Further written evidence submitted by
Article 19
INTRODUCTION
Defamation laws serve an important social purpose,
namely the protection of reputations or, put differently, the
prevention of unwarranted allegations that lower the esteem in
which people are held in society. For this interest to be engaged,
a statement tending to have this effect must be printed, broadcast,
spoken or otherwise communicated to others. As a result, defamation
laws necessarily represent an interference with the right to freedom
of expression. In many cases, this interference will be justified.
At the same time, international courts have often found that national
laws in this area are not justified, in particular because they
fail to promote an appropriate balance between the need to protect
reputations and the fundamental right to freedom of expression.
Defamation laws may fail to strike an appropriate
balance between freedom of expression and reputations for a number
of reasons. In some countries, defamation laws go beyond the legitimate
purpose of protecting individual reputations, broadly prohibiting
criticism of heads of State, foreign governments, the flag and/or
State symbols. Officials and other public figures are naturally
tempted to abuse defamation laws to silence their critics and,
in some countries, they have effectively muzzled debate and critical
voices by invoking harsh defamation laws. In others, the technicalities
of litigation and the cost of defending defamation actions serve
to chill free discussion on matters of public interest. Traditional
defences may offer inadequate protection for free speech in a
democracy, while excessively heavy sanctions may inhibit open
political debate.
In this paper, we argue that criminal defamation
laws inherently fail to strike an appropriate balance between
reputations and freedom of expression. Criminal defamation laws
are a major obstacle to freedom of expression in many parts of
the world. The key problem with criminal defamation is that a
breach may lead to a custodial sentence or another form of severe
criminal sanction, such as a suspension of the right to practise
journalism. The stigma of a criminal conviction can harm a journalist's
career long after the penalty has formally been discharged. The
threat of such sanctions casts a wide shadow as journalists and
other steer well clear of the prohibited zone to avoid any risk
of conviction. This can lead to serious problems of self-censorship,
stifling legitimate criticism of government and public officials.
This paper examines international standards
relating to freedom of expression generally and then in the particular
context of defamation laws, focusing mainly on the jurisprudence
of the European Court of Human Rights. These standards, as well
as comparative standards in this area, have been encapsulated
in the ARTICLE 19 publication, Defining Defamation: Principles
on Freedom of Expression and Protection of Reputations (Defining
Defamation) (see Annex One).[11]
These principles have attained significant international endorsement,
including by the three official mandates on freedom of expression,
the UN Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Opinion and Expression,
the OSCE Representative on Freedom of the Media and the OAS Special
Rapporteur on Freedom of Expression.[12]
The paper goes on to outline ARTICLE 19's key
concerns with criminal defamation laws, arguing that they often
fail to serve a legitimate aim, that they are disproportionate
to the harm caused and that they are not necessary as civil defamation
laws offer adequate redress for harm to reputation.
INTERNATIONAL STANDARDS
ON FREEDOM
OF EXPRESSION
Global Standards
Freedom of expression is a key human right,
in particular because of its fundamental role in underpinning
democracy. Article 19 of the Universal Declaration on Human
Rights (UDHR),[13]
a United Nations General Assembly resolution, guarantees the right
to freedom of expression in the following terms:
Everyone has the right to freedom of opinion
and expression; this right includes the right to hold opinions
without interference and to seek, receive and impart information
and ideas through any media regardless of frontiers.
The International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights (ICCPR)[14]
elaborates on many rights included in the UDHR, imposing formal
legal obligations on State Parties to respect its provisions.
Article 19 of the ICCPR guarantees the right to freedom of expression
in terms very similar to those found at Article 19 of the UDHR.
Freedom of expression is also protected in all
three regional human rights treaties, at Article 10 of the European
Convention on Human Rights (ECHR),[15]
at Article 13 of the American Convention on Human Rights[16]
and at Article 9 of the African Charter
on Human and Peoples' Rights.[17]
Freedom of expression is a key human right.
Not only is it a fundamental human value in and of itself, freedom
of expression also provides a key underpinning for democracythere
can be no democracy if people are not free to say what they want
and do not receive sufficient information to cast an informed
voteand it is key to enforcing other rights. This has been
recognised by international courts and bodies worldwide. It is
worth recalling that at its very first session, in 1946, the UN
General Assembly adopted Resolution 59(I) which states: "Freedom
of information is a fundamental human right and ... the touchstone
of all the freedoms to which the United Nations is consecrated."[18]
This has been echoed by other courts and bodies.
For example, the UN Human Rights Committee has said:
The right to freedom of expression is of paramount
importance in any democratic society.[19]
International law permits limited restrictions
on the right to freedom of expression in order to protect various
interests, including reputation. The parameters of such restrictions
are provided for in Article 19 of the ICCPR, which states:
The exercise of the rights provided for in paragraph
2 of this article carries with it special duties and responsibilities.
It may therefore be subject to certain restrictions, but these
shall only be such as are provided by law and are necessary:
(a) For respect of the rights or reputations
of others;
(b) For the protection of national
security or of public order (ordre public), or of public health
or morals.
Any restriction on the right to freedom of expression
must meet a strict three-part test. This test, which has been
confirmed by the Human Rights Committee,[20]
the body of independent experts responsible for overseeing States'
implementation of the ICCPR, requires that any restriction must
be:
(2) for the purpose of safeguarding a legitimate
interest (including, as noted, protecting the reputations of others);
and
(3) necessary to secure this interest.
The first part of this test implies not only
that the restriction is based in law, but also that the relevant
law meets certain standards of clarity and accessibility. The
law must be formulated with sufficient precision that it is possible
to foresee in advance what is being prohibited.[21]
Article 19(3) of the ICCPR provides an exclusive
list of aims in pursuit of which the exercise of the right to
freedom of expression may be restricted for purposes of the second
part of this test.
The necessity requirement set out in the third
part of the test implies, in particular, that the law should restrict
freedom of expression as little as possible, should be designed
carefully to achieve the objective in question and should not
be arbitrary, unfair or based on irrational considerations. Vague
or broadly defined restrictions, even if they satisfy the "provided
by law" part of the test, are unacceptable because, at least
potentially, they go beyond what is strictly required to protect
the legitimate interest. Furthermore, restrictions on freedom
of expression, must be proportionate to the harm done and not
go beyond what is strictly necessary in all of the circumstances
to protect reputation.
The European Convention on Human Rights
Freedom of expression is protected in Article
10(1) of the European Convention:
Everyone has the right to freedom of expression.
This right shall include freedom to hold opinions and to receive
and impart information and ideas without interference by public
authority and regardless of frontiers.
The European Court of Human Rights has recognised
the vital role of freedom of expression as an underpinning of
democracy:
Freedom of expression constitutes one of the essential
foundations of [a democratic] society, one of the basic conditions
for its progress and for the development of every man.[22]
The Court has also made it clear that the right
to freedom of expression protects offensive and insulting speech,
stating repeatedly:
[Freedom of expression] is applicable not only
to "information" or "ideas" that are favourably
received or regarded as inoffensive or as a matter of indifference,
but also to those that offend, shock or disturb the State or any
sector of the population. Such are the demands of pluralism, tolerance
and broadmindedness without which there is no "democratic
society".[23]
It has similarly emphasised: "Journalistic
freedom ... covers possible recourse to a degree of exaggeration,
or even provocation."[24]
This means, for example, that the media are free to use hyperbole,
satire or colourful imagery to convey a particular message.[25]
The choice as to the form of expression is up to the media. For
example, the Court will not criticise a newspaper for choosing
to voice its criticism in the form of a satirical cartoon andit
has urgedneither should national courts.[26]
The context within which statements are made is relevant as well.
