Select Committee on Environmental Audit Minutes of Evidence


Memorandum submitted by Richard Starkey, The Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research, University of Manchester

INTRODUCTION

  1.  Since July 2003, Dr Kevin Anderson and I (both of the Tyndall Centre, University of Manchester) have been assessing the feasibility and appropriateness of implementing a Domestic Tradable Quotas (DTQs) scheme.

  2.  In December 2005, Dr Anderson and I published a detailed report on DTQs (Starkey and Anderson, 2005).[3] This report (henceforth "the Tyndall DTQs report") has been submitted to the Committee in evidence.

  3.  This memorandum briefly describes the DTQs scheme and then discusses issues of equity not fully addressed in the Tyndall DTQs report but relevant to the public acceptability and therefore the viability of a DTQs scheme. It is submitted in a personal capacity.

BRIEF DESCRIPTION OF DTQS

  4.  DTQs were formulated by Dr David Fleming who first published the idea in 1996 (Fleming, 1996). Dr Fleming maintains a website[4] and his most recent publication is Fleming (2005).

  5.  DTQs are a "cap and trade" scheme for the reduction of greenhouse gas emissions from energy use under which emissions rights are allocated to and surrendered by all end-purchasers of fuel and electricity (both individuals and organizations). The DTQs scheme can be divided into three elements: (1) setting the carbon budget (2) the surrender of carbon units and (3) acquiring carbon units for surrender.

Setting the carbon budget

  6.  The carbon budget is the maximum quantity of greenhouse gases that may be emitted from energy use in a given year. Under DTQs, the carbon budget is reduced year on year in line with national and international emissions reduction targets. Fleming has proposed that, in any given year of the scheme, carbon budgets should be set 20 years ahead, so as to provide a long-term emissions reduction signal to society. He further proposes that carbon budgets are set by an expert independent Carbon Policy Committee, a proposal designed to de-politicize budget setting in same the way that the Bank of England's Monetary Policy Committee is intended to depoliticize the setting of interest rates.

Surrendering carbon units

  7.  A carbon unit is an emissions right, specifically the right to emit 1 kg of carbon dioxide equivalent. All fuels and electricity are assigned a carbon rating based on the quantity of greenhouse gases (measured in carbon units) emitted by the combustion of a unit of each fuel and by the generation of a unit of electricity. Whenever individuals and organizations purchase fuel or electricity, they are required to surrender to the retailer carbon units to cover the quantity of fuel or electricity purchased. For accounting purposes, these units are surrendered up the supply chain and, on reaching the primary energy producer or the energy importer, are passed back to government.

Acquiring units for surrender

  8.  Each year a quantity of carbon units equivalent to that year's carbon budget are allocated by government to individuals and organizations. The proportion of total carbon units allocated to individuals is equal to the proportion of total energy emissions arising from individuals' purchase of fuel and electricity over a given period prior to the introduction of the DTQs scheme. (In the UK, the proportion is currently around 40%.) Carbon units are allocated to adult individuals free and on an equal per capita basis.

  9.  Whilst individuals receive their units for free, organizations must purchase the units they require on a national carbon market. Units enter onto the market from two sources. First, government auctions onto the market those units not allocated to individuals. Second, individuals who emit at a level below that permitted by their allocation, and who have, thus, not surrendered all their units, can sell their surplus units onto the market. Conversely individuals who wish to emit at a level above that permitted by their initial allocation ("above-allocation individuals") must buy additional units on the market. Visitors to the UK are not allocated units and so along with organizations and above-allocation individuals, must purchase them on the market.

ASSESSING DTQS

  10.  In the course of our research we have encountered three main objections to DTQs.

    (i)  Allocating emissions rights on an equal per capita basis is not equitable.

    (ii)  Allocating emissions rights on an equal per capita basis is equitable and therefore 100% of emissions rights, rather than the approximately 40% under DTQs, should be allocated to individuals on an equal per capita basis.

    (iii)  Allocating emissions rights on an equal per capita basis is equitable, but other instruments can achieve this allocation more cost-effectively than DTQs.

