Memorandum submitted by Michael Marcus,
Circuit Court Judge
I have passionately pursued for many years some
of the same questions which confront this Committee.1 I believe
that I have learned some of the most basic issues that must be
addressed before we can expect meaningful improvement in the use
and consequences of prisons in the many countries uncomfortably
competing for leadership with the United States in imprisonment
rates.2 I understand this Committee to be concerned, in part,
with the implications of the Carter Report, and I will
respond to those portions of the Terms of Reference where I believe
I may have something to offer. But I learned in 20 years of practice
as an attorney before taking the bench in 1990 that I should make
my most important points first. This brief paper will endeavor
to do so. The Carter Report's hoary recommendation of "purchasing
and converting a suitable vessel into a prison ship"3 is
symbolic of the need for a profound alteration in our approach
to these problems.
With respect, the Report misses the same point ubiquitously
missed by almost all prison reform work in the Western World for
the last four or five decades: we can make no substantial progress
without eschewing magical thinking and embracing the same tools
required for meaningful progress in any social endeavour with
measurable consequences: prescription of measurable objectives
and rigorous application of rational thought solidly grounded
in empiricism. Of course we can and should vet addiction treatment
programmes for effectiveness and send many addicts to them instead
of to prison. But the enormous problems of crimes and prisons
will continue to frustrate our best intentions until and unless
we abandon the magical thinking that "just deserts"
is a sufficient objective of sentencing and that it actually promotes
the objectives we apparently assign to it. In essence, we must
displace the false religion that dominates criminal justice with
behaviours that actually serve public safety and public values.
I now will attempt to outline the major points
I hope to convey, providing some links to supporting material.
I would welcome enthusiastically any request to provide more documentation
or to continue the discussion.
1. SENTENCING
COMMISSIONS: JUST
DESERTS IS
NOT ENOUGH
The Carter Report is obviously taken
with the combination of sentencing guidelines and a sentencing
commission. I've been deeply involved in this discussion in the
United States, having testified before our own Sentencing Guidelines
Council before Oregon adopted our guidelines in 1989, and having
been involved as well in the American Law Institute's current
project to revise the Model Penal Code to implement a guidelines/commission
approach to sentencing. Guidelines have definite values.4 They
allow an avenue by which to normalize sentencing so as to predict,
and to some extent control, our use of prison resources. They
accomplish some meaningful moderation of the alarming disparity
sometimes achieved by unbridledand unguided and uninformedjudicial
discretion.
But guidelines in the US have at best reduced prison
population growth rates, and they have repeatedly fallen to popular
will motivated to increase sentences, reduce sentencing discretion,
and create mandatory minimum sentencesall of which continue
to swell prisons. Guidelines' accomplish consistency largely by
pretending that quite disparate offenders or offenses are alike.
But most importantly, by focusing on the symptomprison
rate escalationthey wholly ignore the disease. That disease
is the magical thinking that just deserts - a "just sentence"is
a sufficient accomplishment, to the practical exclusion of responsible
allocation of prison and programme resources according to real
evidence of real risk and real opportunity for reduction in criminal
behaviour. Historically, the surge in prison growth in recent
decades was itself in part a reaction to failure of the magical
thinking that merely sending offenders to programmes nominally
relevant to their criminal behaviourtheft talk, alcohol
or drug treatment, anger management, and the likewe would
reduce their criminal behaviour. In both applications, magical
thinking does not produce the results we desire just because we
hope for or expect success. Like anything else that matters, we
need to be rigorous, measure, and progress through the application
of empirical experience. To the extent that any approach deviates
from that principle, we are doomed to repeat the mistakes of the
past and, increasingly, to suffer their consequences.
This flaw in the mission and structure of sentencing
commissions and guidelines is wholly shared with discretionary
sentencing in the absence of guidelines, and completely eclipses
the significance of heated debates concerning the value of judicial
discretion and the correct locus of guideline authority in the
judicial, legislative, or executive portion of government. The
meaningful issue is whether sentences or guidelines are properly
directed and responsibly craftedand all branches of government
have triumphed in their demonstration of a capacity to get it
wholly wrong. Stated otherwise, the profound failure of guideline
structures is that they have always tended to use typical judicial
behaviour as a lodestar for normalizationwithout bothering
to notice that the outcome of that typical behaviour is enormous
recidivism. Missed, also, is that guidelines seek to capture in
a matrix the collected judicial wisdom which made no meaningful
attempt to direct sentencing at reducing recidivism (or serving
any goal other than just deserts), and which was based on no effort
whatever to accumulate any information upon which responsibly
to base any such attempt.
