ministers sometimes and frequently in the media that in some way the rights of a suspected terrorist are being placed above the rights of the public to safety because of the operation of the Act? I put that in very general terms but really, what I am interested in is how the legal answer to that is best defined.

  Lord Justice Kay: The answer really requires a perusal of the decisions in the two or three leading cases which have dealt with that issue. On any basis, it is an extremely difficult issue. If one looks at the Belmarsh detainees case, one sees that on the first issue, has the threshold been crossed to enable the Government to derogate from the Convention, there is on the part of the majority of the law lords a total sympathy with the predicament of the Government and a substantial deference to their interpretation of the need. When it comes to the second stage, derogation is permissible but what about this particular enactment and the way in which it is being used, it seems to me there were factors in play in connection with the detention without trial of foreign—emphasize foreign—terrorist suspects, which led to what I believe was an inevitable judicial conclusion both in relation to discrimination and in relation to proportionality. It is not a case of putting terrorists' rights above something else; it is a question of analysing in detail the points that are in play and coming to a decision against the background of the law, in this case the law as set out in the European Convention on Human Rights. It does not help, I think, in terms of presentation if one's recollection of the case is a snippet from one law lord or another which may have been individualised and was not in reality the reason for the decision of the majority. It seems to me really, simply as an informed person, reading in the media the coverage of what went on in the A case, that the media were very often more interested in what Lord Hoffmann said at the end of his speech, expressing an opinion about threats to the security of the nation, than they were about what Lord Bingham and the majority said about the true reason underlying the decision, because it is a fact that Lord Hoffmann was in fact deciding the case on a slightly different basis from all the others, but that is what caught the media eye, perhaps because of Lord Hoffmann's particular gift of self-expression. That is my answer as far as the Belmarsh case is concerned, that there were technical, subtle, complex issues in play which received careful, erudite analysis and I think if anybody reads the speeches of the law lords, they will see that it is not a case of predisposition, it is not a case of favouring one assumption or another; it is a case of careful legal analysis. Subsequently, when they have dealt, for example, with the case of admissibility of evidence procured abroad by torture, they decided that case both on human rights grounds and domestic law. The decision would have been exactly the same if we had never enacted the Human Rights Act; in fact, the more robust passages in the law lords' judgments relate to the common law rather than the Human Rights Act. When one comes to the subsequent control orders case, I am not sure to what extent this is still ongoing litigation. It has been to the Court of Appeal; I do not know whether it is on the way to the House of Lords, but that, I think, is probably a case where it might have been a more marginal decision for a judge to have to make, for this reason: the central issue is whether the terms of the particular control orders amounted to simply a restriction of the liberty of the people who were being controlled or whether they were a deprivation of their liberty, such was the quantum of the restrictions. That is an evaluative decision. It is not one I had to make. One knows from the Strasbourg jurisprudence that it provided a steer at both ends of the spectrum, but it was relatively unhelpful in the middle ground, and this case may have been said to be in the middle ground. It was carefully resolved by one judge in the High Court, by three judges in the Court of Appeal and they all came to the same conclusion. I would again say that they did so on the basis of detailed analysis of the facts in the case and the legal provisions which they had to apply.

  Q69  Mr Streeter: You said in your evidence "We recognise those areas which, in Lord Bingham's words, lie more at the political than the judicial end of the spectrum." Of course, in your case I accept that is completely the case, but is it not also the case that there are some members of the bench who actually have very little respect for the political will of the people of this country as expressed at the ballot box and are itching to give Parliament a bloody nose whenever they can? Do you really think that everyone has recognised these areas and does indulge in judicial deference?

  Lord Justice Kay: What I do not recognise is the member of the bench or members of the bench that you are seeking there to portray. I have never met a judge who is itching to get at Parliament or the Government, whether this Government or any previous Government. The answer is simply no. As far as this kind of work is concerned, the first instance decision of public law cases in our jurisdiction is handled almost entirely by the Administrative Court. The Administrative Court is staffed by hand-picked judges from among the High Court judges, and mainly from one particular division of the High Court judges. They are selected because they are thought to be people with the expertise and the stature and the necessary feel for the interface of government and the judiciary such that they can be trusted with that kind of work. I would personally resist any suggestion that, either in their selection or in the discharge of their duties, they act in the kind of way that you are there describing.