For example, in the second Oberschlick case, the Court considered
that calling a politician an idiot was a legitimate response to
earlier, provocative statements by that same politician,[27]
while in the Lingens case, the Court stressed that the circumstances
in which the impugned statements had been made "must not
be overlooked".[28]
The Court attaches particular value to political
debate and deliberation on other matters of public importance.
Any statements made in the conduct of such debate can be restricted
only when this is absolutely necessary. As the Court has frequently
noted: "There is little scope ... for restrictions on political
speech or debates on questions of public interest".[29]
The guarantee of freedom of expression applies
with particular force to the media. The Court has consistently
emphasised the "pre-eminent role of the press in a State
governed by the rule of law"[30]
and has stated:
Freedom of the press affords the public one of
the best means of discovering and forming an opinion of the ideas
and attitudes of their political leaders. In particular, it gives
politicians the opportunity to reflect and comment on the preoccupations
of public opinion; it thus enables everyone to participate in
the free political debate which is at the very core of the concept
of a democratic society.[31]
Closely related, and as the Court has stressed
in nearly every case before it concerning the media:
The press plays an essential role in a democratic
society. Although it must not overstep certain bounds, in particular
in respect of the reputation and rights of others, its duty is
nevertheless to impartin a manner consistent with its obligations
and responsibilitiesinformation and ideas on all matters
of public interest. Not only does it have the task of imparting
such information and ideas, the public also has a right to receive
them. Were it otherwise, the press would be unable to play its
vital role of "public watchdog". [references omitted][32]
While the right to freedom of expression is
not absolute, any limitations must remain within strictly defined
parameters. Article 10(2) recognises that freedom of expression
may, in certain narrowly prescribed circumstances, be limited:
The exercise of these freedoms, since it carries
with it duties and responsibilities, may be subject to such formalities,
conditions, restrictions or penalties as are prescribed by law
and are necessary in a democratic society, in the interests of
national security, territorial integrity or public safety, for
the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health
or morals, for the protection of the reputation or rights of others,
for preventing the disclosure of information received in confidence,
or for maintaining the authority or impartiality of the judiciary.
This is quite similar in practice to the three-part
test for restrictions under the ICCPR.
DEFAMATION AND
THE ECHR
The European Court of Human Rights has decided
a large number of cases involving defamation. These cases establish
a number of principles on freedom of expression and defamation,
which are outlined below. These principles apply a fortiori
to criminal defamation laws, even though some of these cases
are based on civil defamation laws, given the more intrusive nature
of criminal defamation as a restriction on freedom of expression.[33]
It is well-established that defamation liability
constitutes an interference with freedom of expression, even when
no award for damages is made.[34]
As a result, defamation laws must remain within the parameters
set by the Convention and, in particular, must meet the three-part
test established under Article 10(2) of the Convention. In considering
these cases, the Court strictly follows the structure of Article
10(2).
The requirement that the restriction on the
ground of defamation be prescribed by law is usually found by
the Court to be easily met,[35]
even though some such laws are phrased, and interpreted by the
judicial organs, extremely loosely so that it is not possible
to determine in advance, even with the assistance of a legal expert,
what, exactly, is prohibited.
Legitimate Aim
As noted above, Article 10(2) of the Convention
provides an exclusive list of aims in pursuit of which the exercise
of the right to freedom of expression may be restricted. In virtually
all cases before the Court, the "protection of the reputation
or rights of others" has been invoked to justify defamation
laws.[36]
In one case, the Court also considered that the speech complained
of was potentially inflammatory and could lead to large-scale
public unrest. In those circumstances, the Court found that the
respondent Government could invoke the "prevention of disorder"
as a legitimate aim.[37]
ARTICLE 19 considers that the European Court has
devoted insufficient attention to the question of legitimate aim.
Although there is little doubt that defamation laws in almost
all cases do in general provide protection for reputation, in
many actual cases, we question whether this is the real aim of
the defamation action. Rather, it may be to prevent criticism
of government, to undermine an opposition party or to serve some
other aim unrelated to reputation. Given that the Court's mandate
is to consider the facts of the case before it, rather than the
law in general, it should look carefully at the facts to determine
whether the real aim of the case was to vindicate reputation.
Many defamation laws aim to protect honour and
dignity but, depending on how this is interpreted, it may be rather
different than reputation, which focuses on external perceptions
rather than internal feelings. Furthermore, laws that penalise
"insult" or "giving offence" without linking
this to the reputation of the offended party should fail the "legitimate
aim" test.
Public Officials
The Court has been very clear on the matter
of public officials and defamation: they are required to tolerate
more, not less, criticism, in part because of the public interest
in open debate about public figures and institutions. In its very
first defamation case, the Court emphasised:
The limits of acceptable criticism are ... wider
as regards a politician as such than as regards a private individual.
Unlike the latter, the former inevitably and knowingly lays himself
open to close scrutiny of his every word and deed by both journalists
and the public at large, and must consequently display a greater
degree of tolerance.[38]
The Court has affirmed this principle in several
cases and it has become a fundamental tenet of its caselaw.[39]
The principle is not limited to criticism of politicians acting
in their public capacity. Matters relating to private or business
interests can be equally relevant. For example, the "fact
that a politician is in a situation where his business and political
activities overlap may give rise to public discussion, even where,
strictly speaking, no problem of incompatibility of office under
domestic law arises".[40]
In statements on matters of public interest,
the principle applies to public officials and to public servants
as well as to politicians.[41]
Although in the case of Janowski v Poland, the Court held
that public servants must "enjoy public confidence in conditions
free of perturbation if they are to be successful in performing
their tasks," this case did not require the Court to balance
the interests of freedom of the media against need to protect
public servants and, importantly, did not concern statements in
the public interest. In the later case of Dalban v Romania,
the Court resolutely found a violation of freedom of expression
where a journalist had been conviction for defaming the chief
executive of a State-owned agricultural company.[42]
In the recent case of Thoma v Luxembourg, the Court put
the issue beyond doubt:
Civil servants acting in an official capacity are,
like politicians, subject to wider limits of acceptable criticism
than private individuals.[43]
Indeed, the Court has rejected any distinction
between political debate and other matters of public interest,
stating that there is "no warrant" for such distinction.[44]
The Court has also clarified that this enhanced protection applies
even where the person who is attacked is not a "public figure";
it is sufficient if the statement relates to a matter of public
interest.[45]
Facts vs Opinions
The Court has made it clear that defamation
law needs to distinguish between statements of fact and value
judgments. This is because the existence of facts can be demonstrated,
whereas the truth of a value judgment is not susceptible of proof.