So guidelines continue to allocate prison beds
based on ordered just deserts rather than risk, need, and science.
From a risk point, we have found that Oregon's guidelines get
it wrong two-thirds of the time.5 This is not just an immediate
waste of resources, but a substantial part of the problem. Empirically
incorrect imprisonmentin the sense that we send many of
the wrong people thereis rampant, and it is itself a major
criminogenic factor for many offenders whose recidivism rate is
increased by their experience. In other words, misusing prison
is one of the major causes of prison growth. The great majority
of inmates now in prisons were previously sentenced for prior
crimes6reflecting the reality that sentencing makes no
responsible effort to reduce future crime. Unfortunately, we increase
the criminality of many offenders by sending them to prison so
that we eventually need prisons for them when we didn't in the
first place. This factor escalates as prison overcrowding worsens
the already counterproductive aspects of prison life. We contribute
to victimization at the hands of several groups of offenders for
whom our mindless distribution of sentences makes things worse:
those who would have committed fewer
crimes had we sent them to appropriate community based programmes
instead of to prison;
those who would have committed fewer
crimes had we afforded them the programmes that we cannot afford
because we misallocate resources to prisons;
those whose prison terms were not
long enough to serve public safety because we were diverting substantial
prison resources from those that should to those who should not
be in prison; and
those in prison who would have committed
fewer crimes after prison had we allocated resources to their
rehabilitation and reintegrationinstead of using those
resources to house others for whom prison was not the best public
safety response.
Guidelines, commissions, and appellate review
can be a useful part of the solution, but they must first overcome
these flaws. In brief, we need to use the guidance of this triumvirate
not primarily to attempt to manipulate how sentencing affects
prison rates, but to achieve evidence-based allocation of prison
and other sentencing resourceswithin limits of proportionality
and law to be sure, but to the ends of serving public safety and
public values, with rigorous attention to actual impact on actual
objectives. Similarly, we must be rigorous in measuring the performance
of programmes that are supposed to reduce criminal behaviour,
and in allocating them intelligently in and out of prison. We
know a lot more now about what makes a programme work than we
did when some prematurely reached the conclusion that "nothing
works", one prominent genesis of the prison population explosion.
See Responding to the Model Penal Code Sentencing Revisions:
Tips for Early Adopters and Power Users, note 4.
2. RISK ASSESSMENTONE
PIECE OF
THE ANSWER
Perhaps the most valuable innovation in the
United States guidelines evolution is the experience of the Virginia
Criminal Sentencing Commission.7 To be sure, that commission,
like all others to date, is profoundly impaired by the pervasive
and suffocating effect of just deserts, with vast attention to
"aggravation", "mitigation", and supposed
past judicial wisdom and public vindictiveness. But Virginia,
and to a growing extent, Missouri, have introduced risk assessment
into the mix with very promising results. Virginia developed and
validated an instrument, and first applied it to select the highest
risk sex offenders for increased incarceration in pursuit of public
safety. The politics of the result were sufficient to motivate
the Virginia Legislature to direct the Commission to develop and
implement a risk assessment instrument to divert a substantial
portion of lower risk offenders away from prison and into community
based sentences. Virginia's experience is that the result significantly
impacted the demands on prison and reduced the recidivism rate
of violent offenders.
Missouri's experience is newer, and consists of a
risk-assessment based instrument to assist in allocating prison
beds based on risk.8
To be sure, all existing sentencing commissions
seem to concern themselves with monitoring and reporting on compliance
by judges with sentencing guidelinesa worthwhile subsidiary
goal, but only to the extent that the guidelines are themselves
productive of something of social value. A thing not worth doing
is not worth doing well. In my view, commissions should be primarily
charged with monitoring how well sentencing achieves its social
objectives of supporting public safety and public values,9 and
only secondarily tasked with monitoring the effect of guidelines
on sentencing behaviour and prison bed demand.