  Q70  Jeremy Wright: Can I ask you about declarations of incompatibility? Professor Klug, who sits behind you, spoke to us earlier on this morning and I think you and she were in agreement that there is no strike-down power for the judiciary on primary legislation, but her analysis was that the matter might still be litigated in Strasbourg even if it could not be litigated here. The parties may then go on to Strasbourg to argue about particular primary legislation. The argument for the Human Rights Act was that it would bring rights home, that it would incorporate that area of rights law into British law so that people would not have to go to Strasbourg. Is there a flaw in the system of declarations of incompatibility and what, in your view, are the merits of declarations of incompatibility?

  Lord Justice Kay: I think the conceptual apparatus within which they may be made was ingenious and went as far as it possibly could to square the circle of the Convention and parliamentary sovereignty. So far, there have been relatively few declarations of incompatibility. The statutory consequence of a declaration is that it may or may not lead to amending legislation. I rather gather from Lord Falconer's Australian lecture that he is entirely satisfied with the way in which declarations of incompatibility are working and the way in which Parliament is responding when declarations are made. They are, as it turns out, a relatively small part of the impact of the Human Rights Act.

  Q71  Mr Beith: I wonder if you could just explain that statement, because you imply by that that much of its impact is extra-judicial, in which case it is slightly worrying.

  Lord Justice Kay: No, I did not mean to give that impression. Of the many cases that have been decided under the Human Rights Act, a handful concern declarations of incompatibility. I cannot remember what the present figure but I think it is still at around eight, nine or 10 such cases where such declarations have been made, and a number of those have been small, relatively technical, procedural points that would not even raise a half-inch column space on page 8 of a newspaper. Although they have arisen in one or two of the big cases as well, they are not the daily feedstuff of the judicial use of the Human Rights Act. We decide cases every day of the week applying Convention law without the need to make a declaration of incompatibility. It is very much the exception rather than the rule and, when we have made the declarations, they have, so far as I know, always been graciously received by the Government and Parliament and amendments have been made. It is true that the matters can still be litigated in Strasbourg by aggrieved people. I have a view about one aspect of what you said and that is to do with the presentation of the Human Rights Act when it was in the form of a bill and when it was going through Parliament. It was to some extent presented as merely relocating the place of litigation and therefore giving easier access, saving people the journey to Strasbourg and so on. Whilst it has that advantage, very conspicuous advantage, the Human Rights Act was about far more than that, and it did far more, clearly, and, it would seem to me, inevitably intentionally, in a considered way, to give new tasks to our judges which they have not had before in quite that form. The whole idea that it was a rather cosmetic, logistical thing without any potential to—I will not say rock the constitutional boat but at least cause the occasional ripple I think was perhaps not a very full idea.

  Q72  Mr Denham: In the Canberra lecture that the Lord Chancellor gave that you have referred to, he set out the principle that it was the job of the executive to set out the strategy for combating terrorism, that it was the job of the courts to determine whether individual actions were lawful. In the three elements of terrorism cases that you have touched on yourself, Belmarsh detention, deportation and control orders, the courts by a series of separate leading decisions effectively removed three planks of the Government's counter-terrorism strategy, leaving it with a relatively small space for manoeuvre. Is that a problem if we actually start from the principle that it is the executive's job to determine the counter-terrorism strategy, if the courts, taking quite separate decisions, actually unpick what the Government regarded as key elements in that strategy, even though each of those may be legally absolutely the right decision?