It follows that: "The requirement to prove the truth of a
value judgment is impossible to fulfil and infringes freedom of
opinion itself, which is a fundamental part of the right to [freedom
of expression]."[46]
In a number of cases before the Court, domestic courts
had wrongly treated allegedly defamatory publications as statements
of fact. For example, in Feldek v Slovakia, the Court disagreed
that the use by the applicant of the phrase "fascist past"
should be understood as stating the fact that a person had participated
in activities propagating particular fascist ideals. It explained
that the term was a wide one, capable of encompassing different
notions as to its content and significance. One of them could
be that a person participated as a member in a fascist organisation;
on this basis, the value-judgment that that person had a "fascist
past" could fairly be made.[47]
The Defence of "Reasonable Publication"
It is now becoming widely recognised that in
certain circumstances even false, defamatory statements of fact
should be protected against liability. A rule of strict liability
for all false statements is particularly unfair for the media,
which are under a duty to satisfy the public's right to know where
matters of public concern are involved and often cannot wait until
they are sure that every fact alleged is true before they publish
or broadcast a story. Even the best journalists make honest mistakes
and to leave them open to punishment for every false allegation
would be to undermine the public interest in receiving timely
information. The nature of the news media is such that stories
have to be published when they are topical, particularly when
they concern matters of public interest. In response to a submission
to this effect by ARTICLE 19, the Court held:
[N]ews is a perishable commodity and to delay
its publication, even for a short period, may well deprive it
of all its value and interest.[48]
A more appropriate balance between the right
to freedom of expression and reputations is to protect those who
have acted reasonably in publishing a statement on a matter of
public concern, while allowing plaintiffs to sue those who have
not, what might be termed the defence of reasonable publication.
For the media, acting in accordance with accepted professional
standards should normally satisfy the reasonableness test. This
has been confirmed by the European Court, which has stated that
the press should be allowed to publish stories that are in the
public interest subject to the proviso that "they are acting
in good faith in order to provide accurate and reliable information
in accordance with the ethics of journalism."[49]
Applying these principles in the case of Troms'
and Stensaas v Norway, the European Court of Human Rights
placed great emphasis on the fact that the statements made in
that case concerned a matter of great public interest which the
plaintiff newspaper had covered overall in a balanced manner.[50]
Statements of Others
The European Court has also held that journalists
should not automatically be held liable for repeating a potentially
libellous allegation published by others. In the case of Thoma
v Luxembourg, a radio journalist had quoted from a newspaper
article which alleged that of all eighty forestry officials in
Luxembourg only one was not corrupt. The journalist was convicted
for libel but the European Court held that the conviction constituted
a violation of his right to freedom of expression: "[P]unishment
of a journalist for assisting in the dissemination of statements
made by another person | would seriously hamper the contribution
of the press to discussion of matters of public interest and should
not be envisaged unless there are particularly strong reasons
for doing so."[51]
The Court also dismissed the contention that the journalist should
have formally distanced himself from the allegation, warning the
public that he was quoting from a newspaper report: A general
requirement for journalists systematically and formally to distance
themselves from the content of a quotation that might insult or
provoke others or damage their reputation is not reconcilable
with the press's role of providing information on current events,
opinions and ideas.[52]
Exemptions from Liability
Certain statements should never attract liability
for defamation. This applies, for example, to statements made
in legislative assemblies or in the course of judicial proceedings,
or reports of official statements or reports quoting from the
findings of official reports.
With regard to statements made in legislative assemblies,
the European Court has recognised that, "[the] aim of the
immunity accorded to members of the ... legislature [is] to allow
such members to engage in meaningful debate and to represent their
constituents on matters of public interest without having to restrict
their observations or edit their opinions because of the danger
of being amenable to a court or other such authority."[53]
Thus, because freedom of parliamentary debate is the every essence
of modern-day democracies, statements made in Parliament may justifiably
attract absolute immunity.[54]
In the case of Nikula v Finland, the
Court held that statements made in the course of judicial proceedings
should enjoy a similarly high degree of protection.[55]
Statements made in court by lawyers should receive protection
in particular, since they play an important role as "intermediaries
between the public and the courts"[56]
and they must be free to defend their client to the best of their
ability. The Court explained:
[T]he threat of an ex post facto review of counsel's
criticism of another party to criminal proceedingswhich
the public prosecutor doubtless must be considered to beis
difficult to reconcile with defence counsel's duty to defend their
clients' interests zealously. It follows that it should be primarily
for counsel themselves, subject to supervision by the bench, to
assess the relevance and usefulness of a defence argument without
being influenced by the potential "chilling effect"
of even a relatively light criminal sanction or an obligation
to pay compensation for harm suffered or costs incurred.[57]
Sanctions
It is clear that unduly harsh sanctions, even
for statements found to be defamatory, breach the guarantee of
freedom of expression. In the case of Tolstoy Miloslavsky v
the United Kingdom, the European Court of Human Rights stated
that "the award of damages and the injunction clearly constitute
an interference with the exercise [of the] right to freedom of
expression."[58]
Therefore, any sanction imposed for defamation must bear a "reasonable
relationship of proportionality to the injury to reputation suffered"
and this should be specified in national defamation laws.[59]
Similarly, in a Declaration on Freedom of Political
Debate in the Media, the Committee of Ministers of the Council
of Europe stresses the need for sanctions both to be proportionate
and to take into account any other remedies provided:
Damages and fines for defamation or insult must
bear a reasonable relationship of proportionality to the violation
of the rights or reputation of others, taking into consideration
any possible effective and adequate voluntary remedies ....[60]
This is clearly of the greatest relevance to
criminal defamation.
One aspect of this requirement is that less
intrusive remedies, and in particular non-pecuniary remedies such
as appropriate rules on the right to reply, should be prioritised
over pecuniary remedies.[61]
Another aspect is that any remedies already provided, for example
on a voluntary or self-regulatory basis, should be taken into
account in assessing court-awarded damages. To the extent that
remedies already provided have mitigated the harm done, this should
result in a corresponding lessening of any pecuniary damages.
ARTICLE 19'S KEY
CONCERNS WITH
CRIMINAL DEFAMATION
The criminalisation of a particular activity
implies a clear State interest in controlling the activity and
imparts a certain social stigma to it. In many countries, the
protection of one's reputation is treated primarily or exclusively
as a private interest and experience shows that criminalising
defamatory statements is unnecessary to provide adequate protection
for reputations. Criminal defamation laws in many countries have
either fallen into disuse or their use has come under heavy criticism.
In Castells v Spain, the European Court of Human Rights
noted:
[T]he dominant position which the Government
occupies makes it necessary for it to display restraint in resorting
to criminal proceedings, particularly where other means are available
for replying to the unjustified attacks and criticisms of its
adversaries or the media.[62]
One of the most serious problems with criminal
defamation laws is that a breach may lead to a harsh sanction,
such as a heavy fine or suspension of the right to practise journalism.