But the major point of this subsection is that
any improvement must embrace and not eschew risk assessment as
an ingredient of the solution. There are voices contending that
risk assessment is imperfect because productive of "false
positives", and unfair because either "punishing for
future conduct" or invoking static variables over which offenders
have no control. Although I advocate empirical vigor in all of
this and make no exception for risk assessmentwe must be
mindful of its flaws and vigilant in pursuing its continued improvement
none of these arguments have ultimate merit. They miss the point
that it is risk that we are managing, not future conduct that
we punish. They support sentencing based on ephemeral rather than
empirical bases which, if measured by fairness or public safety,
is far more productive of false positives (and false negatives).
Deeming an offender a high risk of producing harm is not "false"
simply because he does not actually commit that new crime; the
issue is whether his risk was accurately assessed. As long as
the resulting sentence is neither disproportionate in its severity
nor unlawful, there is nothing unfair or inappropriate in allocating
prison time and space to offenders who are, based on our best
efforts at assessment, more likely than others to do more harm.
To insist that we ignore this difference is to punish many who
do not need it (and thus to be unfair to them) and to incapacitate
insufficiently those who do need itwhich is unfair to their
avoidable victims.10
Ultimately, the opponents of risk assessment
must and do reject public safety as the purpose of incapacitation,
for if public safety is its purpose, pursuit of effective risk
assessment is a necessary corollary.11 It makes no sense to deride
risk assessment as imperfect or unfair (or as "preventive
incarceration") when the default these opponents defend is
overwhelmingly less informed, less careful, less analytical, and
routinely productive of high recidivism rates.12
3. ACCOMPLISHING
CHANGE
This part of the piece assumes agreement that
any meaningful solution requires a profound change in the very
culture of sentencing, that the objective is a rational allocation
of all sentencing resources within the limits of proportionality
and law, based on risk, resource, and priority. The question that
remains is how to move a long-entrenched and archaic liturgy13
into the 21st century to join other social institutions in an
evidence-based, performance measured, accountable engine by which
to pursue rational social objectives. I am not much of a politician,
although I have successfully run in a contested election for the
office I hold, and have often testified to our state Legislature
in support of efforts related to this one.14 I have a few thoughts
on the politics of this undertaking that may be useful, and a
good deal to report on our strategies within the judicial department
for accomplishing this change.
Politics of effective sentencing. What
I have to offer is limited. Most is recited in Justitia's Bandage:
Blind Sentencing.15 First, we must understand that one
obstacle to "reform" is a misconception that the public
is an enormous obstacle. Policy makers constantly overestimate
the public's punitivism, and underestimate its support for effective
efforts at rehabilitation.16 This is not foreign to the United
Kingdom. The Halliday Report concluded:
When asked unprompted what the purpose of
sentencing should be, the most common response is that it should
aim to stop re-offending, reduce crime or create a safer community.
Next most frequently mentioned are deterrence and rehabilitation.
Very few spontaneously refer to punishment or incapacitation.17
The next concept is that there is much room
for bridging ideological divides by agreeing that severity vs.
leniency is not at stakethat what matters is the rational
and efficient distribution of existing resources so as to accomplish
most efficiently crime reduction and whatever other public purposes
are to be pursued with sentencing. There is, as stated, enormously
underestimated public consensus that reducing recidivism is the
major purpose of criminal law and sentences, that rehabilitation
can serve these goals for some, and that incapacitation is necessary
for others. The public, for example, is easily persuaded to divert
drug users to treatment in lieu of prison, itself a relatively
easy but limited remedy to misuse of prison.
The exclusive pursuit of "just deserts"
has been an enormously destructive but effective excuse for not
making any responsible effort to meet these public expectations.
It has also enabled the public fallacy that severity and effectiveness
are directly proportional for all offenders. Accepting accountability
for outcomes and for appropriate allocation of resources measured
by their actual impact on these goals has enormous potential for
support along the vast majority of the continuum of public attitudes
towards crime and punishment.
"Evidence Based Sentencing" has something
of a burden in overcoming a reputation for leniency. Perhaps it
must be renamed, but whatever it is called, the trick is to apply
it not just to justify programmes for lower risk offenders, but
across the entire spectrum of offenses and offenders, within limits
of proportionality and resource, so that we act as if we are actually
part of the modern world of empiricism, as opposed to participants
in ancient rites founded upon magical thinking. This means recognizing
the large cohort of offenders for whom less intervention is demonstrably
better for public safety than more; wisely vetting programmes
for their actual usefulness in reducing the criminogenic aspects
of cohorts of offenders as demonstrated by reduction in recidivism;
ensuring that we assign programmes and custody resources based
on our very best efforts to do that which works on those on whom
it works,18 and substantially lengthening the terms of violent
recidivist offenders against whom incapacitation is indeed the
morally justified and empirically required social protection.
