Proposed Legislative Competence Orders relating to Organ Donation and Cycle Paths - Welsh Affairs Committee Contents


Written evidence submitted by David Evans

SUMMARY

  • The presumption of consent to anything must be seen as highly contentious and a matter of the most serious concern to lawyers.
  • Any such presumption of consent to surgical assault upon a person's body can have no validity if there is reason to think that the person might have objected to that assault on any reasonable grounds.
  • One good reason for refusal of consent to the non-therapeutic surgery required for organ donation might be the likelihood of the potential donor never having given serious consideration to the matter and therefore never having sought information about what is involved in the procurement of viable organs from human bodies.
  • Another is the real possibility that such information as may have been sought and obtained might have been misleading—either directly or through material omission.
  • In that regard the basis upon which a mortally sick patient is declared "deceased"—for the purpose of acquiring his or her organs for transplantation without legal difficulties—is very different from the basis upon which death is ordinarily diagnosed and certified and that highly relevant fact is not fully and generally understood.
  • Such information about death certification for transplant purposes as has been distributed by the Department of Health and its agencies has consistently failed to alert the enquirer to the fact that this is a topic of worldwide debate and concern.
  • It has also failed to provide full and fair information about the limitations of the tests used to diagnose death on neurological grounds while the heartbeat and circulation continue, simply asserting that negative responses to a few bedside tests of some brain stem functions suffice for that diagnosis on some idiosyncratic notion of what human death is.
  • There is, and never has been, a sound scientific basis for equating the syndrome so diagnosed with the death of the person identified as a potential organ donor.
  • Neither is there a sound scientific basis for the diagnosis of death on the circulatory criteria resorted to recently.
  • Since most people cannot be expected to understand what organ procurement from their only notionally dead bodies actually involves, their consent to such procedures cannot be presumed.
  • The same concern applies to the understanding of those who have put their names on the NHS Organ Donor Register—perhaps by ticking a box registering assent to the removal of their organs "after my death".
  • If any of them thought, when registering, that they would be dead in the commonly understood sense before organ removal—or if they didn't realize that they would have to be paralysed for the purpose but not given anaesthesia although possibly still sentient—then they were deceived.
  • I have long been deeply concerned about this—as I see it—probability that registered potential donors do not fully understand what it is that they have "consented" to but I have so far been unable to persuade the Secretary of State for Health to offer full and fair information to those from whom organs are sought, ie to tell them the truth.
  • A move towards "presumed consent" without first ensuring that everyone it may affect is fully and truthfully informed about what has to happen if they are used as organ donors some day—and that they clearly understand—seems to me an extension of the already prevalent deception of altruistic but vulnerable people in the increasingly frenetic search for more organs at whatever cost to professional trust and the old-fashioned idea of fair dealing.

AMPLIFICATION

1.  Use of the term "Deceased adults" in the context of organ procurement, without qualification or explanation, is seriously misleading. The body of a deceased person is commonly envisaged as a cadaver—unreactive, pallid, cooling and stiffening, and certainly without heartbeat, breathing or respiration. It is not possible to procure transplantable complex organs from that dead body. For that reason—to make it possible to obtain organs which will continue to function in another's body for many years—it is necessary to certify the death of the donor long before he or she is really dead in the commonly understood sense (death certification before non-therapeutic surgical operation on someone being necessary to avoid a charge of assault or murder).

2.   Many different ways of coping with this problem have been mooted during the past 40-odd years, mostly based on the idea that death of the brain can be diagnosed while the blood circulation continues and the body remains fully functional. Despite the development of more and more sensitive diagnostic techniques it is still not possible to say that there is no remaining life in the brains of those diagnosed "brain dead"—while the heartbeat and blood circulation continue—on any of the 30 or more schedules in use for that purpose worldwide. And when persisting life—such as electroencephalographic activity, endocrine function and blood pressure control—is demonstrated, it is disregarded as of no significance (although the way our wonderful brains work is not understood) or "explained away" on the basis of supposed extraordinary mechanisms (the ordinary mechanisms not having been shown to be inoperative). In the UK it is simply not sought.

3.  In the UK there is no attempt to test the bulk of the brain—the cerebral hemispheres and mid-brain—or the first two cranial nerves. Death is diagnosed for transplant purposes when, in ventilator-dependent patients, some reflexes with paths through the brain stem are persistently absent over an unspecified period of time and there is no observed response to stimulation of the brain stem respiratory centre by a specified hypercarbic stimulus (a rise in blood carbon dioxide concentration). This is the clinical syndrome known as "brain stem death". Since 1995 there has been no official pretence that this state is brain death—although it is still, carelessly or manipulatively, referred to as such by those seeking organs from patients so diagnosed—but it is claimed that it is a state from which there can be no recovery of consciousness or spontaneous breathing (an untested claim of an allegedly infallible prognosis). Without general discussion or philosophical consensus it has been decreed that that state is to be regarded as the death of the patient and a legal basis for its certification prior to organ removal. There are no sound scientific grounds for that practice. The generation of consciousness, and the minimum neuroanatomical substrate necessary for it, is not understood. The respiratory centre in the brain stem may still respond to anoxic drive (low arterial oxygen tension) although unresponsive to the specified hypercarbic drive—and often does when mechanical ventilation is finally discontinued.