Even where these are not applied, the problem of a "chilling
effect" remains, since the severe nature of these sanctions
means that they cast a long shadow. As noted above, is now well-established
that unduly harsh penalties, of themselves, represent a breach
of the right to freedom of expression even if the circumstances
justify some sanction for abuse of this right. In the very first
defamation case before it, the Court considered that:
the penalty imposed on the author ... amounted to
a kind of censure, which would be likely to discourage him from
making criticisms of that kind again in future ... In the context
of political debate such a sentence would be likely to deter journalists
from contributing to public discussion of issues affecting the
life of the community. By the same token, a sanction such as this
is liable to hamper the press in performing its task as purveyor
of information and public watchdog.[63]
A number of authoritative statements have been
made by various international officials to the effect that criminal
defamation laws and penalties breach the right to freedom of expression.
The UN Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Opinion and Expression
has reiterated this on numerous occasions. In his 1999 Report
to the UN Commission on Human Rights, he stated:
Sanctions for defamation should not be so large
as to exert a chilling effect on freedom of opinion and expression
and the right to seek, receive and impart information; penal sanctions,
in particular imprisonment, should never be applied.[64]
In his Report in 2000, and again in 2001, the
Special Rapporteur went even further, calling on States to repeal
all criminal defamation laws in favour of civil defamation laws.[65]
Every year, the UN Commission on Human Rights, in its resolution
on freedom of expression, notes its concern with "abuse of
legal provisions on defamation and criminal libel".[66]
The three special international mandates for
promoting freedom of expressionthe UN Special Rapporteur,
the OSCE Representative on Freedom of the Media and the OAS Special
Rapporteur on Freedom of Expressionhave also taken this
issue up jointly. In their Declarations of November 1999, November
2000 and again in December 2002, they called on States to repeal
their criminal defamation laws. The 2002 statement read:
Criminal defamation is not a justifiable restriction
on freedom of expression; all criminal defamation laws should
be abolished and replaced, where necessary, with appropriate civil
defamation laws.[67]
Similarly, the UNESCO sponsored Declaration
of Sana'a declared, "Disputes involving the media and/or
the media professionals in the exercise of their profession |
should be tried under civil and not criminal codes and procedures."[68]
The UN Human Rights Committee has repeatedly
expressed its concern about the use of custodial sanctions for
defamation.[69]
The Committee has often commented on criminal defamation laws,
welcoming their abolition where this has occurred,[70]
calling for "review and reform [of] laws relating to criminal
defamation,"[71]
and expressing serious concerns about the potential for abuse
of criminal defamation laws, particularly where expression on
matters of public concern is at stake.[72]
So far, international courts have not gone so
far as to rule out criminal defamation per se, and the
European Court has implicitly approved it by failing find a breach
of the right to freedom of expression in some criminal defamation
cases. However, in Castells, the Court stated that criminal
measures should only be adopted where States act "in their
capacity as guarantors of public order" and where such measures
are, "[i]ntended to react appropriately and without excess
to defamatory accusations devoid of foundation or formulated in
bad faith."[73]
It is significant that the Court approved the application of criminal
measures only as a means of maintaining public order, and not
as a means of protecting reputations.
Furthermore, two recent cases decided by the
Inter-American Court of Human Rights, both of which resulted in
a finding of a breach of the right to freedom of expression, reflect
the increasingly suspicious stance of international courts towards
this form of restriction on freedom of expression.[74]
1. Criminal defamation laws frequently fail
to pursue a legitimate aim
As noted above, defamation laws are frequently
abused to serve aims other than the protection of the reputation
of the plaintiff. This is a particular problem in the context
of criminal defamation laws, given that in many countries these
may be enforced by official rather than private prosecutions.
While this may not, as a matter of legal argument, be sufficient
reason to hold that these laws, per se, represent a breach of
the right to freedom of expressionafter all, practically
any law can be abused, particularly where judicial oversight is
weakit is, nevertheless, a good argument for doing away
with these laws.
Also as noted above, laws which provide special protection
for the reputations of public officials cannot be justified; in
fact, these individuals should be required to tolerate greater
criticism than ordinary citizens. Again, it is often criminal
defamation laws which provide for special protection for officials.
These laws may favour public officials by substantive or procedural
rules, including State assistance in bringing or prosecuting cases,
or because they provide for heavier penalties for defamation of
public officials than for private individuals.
2. Criminal defamation laws are not necessary
because civil laws provide adequate protection for reputation
It is well established that the guarantee of
freedom of expression requires States to use the least restrictive
effective remedy to secure the legitimate aim sought. This flows
directly from the need for any restrictions to be necessary; if
a less restrictive remedy is effective, the more restrictive one
cannot be necessary. In its judgment in Castells v Spain,
the European Court struck down a criminal defamation provision,
stressing that restraint should be used in resorting to the criminal
law, "particularly where other means are available for
replying to the unjustified attacks and criticisms of its adversaries
or the media" (emphasis added).[75]
The Inter-American Court of Human Rights has put the matter even
more clearly:
[I]f there are various options to achieve [a
compelling governmental interest], that which least restricts
the right protected must be selected.[76]
As a result, to the extent that civil defamation
laws are effective in appropriately redressing harm to reputation,
there is no justification for criminal defamation laws. Perhaps
the best evidence of the sufficiency of civil defamation laws
for this task comes from the growing number of jurisdictions where
they are either the preferred means of redress or growing in popularity,
even though criminal defamation laws are still on the books. This
is the case, for example, in many European countries, including
Austria and the Netherlands. In other countries, criminal defamation
laws have fallen into virtual desuetude. There has been no successful
attempt to bring a criminal prosecution for defamation in the
United Kingdom for many years and no private actor has even attempted
to do so for over 25 years.[77]
A number of countries have completely abolished
criminal defamation laws. These include Bosnia-Herzegovina (2002),
Estonia, Georgia (2004), Ghana (2001), Mexico (2007), New Zealand
(1992), Sri Lanka (2002) and the Ukraine (2001). These countries
have not experienced any noticeable increase in defamatory statements,
either of a qualitative or quantitative nature, since they abolished
criminal defamation.
In the United States, criminal defamation laws
have never been upheld by the Supreme Court,[78]
and there is no federal crime of criminal defamation. Other US
courts have also struck down criminal defamation laws and they
have been repealed in some states, including California and New
York, although they do remain on the books in some 17 states.
It may be noted that civil actions are, in any
case, better equipped to remedy the harm of defamation than criminal
actions, because they are designed to remedy the injury to the
victim's reputation by compensation in terms of damages. In contrast,
criminal sanctions do not for the most part aim to remedy the
actual harm caused to the victim but, rather, to punish the defendant.
It may be concluded that the experience of a
range of countries where criminal defamation laws have been struck
down by the courts, repealed by the authorities or fallen into
virtual disuse shows that such laws are not necessary to provide
appropriate protection for reputations. In these countries, civil
defamation laws have proven adequate to this task. Furthermore,
this experience is not limited to established democracies but
includes countries undergoing a transition to democracy, and from
different regions of the world.
Another way in which criminal defamation laws
do not represent the least restrictive approach is that, in many
countries, they shift the burden of proof onto a criminal defendant
by requiring the defendant to prove the truth of his or her statement,
the "reasonableness" of his or her opinion, or that
the publication was for the public benefit.