Strategies for changing sentencing. It
is here that I finally reach our unique product, Multnomah County's
Sentencing Support tools. I reach them here because their primary
purpose is not to dictate sentences, but to assist in changing
the culture of sentencing by encouraging and informing the discussion
about what is most likely to reduce a given offender's future
criminal conduct. The tools are best described through the web
link in endnote 1 (and I'm happy to demonstrate them when we meet).
In brief, they display recidivism outcomes correlated with sentencing
elements (such as jail terms, forms of supervision, treatment
programmes, alternative programmes, and prison) imposed for similar
offenders for similar crimes. The user enters a case number (or
other identifier for an individual offender), chooses a crime
for which a sentence is contemplated, and promptly receives a
display of sentencing elements used for such offenders for such
crimes. The elements are displayed by bars in the order of the
frequency of that element's imposition for such offenders for
such crimes. The height of each bar in the chart is reflective
of the proportion of offenders who received that sentencing element
who were free of recidivism measuredby defaultas
freedom from a conviction for a similar offense within three years
of sentencing. Users can modify what is meant by a "similar
offence," a "similar offender," or "recidivism,"
and promptly receive a new display based on the altered variables.
The tools are designed to be convenient and quick enough to use
in court during a sentencing hearing; I can typically produce
a result in less than a minute including printing copies for counsel.
The court provides a dedicated computer for the use of attorneys.
The prosecutor's office has the tools in-house, as does the largest
of the indigent defense firms.
The tools are not designed to display causal
relationships between dispositions and results, but to group meaningful
displays of historical outcomesto encourage a pursuit of
responsible predictions. They are far from perfect, but far better
than what usually drives sentencing decisions.
Sentencing support tools are but one device
for attempting to move sentencing toward best practices. Others
are described in several articles,19 but here is a short description
of the ideas we have pursued:
Proclaiming in law and in resolutions
that sentencing must pursue public safety through validated responses
that demonstrably reduce recidivism.20
Constructing and maintaining database
practices and applications that provide information to support
data-driven sentencing decisions.21
Integrating risk and need assessment
into sentencing analysis.22
Developing evidence-based practices
in collaboration between courts and probation departments.23
Requiring that authors of pre-sentence
reports for the courts explore, analyze, and report on what is
most likely to reduce future crimeincluding the availability
of effective programmes in and out of custody.24
Including evidence-based practices,
stage of change analysis, motivational interviewing, and practical
sentencing in judicial education curricula.25
Providing on-line practical references
for smart sentencing to judges and advocates.26
Attempting to move the culture of
plea-negotiation towards evidence-based practices.27
Adopting court performance measures
that actually assess how effective sentencing is at achieving
public safety or any other purpose.28
4. THE CARTER
REPORT
I am, of course, in no position to do the budget
projections and analysis necessary to give this Committee precise
answers to questions about the costs associated with the Carter
Report recommendations, or related probation and programmatic
efforts. I can with confidence, however, offer some propositions
that I expect to withstand analysis and the test of time. These
propositions are equally applicable in the USparticularly
in California and Oregon, which have debated responding to crime
and prison problems with some mix of much more prison and some
more "treatment."29
First, whether or not it is unavoidable to include
some expansion of the supply of prison beds in the short run,
expanding prison capacity in relation to the general population
can only exacerbate the problems that generate the prison crisis.
Until and unless we learn to use prison more wiselyby farthan
we do now, adding prison beds will promote increase in crime and
the need for yet more prison beds. We are effectively addicted
to the essentially mindless use of prisons. As with any addiction,
feeding the habit is no cure.
Second, we must commit to the primary objective
of using our resources across the entire spectrum of offenders
to accomplish public safety within the limits of proportionality,
risk, and priority. In order to accomplish the primacy of the
pursuit of public safety, we must displace the facade of just
deserts as an adequate measure of our sentencing performance.