  Lord Justice Kay: The answer is that, the torture one apart, if we were living post 9/11 but without the Human Rights Act, there would not have been judicial decisions of the kind that you are referring to in those crucial cases. There are judicial decisions to that effect now because of the Human Rights Act. Question: did the law lords in two of them and the Court of Appeal in the other take an eccentric or expansionist or particularly radical view of the Human Rights Act and the Convention? Answer: in my judgment, no. They took what was a fairly predictably straightforward view of that Act and the Convention. That is why, when this question is posed, I pose the question rhetorically in reply that I did in my short presentation. Do you think for one moment, if the matter had been litigated in Strasbourg, that the Belmarsh case would have been decided any differently? Personally, I would be astonished if it had been. Ditto the torture case.

  Q73  Mr Denham: Some of us who are parliamentarians who took part in consideration of the legislation that underlay the Belmarsh decision and then the control orders decision may have had the expectation that the fact that Parliament had considered these matters very seriously and at great length would have been given perhaps more weight than it appeared to have been by the courts when they came to determine these matters. Were parliamentarians unrealistic in the amount of weight that they expected the courts to give to a decision where not only had the government and the executive taken a decision but Parliament itself had agonised very long and hard over these issues?

  Lord Justice Kay: We are talking about questions of law ultimately and the best analysts of law are people who are trained in law. My suspicion—I put it no higher than that—is that parliamentary expectations might well have been pitched too high, at least as far as the first round was concerned. Certainly I think that in the torture case, it was never the case that Parliament...

  Q74  Mr Denham: That is the one where Parliament has not actually legislated.

  Lord Justice Kay: So we can leave that one aside. The control orders one I would say, as I said before, is a little more marginal. Restrictions come at a point on the continuum where, at the very least, if deployed in that particular way, they were at risk of that particular result. It is not, in my view, as clear a case as the other cases we have talked about but I say no more in case the final word has yet to be spoken by the House of Lords.

  Q75  Dr Whitehead: Could I raise some thoughts about your thoughts on proportionality. The points I think you made very firmly in your remarks relate to the idea that, as far as proportionality is concerned, by which I assume we are talking about proportionality in terms of qualified rights which can be restricted, you have pointed out that a judge has to come to his own view of the least intrusive solution, a more interventionist approach, and you have stated that that calls for a novel judicial technique. My concern is that perhaps that might be recast in terms of not just a novel judicial technique in terms of having to come to one's own view but also come to a view about one of the two sides against which proportionality has to be judged, namely the rights or the interests of society. I note that you have also stated that judges, you say, can draw on centuries of experience in relation to protection of individual liberty. The missing dots at the end, as it were, might suggest the protection of individual liberty against the state, but the interests of the community to some extent are defined by the state, so is it not the case that actually, there is one area of the two poles against which proportionality might be judged which is not defined whereas there is one other area that is defined and that in itself gives an additional area of problem as far as judicial interpretation is concerned?

  Lord Justice Kay: It is a balancing exercise, and it is a balancing exercise where one considers the full range of consequences for the state, for society, for the individual. I see no difficulty in that as a task. There is, I suppose, a natural reaction on the part of government to be disappointed when the striking of the balance is not precisely where they would have hoped that it might be. That part is not particularly difficult to do, provided that all things are properly taken into account. One thing you can be sure of, as I address at the end of my opening statement: in the big cases the level of legal representation on both sides is so abundantly talented that every conceivable matter is addressed and considered before a decision is made.

  Q76  Dr Whitehead: Is it not the case though that what one might define as the rights of the community are themselves very ill-defined and therefore are subject to an additional or necessary interpretation over and above the actual interpretation that, as you have pointed out, is the decision that the judge is required to take?