Addressing this point in the English case of
Gleaves v Deakin, Lord Diplock expressed the view that
the offence of criminal libel violated Article 10 of the European
Convention on Human Rights. Indeed, he said it turned Article
10 "on its head" because:
Under our criminal law a person's freedom of expression,
wherever it involves exposing seriously discreditable conduct
of others, is to be repressed by public authority unless he can
convince a jury ex post facto that the particular exercise of
the freedom was for the public benefit; whereas article 10 requires
that freedom of expression shall be untrammelled by public authority
except where its interference to repress a particular exercise
of the freedom is necessary for the protection of public interest.[79]
3. Criminal defamation laws are not necessary
because the sanctions they envisage are disproportionate
As noted above, disproportionate sanctions for
defamation, of themselves, represent a breach of the right to
freedom of expression. Criminal sanctions for defamation fall
foul of this rule because they are unduly harsh, taking into account
the harm caused. The threat of a criminal record, a penal sentence
or even a suspended sentence all impose a great and unnecessary
burden on a potential critic. There may also be penalties associated
with having a criminal record. In the case of Mr Herrera Ulloa,
whose conviction by the Costa Rican courts for criminal defamation
was found to breach his right to freedom of expression by the
Inter-American Court of Human Rights,[80]
these included ineligibility for probation upon further conviction
for criminal defamation, and being barred from adopting a child,
holding a position in the civil service or practising a profession.
The European Court of Human Rights has upheld criminal
defamation convictions on occasion but, in these cases, it has
been at pains to point out that the sanctions were modest and
hence met the requirement of proportionality. For example, in
Tammer v Estonia, the Court specifically noted, "the
limited amount of the fine imposed" in upholding the conviction;
the total fine in that case was ten times the daily minimum wage.[81]
The Court's jurisdiction is limited to assessing
the facts of the case before it so that, if a sanction is limited,
it must recognise that. However, a more general assessment of
criminal defamation laws leads to the conclusion that the possibility
of criminal sanctions exerts a serious chilling effect on freedom
of expression and cannot be justified. In its Report on the
Compatibility of "Desacato" Laws With the American Convention
on Human Rights, the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights
noted the particular problem with sanctions of a criminal nature,
stating:
The fear of criminal sanctions necessarily discourages
people from voicing their opinions on issues of public concern
...[82].
This has also been echoed by the UN Human Rights
Committee, which has made it clear that criminal convictions for
defamation tend to be disproportionate to any damage caused, stating
that, "the severity of the sanctions imposed on the author
[a prison sentence and a fine] cannot be considered as a proportionate
measure to protect ... the honour and the reputation of the President
..."[83].
CONCLUSION: ABOLISHING
CRIMINAL DEFAMATION
LAWS
In many countries, criminal defamation laws
are abused by the powerful to limit criticism and to stifle public
debate. ARTICLE 19 considers that the threat of harsh criminal
sanctions, especially imprisonment, exerts a profound chilling
effect on freedom of expression. As the jurisprudence and decisions
of the UN and regional human rights bodies testify, such sanctions
clearly cannot be justified, particularly in light of the adequacy
of non-criminal sanctions in redressing any harm to individuals'
reputations. There is always the potential for abuse of criminal
defamation laws, even in countries where in general they are applied
in a moderate fashion. ARTICLE 19 therefore calls on States to
repeal such laws.
At the same time, it is recognised that in many countries
criminal defamation laws are still the primary means of addressing
unwarranted attacks on reputation. To minimise the potential for
abuse or unwarranted restrictions on freedom of expression in
practice, it is essential that immediate steps be taken to ensure
that these laws conform to international standards.
Recommendations
(a) All criminal defamation laws should be abolished
and replaced, where necessary, with appropriate civil defamation
laws. Steps should be taken, in those States which still have
criminal defamation laws in place, to progressively implement
this Principle. (b) As a practical matter, in recognition of the
fact that in many States criminal defamation laws are the primary
means of addressing unwarranted attacks on reputation, immediate
steps should be taken to ensure that any criminal defamation laws
still in force conform fully to the following conditions:
(i) no-one should be convicted for
criminal defamation unless the party claiming to be defamed proves,
beyond a reasonable doubt, the presence of all the elements of
the offence, as set out below;
(ii) the offence of criminal defamation
shall not be made out unless it has been proven that the impugned
statements are false, that they were made with actual knowledge
of falsity, or recklessness as to whether or not they were false,
and that they were made with a specific intention to cause harm
to the party claiming to be defamed;
(iii) public authorities, including
police and public prosecutors, should take no part in the initiation
or prosecution of criminal defamation cases, regardless of the
status of the party claiming to have been defamed, even if he
or she is a senior public official;
(iv) prison sentences, suspended prison
sentences, suspension of the right to express oneself through
any particular form of media, or to practise journalism or any
other profession, excessive fines and other harsh criminal penalties
should never be available as a sanction for breach of defamation
laws, no matter how egregious or blatant the defamatory statement.
Annex One
DEFINING DEFAMATION: PRINCIPLES ON FREEDOM
OF EXPRESSION AND PROTECTION OF REPUTATIONS
PREAMBLE
Considering, in accordance with the principles
proclaimed in the Charter of the United Nations, as elaborated
in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, that recognition
of the equal and inalienable rights of all human beings is an
essential foundation of freedom, justice and peace;
Reaffirming the belief
that freedom of expression and the free flow of information, including
free and open debate regarding matters of public interest, even
when this involves criticism of individuals, are of crucial importance
in a democratic society, for the personal development, dignity
and fulfilment of every individual, as well as for the progress
and welfare of society, and the enjoyment of other human rights
and fundamental freedoms;
Taking into consideration relevant
provisions of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the African Charter on
Human and Peoples' Rights, the American Convention on Human Rights
and the European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms,
as well as provisions in national constitutions;
Bearing in mind the fundamental necessity
of an independent and impartial judiciary to safeguard the rule
of law and to protect human rights, including freedom of expression,
as well as the need for ongoing judicial training on human rights,
and in particular on freedom of expression;
Mindful of the importance to individuals
of their reputations and the need to provide appropriate protection
for reputation;
Cognisant also of the prevalence of defamation
laws which unduly restrict public debate about matters of public
concern, of the fact that such laws are justified by governments
as necessary to protect reputations, and of the frequent abuse
of such laws by individuals in positions of authority;
Aware of the importance of open access
to information, and particularly of a right to access information
held by public authorities, in promoting accurate reporting and
in limiting publication of false and potentially defamatory statements;
Cognisant of the role of the media in
furthering the public's right to know, in providing a forum for
public debate on matters of public concern, and in acting as a
"public watchdog" to help promote government accountability;
Recognising the importance of self-regulatory
mechanisms established by the media that are effective and accessible
in providing remedies to vindicate reputations, and that do not
unduly infringe the right to freedom of expression;
Desiring to promote a better understanding
of the appropriate balance between the right to freedom of expression
and the need to protect reputations;
We[84]
recommend that national, regional and international bodies undertake
appropriate action in their respective fields of competence to
promote the widespread dissemination, acceptance and implementation
of these Principles:
SECTION 1 GENERAL
PRINCIPLES
Principle 1: Freedom of Opinion, Expression and
Information
(a) Everyone has the right to hold opinions without
interference. (b) Everyone has the right to freedom of expression,
which includes the freedom to seek, receive and impart information
and ideas of all kinds, regardless of frontiers, either orally,
in writing or in print, in the form of art, or through any other
media of his or her choice.