There are legitimate objectives lurking with "just deserts,"
but they, too, are capable of identification and measurementat
least to an enormously improved extent as compared with existing
practices. Thus, we should do our best to quantify those bundled
objectives and to determine the actual extent to which they are
served by sentencing dispositions. On occasion, but rarely, they
will justify deviation from the sentence best crafted to serve
public safety.30
Third, our commitment to actual outcomes must
include relying on the best research and data in making policy-level
and individual sentencing decisions. The issue of the reliability
of the evidence for "evidence based practices" is quite
real. There are some clear essentials:
Research is essential, but so is
actual performance measurement based on the impact on recidivism,
for comparable cohorts, of all of the dispositions practically
and legally available for those cohortsfrom and including
doing nothing substantialwhich is demonstrably the most
effective response to a large portion of the least serious categories
of offenders, through community based programmes and alternatives,
to prisonincluding the length and circumstances of incarceration,
which in turn includes prison programming and reintegration efforts.
Because the meaning of research and
data is so easily lost on those who collect and dwell on it, and
manipulated by those who have an interest in outcomes, the highest
calling of sentencing commissions is not monitoring compliance
with guidelines or sentencing protocols, but (1) vetting research
and data for constant validation and improvement, and (2) devising
and deploying strategies for achieving evidence-based practices
and desired public safety results both at policy level and individual
sentencing decisions.
Whatever the deficits in available
research and data, sentencing that attempts to make the best use
of that research and data is overwhelmingly more likely to achieve
public safety and to promote public values than current sentencing
behaviourswhich are predominantly dependent upon the fallacy
that just deserts is a sufficient accomplishment.
Finally, the long term costs and cost savings
of responses to the crime and prison crisis will overwhelming
depend not upon the immediate amount of any investment, but upon
the extent to which we can improve our ability to deploy all correctional
assets efficiently to reduce recidivism. Recidivism is the major
driver of these expenses, as well as of the expense to society
of avoidable victimizations.
CONCLUSION
The shelves of public and private collections,
and their more recent electronic storage equivalents, are filled
with decades of well-intended and presumably thoughtful studies
by advisory groups and committees (I've served on several)most
of which have had little impact on our behaviours and are long
forgotten. It is respectfully submitted that this Committee's
work is likely to suffer the same fate unless it responds on the
level of these suggestionsnot necessarily by adopting all
or even any of them, but at least by vigorously pursuing the causes
of the crisis rather than merely its symptoms, and by boldly confronting
the need for profound, systematic alterations to the culture and
practice of criminal justice.
April 2008
REFERENCES1 Much
of this pursuit is evidenced on or through the web site I have
maintained for many years, smartsentencing.com. This site describes
our sentencing support tools, our legislative efforts to promote
evidence-based sentencing, and the various articles I have published
in an attempt to promote the changes I believe necessary to take
us all out of our cruel morass. The site also has an eMail link.
I endeavour to answer every question put to me about this effort;
the site has a "frequently asked question" page for
the same purpose.
2 The most current report puts the U.S. at the
very top of this terrible pile, with England and Wales at about
16th placejust behind Romania. One in 100: Behind Bars
in America 2008 at 35, Table A-7 (Pew Charitable Trust 2008).
While the US is way ahead in the proportion of its population
in prison, the prison growth rate in England and Wales well justifies
grave concernand eases, somewhat, the irony of the notion
that we in the U.S. have something to offer. I believe some of
us do have much to offer, but our ideas are either obviously wrong
or quite right but well out of the mainstream of actual practice.
I think I can make the case for the latter.
3 Carter Report at 28. The rotting prison
hulks in the Thames came immediately to my mind. See What Are
We up to and Whyor If We're Doing More Harm than Good,
Why Rush?, presented at the West Central Wardens & Superintendents
Association "Round-up on the Oregon Trail," Pendleton,
Oregon, June 1997. To be fair, using a suitable vessel to supplement
prison space as a temporary solution to overcrowding is hardly
irrational, and the prison ship is but a minuscule part of Lord
Carter's recommendations.
4 For purposes of this discussion, all of the
points are supported at greater length in particular in two articles
on the subject, of which I have reprints that I'd be happy to
provide when we meet in person: Responding to the Model Penal
Code Sentencing Revisions: Tips for Early Adopters and Power Users,
17 S Cal Interdiscipl L J 68 (2007) (includes A Harm-Reduction
Sentencing Code); and Comments on the Model Penal Code:
Sentencing Preliminary Draft No. 1, 30 American Journal of
Criminal Law 135 (2003).