  Lord Justice Kay: I do not know what to give you as an example. Perhaps from immigration. There is a deep, established acceptance that the state has an interest in the control of immigration and in keeping it fair. There is an acknowledgement that if you deport somebody and thereby split a family, that person has Article 8 rights that are in play but, for the reasons that I mention briefly in the paper, we know how the state has prioritised the striking of the balance by the provisions of the immigration legislation and the immigration rules and the policy statements that are made. They serve as a starting point. That is why the courts in that situation will treat them not just as a starting point but go to the other end and say it requires a truly exceptional case for a deportation to be stopped in the private interest of the person whose Article 8 right has been engaged. I think that rather illustrates the balance and the way in which courts go about identifying the factors and weighing them. It is difficult to superimpose on that some additional unformulated community interest over and above the specific interests that have to be identified for carrying out the proportionality exercise. It may be expressed in vague language because it is universal, it applies in all situations, but when it has to be applied in a particular case, it is very necessary to see what the particular aim is of the particular provision or decision, whether that is in accordance with the law, whether it is a legitimate aim, all that on the side of the government, so to speak, and what the particular interest is that is being affected or potentially affected by the policy or its operation. It is only when you get down to the individual case, I think, that you can be sufficiently specific about the competing interests to enable you to make the decision that strikes the balance. As it happens, I would have thought that, standing back, looking at the thousands of cases that have been decided under the Human Rights Act where proportionality is in issue, in the overwhelming majority the individual has lost, not won.

  Q77  James Brokenshire: Lord Justice Kay, you have made clear in your statement that you take issue with the Lord Chancellor's interpretation or reflection on the approach of the judiciary when examining this particular area in suggesting it is an exercise of discretion. Obviously, in the session thus far we have heard of the different approach that has been taken, albeit that you would characterise that more as interventionist or a change in emphasis of the law-making style and the application of the law in that particular manner. In raising it, you clearly see this as a matter of concern. To what extent should it be a concern for us and what do you see as the implications of that apparent disconnect or misunderstanding of the approach the judiciary has actually been taking?

  Lord Justice Kay: First of all, I do not want to be misunderstood about any area of disagreement I have with the Lord Chancellor. It arises solely about his use of the word "discretion" repeatedly in that lecture. So far as I know, the Lord Chancellor is not critical of any of the judicial decisions that have actually been made. I am simply expressing a different view about the conceptual and analytical tools that we use in our decision-making process. Could you reformulate the second part of the question or the main part of the question, because I do not think I followed it.

  Q78  James Brokenshire: The aspect that that leads on to is that if there is this misunderstanding, if I can put it in those terms, between the judicial tools that you are using and the Lord Chancellor's interpretation of that in his comments on the word "discretion", do you see that as a point of concern and, if so, what would the implications of that be?

  Lord Justice Kay: Obviously, as judges, we want people to evaluate our decisions on the basis upon which we have constructed them. If one introduces the language of "discretion", it makes it sound as though there was really a rather wider choice as to what the outcome of the case should have been, and "If only the judges had paused for a few moments longer, they would have found a way of agreeing with us rather than disagreeing with us." There is a danger if it is presented in that way, if that is not the basis upon which a case is decided. If there is one message that I think all judges would wish to get across in these cases, very difficult and complex as they are, it is that we are applying the law, and in particular the law enacted by Parliament, and we are not engaged on some discretionary frolic of our own, pitching things where we think they ought to be pitched.

  Q79  Mr Beith: But is not judicial deference a form of discretion in that you are making the decision—as you said, judges do not know a lot about national security, you do know about liberty, so you will back off slightly when the state is making a judgment about national security. Is that not a form of discretion?

  Lord Justice Kay: I think it is only discretion in the sense that some people use almost all decision-making as an exercise of discretion. It is a problem judges have all the time, not just with the Human Rights Act and in public law cases. Lawyers are for ever addressing courts in private law cases on the basis of the judge has a discretion for this, that and the other. Sometimes we do, but very often when they are talking about discretion it is not a discretion at all; it is a question of identifying the law and applying it to the facts. There is a discretion in the Human Rights Act. There is a discretion over, for example, declarations of incompatibility. There is no discretion in deciding whether or not a piece of legislation is compliant and compatible; that is a matter of law, but if you then have to decide whether to go on to make a declaration of incompatibility, there is a discretion because the Act says "the court may" and that is a discretionary matter. I certainly have sat on one case where that was the only issue in the case. The Government was accepting incompatibility; it was inviting the court not to make the declaration on the basis that they were attending to it anyway and there was no need.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2007
Prepared 3 May 2007