(c) The exercise of the right provided for in paragraph
(b) may, where this can be shown to be necessary, be subject to
restrictions on specific grounds, as established in international
law, including for the protection of the reputations of others.
(d) Anyone affected, directly or indirectly, by a
restriction on freedom of expression must be able to challenge
the validity of that restriction as a matter of constitutional
or human rights law before an independent court or tribunal.
(e) Any application of a restriction on freedom of
expression must be subject to adequate safeguards against abuse,
including the right of access to an independent court or tribunal,
as an aspect of the rule of law.
Principle 1.1: Prescribed by Law
Any restriction on expression or information
must be prescribed by law. The law must be accessible, unambiguous
and narrowly and precisely drawn so as to enable individuals to
predict with reasonable certainty in advance the legality or otherwise
of a particular action.
Principle 1.2: Protection of a Legitimate Reputation
Interest
Any restriction on expression or information which
is sought to be justified on the ground that it protects the reputations
of others, must have the genuine purpose and demonstrable effect
of protecting a legitimate reputation interest.[85]
Principle 1.3: Necessary in a Democratic Society
A restriction on freedom of expression or information,
including to protect the reputations of others, cannot be justified
unless it can convincingly be established that it is necessary
in a democratic society. In particular, a restriction cannot be
justified if:
(i) less restrictive, accessible means exist
by which the legitimate reputation interest can be protected in
the circumstances; or
(ii) taking into account all the circumstances, the
restriction fails a proportionality test because the benefits
in terms of protecting reputations do not significantly outweigh
the harm to freedom of expression.
Principle 2: Legitimate Purpose of Defamation
Laws
(a) Defamation laws cannot be justified unless their
genuine purpose and demonstrable effect is to protect the reputations
of individualsor of entities with the right to sue and
be suedagainst injury, including by tending to lower the
esteem in which they are held within the community, by exposing
them to public ridicule or hatred, or by causing them to be shunned
or avoided.
(b) Defamation laws cannot be justified if their
purpose or effect is to protect individuals against harm to a
reputation which they do not have or do not merit, or to protect
the "reputations" of entities other than those which
have the right to sue and to be sued. In particular, defamation
laws cannot be justified if their purpose or effect is to:
(i) prevent legitimate criticism of officials
or the exposure of official wrongdoing or corruption;
(ii) protect the "reputation" of objects,
such as State or religious symbols, flags or national insignia;
(iii) protect the "reputation" of the
State or nation, as such;
(iv) enable individuals to sue on behalf of persons
who are deceased; or
(v) allow individuals to sue on behalf of a group
which does not, itself, have status to sue.
(c) Defamation laws also cannot be justified on the
basis that they serve to protect interests other than reputation,
where those interests, even if they may justify certain restrictions
on freedom of expression, are better served by laws specifically
designed for that purpose. In particular, defamation laws cannot
be justified on the grounds that they help maintain public order,
national security, or friendly relations with foreign States or
governments.
Principle 3: Defamation of Public Bodies
Public bodies of all kindsincluding all
bodies which form part of the legislative, executive or judicial
branches of government or which otherwise perform public functionsshould
be prohibited altogether from bringing defamation actions.
SECTION 2 CRIMINAL
DEFAMATION
Principle 4: Criminal Defamation
(a) All criminal defamation laws should be abolished
and replaced, where necessary, with appropriate civil defamation
laws. Steps should be taken, in those States which still have
criminal defamation laws in place, to progressively implement
this Principle. (b) As a practical matter, in recognition of the
fact that in many States criminal defamation laws are the primary
means of addressing unwarranted attacks on reputation, immediate
steps should be taken to ensure that any criminal defamation laws
still in force conform fully to the following conditions:
(v) no-one should be convicted for criminal defamation
unless the party claiming to be defamed proves, beyond a reasonable
doubt, the presence of all the elements of the offence, as set
out below;
(vi) the offence of criminal defamation shall
not be made out unless it has been proven that the impugned statements
are false, that they were made with actual knowledge of falsity,
or recklessness as to whether or not they were false, and that
they were made with a specific intention to cause harm to the
party claiming to be defamed;
(vii) public authorities, including police and
public prosecutors, should take no part in the initiation or prosecution
of criminal defamation cases, regardless of the status of the
party claiming to have been defamed, even if he or she is a senior
public official;
(viii) prison sentences, suspended prison sentences,
suspension of the right to express oneself through any particular
form of media, or to practise journalism or any other profession,
excessive fines and other harsh criminal penalties should never
be available as a sanction for breach of defamation laws, no matter
how egregious or blatant the defamatory statement.
SECTION 3 CIVIL
DEFAMATION LAWS
Principle 5: Procedure
(a) The limitation period for filing a defamation
suit should, except in exceptional circumstances, be no more than
one year from the date of publication. (b) Courts should ensure
that each stage of defamation proceedings is conducted with reasonable
dispatch, in order to limit the negative impact of delay on freedom
of expression. At the same time, under no circumstances should
cases proceed so rapidly as to deny defendants a proper opportunity
to conduct their defence.
Principle 6: Protection of Sources
(a) Journalists, and others who obtain information
from confidential sources with a view to disseminating it in the
public interest, have a right not to disclose the identity of
their confidential sources. Under no circumstances should this
right be abrogated or limited in the context of a defamation case.
(b) Those covered by this Principle should not suffer
any detriment in the context of a defamation case simply for refusing
to disclose the identity of a confidential source.
Principle 7: Proof of Truth
(a) In all cases, a finding that an impugned statement
of fact is true shall absolve the defendant of any liability.[86]
(b) In cases involving statements on matters of public
concern,[87]
the plaintiff should bear the burden of proving the falsity of
any statements or imputations of fact alleged to be defamatory.
(c) Practices which unreasonably restrict the ability
of defendants to establish the truth of their allegations should
be revised.
Principle 8: Public Officials
Under no circumstances should defamation law
provide any special protection for public officials, whatever
their rank or status. This Principle embraces the manner in which
complaints are lodged and processed, the standards which are applied
in determining whether a defendant is liable, and the penalties
which may be imposed.
Principle 9: Reasonable Publication
Even where a statement of fact on a matter of public
concern has been shown to be false, defendants should benefit
from a defence of reasonable publication. This defence is established
if it is reasonable in all the circumstances for a person in the
position of the defendant to have disseminated the material in
the manner and form he or she did. In determining whether dissemination
was reasonable in the circumstances of a particular case, the
Court shall take into account the importance of freedom of expression
with respect to matters of public concern and the right of the
public to receive timely information relating to such matters.
Principle 10: Expressions of Opinion
(a) No one should be liable under defamation law
for the expression of an opinion.
(b) An opinion is defined as a statement which
either:
(i) does not contain a factual connotation which
could be proved to be false; or
(ii) cannot reasonably be interpreted as stating
actual facts given all the circumstances, including the language
used (such as rhetoric, hyperbole, satire or jest).