5 See Responding to the Model Penal Code Sentencing
Revisions: Tips for Early Adopters and Power Users, supra
note 4, 17 S Cal Interdiscipl L J at 76 & n 30.
6 Eg, Bureau of Justice Statistics Criminal
Offenders Statistics, United States Department of Justice.
7 Virginia's web site provides the annual and
subject reports that describe the risk assessment experience in
detail, particularly those of the initial validation and application
of risk assessment to sex offenders, describing the implementation
of risk assessment to divert low risk offenders from prison, and
describing the result: fewer lower risk offenders in prison, longer
terms for higher risk offenders, and lower recidivism rates for
higher risk offenders.
8 The Missouri Sentencing Advisory Commission
implemented a risk assessment-based "System of Recommended
Sentencing" in 2006, and described its impact on reducing
the flow of incoming prisoners most recently in a 2007 Biennial
Report.
9 Eg, Responding to the Model Penal Code Sentencing
Revisions: Tips for Early Adopters and Power Users, supra
note 4.
10 See generally, Christopher Slobogin, The
Civilization of the Criminal Law, 58 Vanderbilt Law Rev 118
(2005), and authorities cited. [The link takes you to an abstract;
the entire article may be downloaded from any of the links below
the abstract]. For a more extended examination of risk assessment,
see Marcus, Blakely, Booker, and the Future of Sentencing,
17 Federal Sentencing Reporter, 243 (2005); Marcus, Limiting
Retributivism: Revisions to Model Penal Code Sentencing Provisions,
29 Whittier Law Review 295, 317-29 (2007).
11 If public safety is not the objective, it
makes more sense and is more humane at least to offer caning as
an alternative to prison terms. If public safety is out of the
equation, caning would probably satisfy any public need for retribution
short of capital cases; it would solve the prison overcrowding
problem; it would save enormous sums that might be devoted instead
to programmes that actually work to reduce criminal behaviour,
and to social services that divert potential offenders from crime
altogether: high school completion, parenting education, and interdisciplinary
multisystemic intervention.
12 Comments on the Model Penal Code: Sentencing
Preliminary Draft No. 1, supra note 4, at 145-56 & n 44,
cited in The Civilization of the Criminal Law, supra note
10, at 22.
13 Marcus, Archaic Sentencing Liturgy Sacrifices
Public Safety: What's Wrong and How We Can Fix It, 16 Federal
Sentencing Reporter 76 (2003).
14 We are in the midst of a sweeping modernization
of court technology. Our Chief Justice asked me and our local
Trial Court Administrator to make the case to our Legislature
that improving our performance of our missionincluding
public safety and community well beingis the reason to
avoid delay in funding notwithstanding an economic downturn. We
obtained the authorization. (I've put these clips on YouTube
at least temporarily to facilitate sharing them; I hope to find
a more suitable mechanismand disclaim any embarrassing
unintended associations with content of obvious irrelevance.)
15 Marcus, Justitia's Bandage: Blind Sentencing,
International Journal of Punishment and Sentencing (2005).
16 Princeton Survey Research Associates International
for the National Center for State Courts, The NCSC Sentencing
Attitudes Survey: A Report on the Findings (July 2006) at
36; Peter D. Hart Research Associates, Inc., Changing Public
Attitudes Toward the Criminal Justice System (The Open Society
Institute, February 2002); Belden, Russonello & Stewart, Optimism,
Pessimism, and Jailhouse Redemption: American Attitudes on Crime,
Punishment, and Over-incarceration (Washington, DC 2001);
Cutting CorrectlyNew Priso N Policies for Times of Fiscal
Crisis (Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice, 2002), US
Department of Justice, National Institute of Corrections, Promoting
Pubic Safety Using Effective Interventions, Section 1 (February
2001), citing, eg, B K Applegate and F T Cullen, and B S Fisher,
Public Support for Correctional Treatment: The Continuing Appeal
of the Rehabilitative Ideal, 77 Prison Journal 237-58 (1997).