  11.  Objections (ii) and (iii) and responses to them are discussed at length in the Tyndall DTQs report and hence this memorandum focuses on objection (i).

FAIRNESS OF AN EQUAL PER CAPITA ALLOCATION

  12.  In exploring the equity (or fairness) of an equal per capita allocation of emissions rights (henceforth "EPCA"), I put forward an argument for fairness that finds some support within the philosophical literature on distributive justice. I contrast this with the main argument for the fairness of EPCA found within what might be termed the "non philosophical" literature (ie writings that do not explicitly draw on the distributive justice literature). Though somewhat academic in parts, the discussion is relevant to the public acceptability and, thus, the viability of a DTQs scheme.[5]

  13.  Within the non-philosophical literature:

    The central argument for equal per capita rights is that the atmosphere is a global commons, whose use and preservation are essential to human well being (Baer, 2002, p401).

  14.  Used in this sense, the term "commons" refers to something that has, since the beginning of humanity, been owned jointly and equally by humanity. And if the atmosphere is jointly and equally owned, it follows that all of humanity should have the right to emit equally into it.

  15.  However, within the philosophical literature, it is disputed that the atmosphere is a commons in this sense. It is held by a number of philosophers, both on the left and the right politically, that, in fact, nature was, in the beginning, unowned and that, over time, various parts of nature have been taken into ownership by individuals acting upon them in an appropriate manner. It is further held by some philosophers that the part of nature which is the atmosphere is incapable of being taken into ownership in the way that, for example, fossil fuel can be, and that the atmosphere is therefore not only unowned by unownable. For instance, Schmidtz (1997, pp43-4) argues that there is:

    no foreseeable prospect of being able to privatize the air ... [as] it is difficult to parcel out ...

  16.  Given that fossil fuel is something that can, uncontroversially, be owned, is it the case that, in a fair society, individuals would be entitled to equal quantities of fossil fuel, and thus emissions rights? If so, then we would have an argument for EPCA that did not require an endorsement of the (philosophically contested) claim that that the atmosphere is a commons.

  17.  Such an equal sharing out of fossil fuel would be an example of the norm of "equality of resources". However, this is not a norm that has been endorsed by most egalitarian liberal philosophers:[6]

    The norm of equality of resources stipulates that to achieve equality ... everybody [should receive] a share of goods that is exactly identical to everyone else's and that exhausts all available resources to be distributed. A straightforward objection to equality of resources so understood is that if Smith and Jones have similar tastes and abilities except that Smith has a severe handicap remediable with the help of expensive crutches, then if the two are accorded equal resources, Smith must spend the bulk of his resources on crutches whereas Jones can use his resource share to fulfil his aims to a far greater extent. It seems forced to claim that any notion of equality of condition that is worth caring about prevails between Smith and Jones (Arneson, 1989, p77-8).

  18.  Most egalitarian liberals also reject the notion that "equality of condition" is achieved by equalizing welfare.

    Equality of welfare is a poor ideal. Individuals can arrive at different welfare levels due to choices they make for which they alone should be held responsible. A simple example would be to imagine two persons of identical tastes and abilities who are assigned equal resources by an agency charged to maintain distributive equality. The two then engage in high-stakes gambling, from which one emerges rich (with high expectation of welfare) and the other poor (with low welfare expectation). In [this] example ... it would be inappropriate to insist on equality of welfare when welfare inequality arises through voluntary choice of the person who gets less welfare (Arneson, 1989, p83-4).

  19.  In place of equalizing welfare, Arneson therefore suggests that what should be equalized is, in fact, "opportunity for welfare".[7] (In his example in the previous paragraph, the two persons are provided with resources that give them equal opportunity for welfare. However, instead of realizing this opportunity by consuming these resources, they decide to gamble with them.)