Principle 11: Exemptions from Liability
(a) Certain types of statements should never
attract liability under defamation law. At a minimum, these should
include:
(i) any statement made in the course of proceedings
at legislative bodies, including by elected members both in open
debate and in committees, and by witnesses called upon to give
evidence to legislative committees;
(ii) any statement made in the course of proceedings
at local authorities, by members of those authorities;
(iii) any statement made in the course of any
stage of judicial proceedings (including interlocutory and pre-trial
processes) by anyone directly involved in that proceeding (including
judges, parties, witnesses, counsel and members of the jury) as
long as the statement is in some way connected to that proceeding;
(iv) any statement made before a body with a
formal mandate to investigate or inquire into human rights abuses,
including a truth commission;
(v) any document ordered to be published by a
legislative body;
(vi) a fair and accurate report of the material
described in points (i)(v) above; and
(vii) a fair and accurate report of material
where the official status of that material justifies the dissemination
of that report, such as official documentation issued by a public
inquiry, a foreign court or legislature or an international organisation.
(b) Certain types of statements should be exempt
from liability unless they can be shown to have been made with
malice, in the sense of ill-will or spite. These should include
statements made in the performance of a legal, moral or social
duty or interest.
Principle 12: Scope of Liability
(a) No one should be liable under defamation law
for a statement of which he or she was not the author, editor
or publisher and where he or she did not know, and had no reason
to believe, that what he or she did contributed to the dissemination
of a defamatory statement.
(b) Bodies whose sole function in relation to a particular
statement is limited to providing technical access to the internet,
to transporting data across the internet or to storing all or
part of a website shall not be subject to any liability in relation
to that statement unless, in the circumstances, they can be said
to have adopted the relevant statement. Such bodies may, however,
be required to take appropriate action to prevent further publication
of the statement, pursuant either to an interim or to a permanent
injunction meeting the conditions, respectively, of Principle
16 or 17.
SECTION 4 REMEDIES
Principle 13: Role of Remedies
(a) No mandatory or enforced remedy for defamation
should be applied to any statement which has not been found, applying
the above principles, to be defamatory. (b) The overriding goal
of providing a remedy for defamatory statements should be to redress
the harm done to the reputation of the plaintiff, not to punish
those responsible for the dissemination of the statement.
(c) In applying remedies, regard should be had to
any other mechanismsincluding voluntary or self-regulatory
systemswhich have been used to limit the harm the defamatory
statements have caused to the plaintiff's reputation. Regard should
also be had to any failure by the plaintiff to use such mechanisms
to limit the harm to his or her reputation.
Principle 14: Non-Pecuniary Remedies
Courts should prioritise the use of available
non-pecuniary remedies to redress any harm to reputation caused
by defamatory statements.
Principle 15: Pecuniary Awards
(a) Pecuniary compensation should be awarded only
where non-pecuniary remedies are insufficient to redress the harm
caused by defamatory statements.
(b) In assessing the quantum of pecuniary awards,
the potential chilling effect of the award on freedom of expression
should, among other things, be taken into account. Pecuniary awards
should never be disproportionate to the harm done, and should
take into account any non-pecuniary remedies and the level of
compensation awarded for other civil wrongs.
(c) Compensation for actual financial loss, or material
harm, caused by defamatory statements should be awarded only where
that loss is specifically established.
(d) The level of compensation which may be awarded
for non-material harm to reputationthat is, harm which
cannot be quantified in monetary termsshould be subject
to a fixed ceiling. This maximum should be applied only in the
most serious cases.
(e) Pecuniary awards which go beyond compensating
for harm to reputation should be highly exceptional measures,
to be applied only where the plaintiff has proven that the defendant
acted with knowledge of the falsity of the statement and with
the specific intention of causing harm to the plaintiff.
Principle 16: Interim Injunctions
(a) In the context of a defamation action, injunctions
should never be applied prior to publication, as a form of prior
restraint.
(b) Interim injunctions, prior to a full hearing
of the matter on the merits, should not be applied to prohibit
further publication except by court order and in highly exceptional
cases where all of the following conditions are met:
(i) the plaintiff can show that he or she would
suffer irreparable damagewhich could not be compensated
by subsequent remediesshould further publication take place;
(ii) the plaintiff can demonstrate a virtual
certainty of success, including proof:
that the statement was unarguably defamatory;
and
that any potential defences are manifestly
unfounded.
Principle 17: Permanent Injunctions
Permanent injunctions should never be applied
except by court order and after a full and fair hearing of the
merits of the case. Permanent injunctions should be limited in
application to the specific statements found to be defamatory
and to the specific people found to have been responsible for
the publication of those statements. It should be up to the defendant
to decide how to prevent further publication, for example by removing
those particular statements from a book.
Principle 18: Costs
In awarding costs to both plaintiffs and defendants,
courts should pay particular attention to the potential effect
of the award on freedom of expression.
Principle 19: Malicious Plaintiffs
Defendants should have an effective remedy where
plaintiffs bring clearly unsubstantiated cases with a view to
exerting a chilling effect on freedom of expression, rather than
vindicating their reputations.
June 2009
11 ARTICLE 19, London, 2000. Available at: http://www.article19.org/publications/law/standard-setting.html. Back
12
See their Joint Declaration of 30 November 2000. Available at:
http://www.unhchr.ch/huricane/huricane.nsf/view01/EFE58839B169CC09C12569AB002D02C0?opendocument Back
13
UN General Assembly Resolution 217A(III), adopted 10 December
1948. Back
14
UN General Assembly Resolution 2200A(XXI), adopted 16 December
1966, in force 23 March 1976. Back
15
Adopted 4 November 1950, E.T.S. No. 5, in force 3 September 1953. Back
16
Adopted at San José, Costa Rica, 22 November 1969, O.A.S.