17 Making Punishments Work: Report of a Review
of the Sentencing Framework for England and Wales (Home Office
2001) App 5 at 108. The British Sentencing Advisory Council commissioned
public opinion polls to assist in recommending sentencing guidelines
to the Court of Appeal because it saw such polls as a better measure
of what it takes to maintain "public confidence" than
press coverage of notorious cases. Unfortunately, the Council
stacked the deck by focusing on public attitudes toward factors
of aggravation and mitigation and particular variations in targeted
crimes. Sentencing Advisory Panel, Annual Report (2003)
at 25. The United States Sentencing Commission adopted a similar
approach in commissioning a study of how Americans would sentence
federal crimes. Peter H Rossi & Richard A Berk, National
Sample Survey: Public Opinion on Sentencing Federal Crimes: Executive
Summary (1997). Asking the public to hold forth on what punishment
"fits the crime" is like asking the public for an opinion
on religion. Carefully constructed opinion polls, however, can
be a useful part of a process for assessing what is really necessary
to serve such issues as public trust and confidence in courts
and the government, and what actually serves the function of supporting
those public purposes hidden behind the liturgical mask of "just
deserts." See Responding to the Model Penal Code Sentencing
Revisions: Tips for Early Adopters and Power Users, supra note
4.
18 The exhaustive 1998 "Maryland Study"
of the effectiveness of programmes concluded:
"Today, while there is still some debate
about the effectiveness of rehabilitation (eg, Lab and Whitehead
1988; Whitehead and Lab 1989) recent literature reviews and metaanalyses
demonstrate that rehabilitation programs can effectively change
offenders (Andrews and Bonta 1994; Andrews, Bonta, and Hoge 1990;
Andrews, Zinger, Hoge, Bonta, Gendreau, and Cullen 1990; Palmer
1975; Gendreau and Ross 1979, 1987). In general, according to
Andrews et al (1990), reviews of the literature show positive
evidence of treatment effectiveness. For example,in a series of
literature reviews, the proportion of studies reporting positive
evidence of treatment effectiveness varied from near 50% to 86%:
75% (Kirby 1954), 59% (Bailey 1966), 50% (Logan 1972), 48% (Palmer's
1975 retabulation of studies reviewed by Martinson in 1974), 86%
(Gendreau and Ross 1979) and 47%t (Lab and Whitehead 1988). In
reviewing these studies, Andrews et al (1990) conclude
that `This pattern of results strongly supports exploration of
the idea that some service programs are working with at least
some offenders under some circumstances.' The important issue
is not whether something works but what works for whom."
Lawrence W Sherman, Denise C Gottfredson, Doris L
MacKenzie, John Eck, Peter Reuter, and Shawn D Bushway, Preventing
Crime: What Works, What Doesn't, What's Promising (National
Institute of Justice 1998). The quote is from the unpaginated
report under the heading "4. Rehabilitation and Treatment."
19 Nation-wide, the most recent treatments of
these types of attempts at injecting evidence-based sentencing
into the culture of criminal justice are Roger K Warren, Evidence-Based
Practices and State Sentencing Policy: Ten Policy Initiatives
to Reduce Recidivism, 82 Indiana L J 1307 (2007); and Marcus,
Smart Sentencing: Public Safety, Public Trust and Confidence
Through Evidence-Based Dispositions, in Future Trends in
State Courts 2006 at 56, (Nat'l Ctr For State Courts 2006). See
also Justitia's Bandage: Blind Sentencing, supra note 15,
at 20-28. Devising such strategies is the mission of the National
Institute of Corrections's National Advisory Committee on Evidence
Based Decision Making for Local Court Systems (of which I am a
member) that last met in November, 2007. NIC has recently released
a request for proposals for a Cooperative Agreement: Evidence
Based Decision Making for Local Criminal Justice Systems.
20 Our examples are collected here: Legislative,
Judicial, and Criminal Justice Commission Materials. The purposes
recited in the Criminal Justice Act 2003 are typical of
those in most US States, and reflect the same purposes adopted
by the 1962 Model Penal Code. Section 142(1) of the Criminal Justice
Act surely contains the crucial ingredients for these purposes:
"the reduction of crime," "the reform and rehabilitation
of offenders," and "the protection of the public."
The problem has usually been that these are but banners for the
justification of punishment rather than actual goals responsibly
pursued. Moreover, the unprioritized list of purposes gives no
actual direction to those who argue or decide sentencing issuesjudging
by the reduction of the whole exercise in most cases to ephemeral
and unaccountable musings about aggravation and mitigation, the
liturgy of just deserts. See, eg, Justitia's Bandage: Blind
Sentencing, supra note 15, at 10-11, and authorities cited.