  20.  Arneson argues that equalizing resources can lead to inequality in opportunity for welfare. Conversely, providing individuals with equal opportunity for welfare is likely to entail providing them with entitlements to unequal amounts of resources. For instance, people who live in colder regions may require more energy for heating. Or, as life in the countryside requires more travelling, people living there may require more energy for transport. (Indeed, one might even argue that people who feel the cold may require more energy for heating than people who generate lots of body heat!) And, if fossil fuel energy comprises the same proportion of each individual's energy use, then an entitlement to differing quantities of energy translates into an entitlement to differing quantities of fossil fuel and, thus, emissions rights.

  21.  This sort of argument was been made in relation to the allocation of emissions rights between nations. For example, Raymond (2006, p656-7) takes the view that:

    the more one considers the equal per capita argument, the harder it is to shake certain reservations about the idea... Does a poor writer living in a garret in St Petersburg, for example, have the same entitlement to the atmosphere as one living in San Diego, or do the cold Russian winters (heating being a major source of GHG emissions) merit additional consideration? What about the rancher living in eastern Montana, 40 miles from the nearest school or hospital, versus the resident of Tokyo? The problem is that once one begins unpacking the apparent equality of the per capita right, it becomes clear that it creates significant inequalities based on criteria—warm versus cold climate, rural versus urban dwelling—that look morally arbitrary. Tailoring the allocation principle to adjust for these various mitigating factors, however, again threatens to undermine its initial advantages of clarity and simplicity as a basic human right.

  22.  This sort of argument has also been made with regard to DTQs (a proposal for the allocation of emissions rights within nations). For example, commenting on a recent blog posted by the Secretary of State for Environment, Food and Rural Affairs on DTQs (Miliband, 2006), one respondent (Harry Manuel) argued (echoing Arneson) that those with a disability may require additional emissions rights:[8]

    Will everyone get the same fixed amount, if so this is unfair on those with disability etc, who have a greater reliance on mechanical/electrical aids?[9]

  23.  Mrs Thatcher's former Press Secretary, Bernard Ingham (2006), also responded to the Secretary of State in an article in his local paper, describing DTQs as:

    A perfect wheeze for champagne socialists, but egalitarian, my foot. Nor is there anything fair about a single carbon allowance, bearing in mind the differing needs of the elderly, families with young children, the disabled and those who live in the country who simply have to have a vehicle.

  24.  Faced with the charge that equality of opportunity for welfare requires something other than the EPCA of DTQs, what defence can the supporter of DTQs mount? Of course, the supporter can reject egalitarian liberal arguments in favour of the commons argument. However, I think that the supporter of DTQs can, in fact, mount a defence that accords with the egalitarian liberal approach. And that defence is that an equal per capita allocation is fair if it is the closest affordable approximation to the allocation of emissions rights that would pertain under equal opportunity for welfare.

  25.  Imagine a society implementing equal opportunity for welfare with regard to energy use. Prior to implementation, everyone starts with an equal allocation of energy. It is then calculated what adjustments would need to be made to take account of the various factors affecting opportunity for welfare such as the temperature, whether people live in the town or in the country, the energy efficiency of dwellings, the extent to which people feel the cold and so forth. These adjustments result in individuals being allocated differing quantities of energy. And, as fossil fuel energy comprises the same proportion of each individual's energy use, individuals are therefore entitled to differing quantities of fossil fuel and, thus, emissions rights.

  26.  In this example, a fair allocation of emissions rights arises from the fair allocation of energy. By contrast, climate change policy, when considering issues of fairness, is concerned not to allocate energy fairly, but only emissions rights.[10] But, in a situation (like today) where energy is not allocated fairly, the fair allocation of emissions rights can be established only by determining the allocation that would arise if energy were to be allocated fairly.

  27.  This fair allocation of emissions rights can in theory be established by everyone starting with an equal allocation. The same adjustments (for temperature, town/country etc) would then made to this allocation as would be made to the equal allocation of energy if one were setting out (as in the example in paragraph 25) to allocate energy so as to bring about equal opportunity for welfare.

  28.  However, in practice it may simply be too administratively burdensome and expensive to collect the information on individuals necessary to make such adjustments (see following examples). If so, the closest affordable approximation to a fair allocation of emissions rights (ie that which would pertain under equal opportunity for welfare) is to stick with the pre-adjusted, equal per capita allocation.