Treaty Series No. 36, 1144 U.N.T.S. 123, in force 18 July 1978. Back
17
Adopted at Nairobi, Kenya, 26 June 1981, OAU Doc. CAB/LEG/67/3
rev. 5, 21 I.L.M. 58 (1982), in force 21 October 1986. Back
18
14 December 1946. "Freedom of information" is referred
to in the broad sense of the free circulation of information and
ideas. Back
19
Tae-Hoon Park v Republic of Korea, 20 October 1998, Communication
No 628/1995, para 10.3. Back
20
See, for example, Laptsevich v Belarus, 20 March 2000,
Communication No. 780/1997. Back
21
The Sunday Times v United Kingdom, 26 April 1979, Application
No 6538/74, para 49. Back
22
Handyside v United Kingdom, 7 December 1976, Application
No 5493/72, para 49. Back
23
Ibid, para 49. Statements of this nature abound in the
jurisprudence of courts and other judicial bodies around the world. Back
24
Dichand and others v Austria, 26 February 2002, Application
No 29271/95, para 39. Back
25
See Karatas v Turkey, 8 July 1999, Application No 23168/94,
paras 50-54. Back
26
See, for example, Bladet Troms' and Stensaas v Norway,
20 May 1999, Application No 21980/93, para 63 and Bergens Tidende
and Others v Norway, 2 May 2000, Application No 26131/95,
para 57. Back
27
Oberschlick v Austria (No 2), 1 July 1997, Application
No 20834/92, para 34. Back
28
Lingens v Austria, 8 July 1986, Application No 9815/82,
8 EHRR 407. para 43. Back
29
See, for example, Dichand and others v Austria, note 14,
para 38. Back
30
Thorgeirson v Iceland, 25 June 1992, Application No 13778/88,
para 63. Back
31
Castells v Spain, 24 April 1992, Application No 11798/85,
para. 43. Back
32
Handyside v United Kingdom, 7 December 1976, Application
No 5493/72, para 49. Back
33
See, for example, Dichand and others v Austria, note 14,
para 40. Back
34
See, for example, McVicar v the United Kingdom, 7 May 2002,
Application No 46311/99. Back
35
Overly broad and/or vaguely defined offences should not, in principle,
be considered to be prescribed by law but in practice the Court
has been very reluctant to find a breach on this basis alone in
defamation cases. Back
36
See, for example, Lingens v Austria, note 18, para 36 and
Schwabe v Austria, 28 August 1992, Application No 13704/88,
para 25. Back
37
Castells v Spain, note 21, paras 38-39. Back
38
Lingens v Austria, note 18, para 42. Back
39
See, for example, Lopes Gomez da Silva v Portugal, 28 September
2000, Application No 37698/97, para 30; Wabl v Austria,
21 March 2000, Application No 24773/94, para 42; and Oberschlick
v Austria, 23 May 1991, Application No 11662/85, para 59. Back
40
Dichand and others v Austria, note 14, para 51. Back
41
See Janowski v Poland, 21 January 1999, Application No
25716/94, para 33. See also Thorgeir Thorgeirson v Iceland,
note 20. Back
42
Dalban v Romania, 28 September 1999, Application No 28114/95. Back
43
Thoma v Luxembourg, 29 March 2001, Application No 38432/97,
para 47. Back
44
Thorgeir Thorgeirson v Iceland, note 20, para 64. Back
45
See, for example, Bladet Troms' and Stensaas v Norway,
note 16. Back
46
Dichand and others v Austria, note 14, para 42. Back
47
12 July 2001, Application No 29032/95. Back
48
The Sunday Times v the United Kingdom (No 2), 24 October
1991, Application No 13166/87, para 51. Back
49
Bladet Troms' and Stensaas v Norway, note 16, para 65. Back
50
Ibid. Back
51
Thoma v Luxembourg, note 32, para 62. Back
52
Ibid, para 64. Back
53
A. v the United Kingdom, 17 December 2002, Application
No 35373/97, quoting with approval the admissibility decision
of the European Commission of Human Rights in Young v Ireland,
17 January 1996, Application No 25646/94. Back
54
See also Jerusalem v Austria, 27 February 2001, Application
No 26958/95, para 36. Back
55
Nikula v Finland, 21 March 2002, Application No 31611/96,
para 55. Back
56
Ibid, para 45. Back
57
Ibid, para 54. Back
58
13 July 1995, Application No 18139/91, para 35. Back
59
Ibid, para 49. Back
60
Adopted 12 February 2004. Back
61
See, for example, Ediciones Tiempo SA v Spain, 12 July
1989, Application No 13010/87 (European Commission of Human Rights). Back
62
Castells v Spain, note 21, para 46. Back
63
Lingens v Austria, note 18. Back
64
Promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion
and expression, UN Doc E/CN.4/1999/64, 29 January 1999, para
28. Back
65
See Promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion
and expression, UN Doc E/CN.4/2000/63, 18 January 2000, para
52 and Promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion
and expression, UN Doc E/CN.4/2001/64, 26 January 2001. Back
66
See, for example, Resolution 2005/38, 19 April 2005, para 3(a). Back
67
Joint Declaration of 10 December 2002. Back
68
Declaration of Sana'a, 11 January 1996, endorsed by the
General Conference by Resolution 34, adopted at the 29th session,
12 November 1997. Back
69
This concern has been expressed in the context of specific country
reports. For example in relation to Iceland and Jordan (1994),
Tunisia and Morocco (1995), Mauritius (1996), Iraq and Slovakia
(1997), Zimbabwe (1998), and Cameroon, Mexico, Morocco, Norway
and Romania (1999), Azerbaijan, Guatemala and Croatia (2001),
and Serbia and Montenegro (2004). Back
70
For example in the case of Sri Lanka. See Concluding Observations
on Sri Lanka, 1 December 2003, CCPR/CO/79/LKA, para 17. Back
71
For example, in its Concluding Observations on Norway, 1 November
1999, CCPR/C/79/Add.112, para 14. Back
72
For example, in relation to Kyrgyzstan: "[The Committee]
is especially concerned about the use of libel suits against journalists
who criticize the Government. Such harassment is incompatible
with the freedom of expression .... The State party should ensure
that journalists can perform their profession without fear of
being subjected to prosecution and libel suits for criticizing
government policy or government officials. Journalists and human
rights activists subjected to imprisonment in contravention of
articles 9 and 19 of the Covenant should be released, rehabilitated
and given compensation pursuant to articles 9.5 and 14.6 of the
Covenant." Concluding Observations on Kyrgyzstan, 24 July
2000, CCPR/C/69/KGZ, para. 20. See also the Concluding Observations
referred to above, note 58. Back
73
Castells v Spain, note 21, para 46. Back
74
Herrera-Ulloa v Costa Rica, 2 July 2004, Series C, No 107
and Ricardo Canese v Paraguay, 31 August 2004, Series C,
No 111. Back
75
Castells v Spain, note 21, para 46. Back
76
Compulsory Membership in an Association Prescribed by Law for
the Practice of Journalism, Advisory Opinion OC-5/85 of 13
November 1985, Series A, No 5, para 46. Back
77
Historical attempts include Goldsmith v Pressdram [1977]
QB 83, Gleaves v Deakin [1980] AC 477 and Desmonde v
Thorpe [1982] 3 All ER 268. None of these cases have gone
to trial because either the plaintiffs failed to obtain leave
to proceed or the cases were discontinued. Back
78
They have been struck down on at least two occasions. See Garrison
v Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64 (1964) and Ashton v Kentucky,
384 US 195 (1966). Back
79
Gleaves v Deakin, note 66, 483. Back
80
Note 63. Back
81
6 February 2001, para 69. See also Constantinescu v Romania,
21 March 2000. Back
82
Part IV(B). Back
83
Morais v Angola, 18 April 2005, Communication No 1128/2002,
para 6.8 (UN Human Rights Committee). Back
84
The "we" here comprises the participants at the London
Workshop referred to in footnote 3, a broad consensus of opinion
among the much larger group of individuals who have been involved
in the process of developing these Principles, as well as a growing
list of individuals and organisations who have formally endorsed
them. Back
85
See Principle 2. Back
86
See also Principle 9 on Reasonable Publication. Back
87
As used in these Principles, the term "matters of public
concern" is defined expansively to include all matters of
legitimate public interest. This includes, but is not limited
to, all three branches of government-and, in particular, matters
relating to public figures and public officials-politics, public
health and safety, law enforcement and the administration of justice,
consumer and social interests, the environment, economic issues,
the exercise of power, and art and culture. However, it does not,
for example, include purely private matters in which the interest
of members of the public, if any, is merely salacious or sensational. Back
|