21 Multnomah County's Sentencing Support tools
however modest, are still the most highly developed in the world
as far as I can tell. There is a recent analog for probation officers
in the District of Columbia. Oregon's ongoing court technology
modernization project is committed to expanding sentencing support
tools state-wide, and also to release, probation, juvenile, and
family law matters. Note that there is a more basic level at which
technology can support smarter sentencing: simply providing convenient
access to information such as prior criminal history, related
cases and holds, performance on supervision, and available programmes
in and out of custody.
22 As noted, Virginia (note 7, supra)
and Missouri (note 8, supra) have accomplished this in
their guidelines; Oregon has attempted to do so but has yet to
succeed. We have certainly regularly incorporated risk assessment
into presentence investigations.
23 Probation departments are often steeped on
the literature of criminology and evidence-based practices; they
are familiar with needs and risk assessment instruments. In the
past, they have been allowed and encouraged to leave those concepts
outside when they enter our temples of denunciation, and to argue
deserts instead of science at probation hearings. Yet, by their
training, at least many probation officers and their managers
are generally receptive to changing the role of probation officers.
In my experience, many are enthusiastic about becoming the courts'
experts in what works and in what is available, and advocates
for smarter sentencing. This is perhaps the most effective of
our innovations to date.
24 We began this initiative in 2002 by adding
a checkbox calling for such information to our local form of order
for a presentence investigation. The Oregon Legislature expanded
this requirement state-wide in 2005. The change has been dramatic
and positive in the value of presentence investigations, but limited
due to the relative rarity of such investigations since the advent
of sentencing guidelines in 1989. Since these reports are prepared
within our probation department, however, the change has spread
to probation reportswhich also regularly include risk and
needs assessments, stage of change analysis, and useful information
about the actual availability of programmes and their likely success.
So far, however, only presentence investigations routinely include
sentencing support tool results.
25 It took years, but we finally succeeded in
getting a "practical sentencing"session on the curriculum
of an annual trial judges' conference.
26 Oregon maintains an on-line Criminal Benchbook;
Chapter 16, Sentencing, begins with some 30 pages of practical
suggestions for achieving effective sentencing. [The page numbers
and chapter heads are internal hyperlinks; the book itself is
some 1,100 pages long.]
27 Plea bargains account for the vast majority
of sentences in the US. This is apparently now true in the UK
as well. Any change that matters must change plea bargaining.
We are making initial attempts locally to address this aspect
of the problem.
28 The "court performance measure"
movement has so far almost entirely avoided measuring anything
of value apart from speed. See generally Courtools On-line
(National Center for State Courts). Oregon has slowly begun
developing tools that address recidivism around treatment courts.
The issue is, of course, controversial among judges who think
only they get to do the judging, but I expect to expand this measure
to sentencing in general within the next two to four years.
29 California's 2007 Assembly Bill 900, subject
of a recent symposium at the University of San Francisco Law School
in which I participated, is much of what the Carter Report
prescribesmany more beds, some more treatment. A measure
seeking adoption through the ballot process, California's Nonviolent
Offender Rehabilitation Act of 2008, would laudably focus on providing
treatment to the substantial portion of the criminal justice population
subject to drug addiction. In Oregon, our November 2008 ballot
will see a competition between proposals opting for a very great
addition to our prison capacity and one offering a slightly less
drastic addition coupled with a substantial increase in treatment
resources.
30 The legitimate purposes of sentencing other
than public safety are probably limited to those that respond
to a legitimate need of a victim, prevent vigilantism or private
retribution, maintain respect for legitimate authority, or enhance
respect for the persons, property, or rights of others. In short,
the purposes of punishment other than public safety are those
that serve public values. Even if this list is not exhaustive,
the critical piece is to identify purposes other than safety and
to ensure that they impact sentencing through reasoned and evidence-based
analysis, particularly in the rare instance when they might actually
conflict with public safety objectives. Examples of the latter
are the social drinker who causes a death, the sex abuser whose
victim needs a tangible identification of blame with the offender,
or the criminal behaviour that is actually based on a cost/benefit
analysis, such as an industrial polluter. See Responding to
the Model Penal Code Sentencing Revisions: Tips for Early Adopters
and Power Users, supra note 4, 17 S Cal Interdiscipl L J at
78-83, 114-15.
|