  29.  The following are two examples of the expense involved in collecting "adjustment information":

    (1)  There would be a significant administrative burden and expense to classifying each dwelling according to average temperature and tracking individuals' moves between dwellings so as to accurately adjust their allocation of emissions rights.

    (2)  Whilst it is probably feasible to assess how rural/urban each of a nation's dwellings is, this would not accurately reveal how much travel a person required to live their life. For whilst rural life might on average require more travel than urban living, some urban dwellers may have to travel significant distances (eg to work) putting them above the rural average. Hence, obtaining accurate data on the amount of travel required by each individual to live their lives would be extremely expensive.

  30.  In making the closest affordable approximation argument, the supporter of DTQs would be arguing not that EPCA is the fairest allocation in theory, but simply that it is the fairest allocation in practice. And making this argument may be significant if government is minded to implement a DTQs scheme. For to argue that EPCA is absolutely fair may well invite a cacophony of objections such as those described above and diminish the public acceptability of the scheme. However, if it was argued that the equal per capita allocation was simply the fairest in practice, then the government would create a space in which to recognize the concerns of specific groups and could leave open the possibility of taking actions to accommodate their concerns. For instance, government could ensure that DTQs was implemented as part of a portfolio of measure to make certain that those on low incomes were not disadvantaged by the scheme.[11] The adoption by government of this "fairest-in-practice" approach, may therefore promote a greater acceptability of DTQs amongst the public.

REFERENCES

  Arneson, R (1989) Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, Philosophical Studies, 56, pp77-93.

  Baer, P (2002) Equity, Greenhouse Gas Emissions, and Global Common Resources. In Schneider, S, Rosencranz, A and Niles, J (eds) Climate Change Policy: A Survey pp393-408, Washington DC: Island Press.

  Fleming, D (1996) Stopping the Traffic, Country Life, vol 140, 19; 9 May, pp 62-65.

  Fleming, D (2005) Energy and the Common Purpose: Descending the Energy Staircase with Tradable Energy Quotas (TEQs), London: The Lean Economy Connection.

  Ingham, B (2006) Bring Me Sunshine, Hebden Bridge Times, 3 August .

  Miliband, D (2006) Carbon Allowances www.davidmiliband.defra.gov.uk/blogs/ministerial_blog/archive/2006/07/19/1557.aspx

  Raymond, L (2006) Cutting the "Gordian knot" in Climate Change Policy, Energy Policy 34, pp655-658.

  Schmidtz, D (1997) The Institution of Property. In Ladeur, K (ed) Liberal Institutions, Economic Constitutional Rights, and the Role of Organizations, Baden Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, pp31-51.

  Starkey, R and Anderson, K (2005) Domestic Tradable Quotas: A Policy Instrument for Reducing Greenhouse Gas Emissions from Energy Use, Tyndall Technical Paper 39 www.tyndall.ac.uk/research/theme2/final_reports/t3_22.pdf

July 2007






3   Available at www.tyndall.ac.uk/research/theme2/final_reports/t3_22.pdf Back

4   www.teqs.org Back

5   This work is ongoing and is presented here in provisional form to provide the Committee with an illustration of the research conducted at Tyndall Manchester since the publication of the Tyndall DTQs report. Back

6   The views of egalitarian liberals are important as they take a much more egalitarian approach to the distribution of resources than, for example, libertarian philosophers. Back

7   Other egalitarian liberal philosophers have suggested alternative formulations of what should be equalized but this does not affect the basic argument set out below. Back

8   This response (21 July) can be viewed on the webpage referenced in Miliband (2006). Back

9   Of course, it may be that a person with a disability is not able to travel much and so has low transport emissions. Back

10   It might be argued that the aim of policy is to graft a fair allocation of emissions rights onto today's less-than-fair allocation of energy! Back

11   See the Tyndall DTQs report, Section 3.4. Back


 
previous page contents next page

House of Commons home page Parliament home page House of Lords home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2008
Prepared 26 May 2008