4.  In recent years there has been a move towards procuring organs from patients whose hearts have been allowed to stop for a very short time—typically 2-5 minutes—after disconnection of the mechanical ventilator upon which he or she was dependent. This is a similarly specious exercise in the attempt to diagnose death while complex organs are still viable. The length of time it is necessary to wait—after what appears to be the final heartbeat—in order to be sure that there is no possibility of resuscitation or remaining life in the brain is simply not known. It is an area of great interest for several reasons and should be the subject of intense ethical scientific research. From my personal experience of many hundreds of cases of cardiac arrest I can say, with confidence, that the minimum time is likely to be dependent upon temperature and pertaining metabolic factors and to exceed currently accepted periods by a large margin. I have several times resuscitated patients after documented cardiac arrest for periods of up to 40 minutes, with full neurological recovery.

5.  "Brain stem death" has never been accepted as a sufficient basis for the diagnosis and certification of death for transplant purposes in many or most parts of the world, particularly in the USA. The US President's Council on Bioethics distanced itself from this UK practice in December 2008 (page 66 of its White Paper titled Controversies in the Determination of Death) but no mention of this has been made in the Department's literature or the mainstream UK medical journals.

6.  Only a few specially privileged UK doctors are empowered to diagnose death on "brain stem death" grounds. Many or most of the doctors in this country do not understand the complexities of these issues, having no need to take time-consuming practical interest—apart, one might think, from their responsibility for advising their patients enquiring about the wisdom of registering as organ donors. It is not known how many of them actively support organ transplantation as currently practised—or would do so if fully and accurately informed about procurement practice. They have never been asked. For many years our young doctors have been actively misinformed about "brain stem death" by the Academy of Medical Royal Colleges' Codes of Practice and Pallis' ABC of Brain Stem Death, published by the BMA but there are now welcome signs of their proper suspicion of those sources.

7.  While the medical profession as a whole is not fully apprised of the relevant facts, it is inconceivable that the general public has a clear, fully informed, understanding of the special nature of the "death" after which their organs will be removed if they join the NHS Organ Donor Register or, if "presumed consent" is adopted, if they fail to register objection before they become ventilator-dependent and unable to do so.

8.  It is likely that at least some of those who have registered as potential donors under the current system thought when they did so—if they thought about it at all when, perhaps, acting in response to an emotional appeal in the company of other generously motivated souls—that they would be dead in the commonly understood sense of that term before surgery to remove their organs commenced. That being the case, they had a materially different understanding of the meaning of the words "after my death" on the application form from that of those who might one day take up their offer. That, in itself, surely renders the offer invalid, the two parties to it being not ad idem about its terms.

9.  While that may be a matter for the lawyers it is cause for much greater concern to most of us if those people did not fully understand that, instead of being unresponsive and certainly unconscious when undergoing organ procurement surgery, they would be so reactive as to necessitate their being paralysed with drugs to facilitate that surgery and that they might not be given anaesthesia to cover any possibility of suffering while it was going on—although indications of such suffering (rises in blood pressure and heart rate) are commonplace. That is, to my mind, an ethical consideration far outweighing the legal aspects. It is, indeed, beyond my understanding of the proper doctor-patient relationship that anaesthesia may be withheld in those circumstances—as I am assured it often is. There should surely be provision on any form registering consent to being used as an organ donor for the specification of full general anaesthesia to cover the evisceration.

10.  The possibility of residual sentience is real although discounted in official propaganda. An anaesthetist with expertise in this area told an audience of lawyers and doctors in Cambridge recently that he did not accept "brain stem death" as death and believed that "something was still coming through" in patients so diagnosed. That being so, he would not allow his organs to be taken without full general anaesthesia.

11.  The frequently repeated assertion that 90% of the UK population is in favour of organ transplantation—the current system for organ procurement being implied—is another specious claim. It is used quite improperly as persuasion to offer one's organs (on the basis of the bogus agreement involving different interpretations of its crucial wording) if one might be prepared to accept another's organs one day. The true figure for public acceptance of transplant procedures—explained in full and without euphemism or "spin"—would be of great interest. There are indications that it would prove to be less than 50%.

12.  In the world at large, if not yet in the UK, there is increasing realization that viable organs for transplantation cannot be obtained from the truly dead. In consequence there are proposals for legislation permitting the removal of organs from fully informed consenting donors towards the end of their lives under specified conditions, thus obviating all obfuscation and deception (while admitting that the procurement procedure is the proximate cause of death). In this climate of refreshing regard for the truth and fair dealing it seems perverse to attempt to increase the supply of organs by another less than completely open strategy depending on ignorance and inertia.

13.  Organizations such as the Church of England which should offer guidance to its members on these life-and-death issues have persistently failed to grasp the nature of redefinitions of death for utilitarian purposes. However, the Chief Rabbi has recently issued a ruling against acceptance of "brain stem death" as human death, and against the carrying of Donor Cards. The Roman Catholic church stands back from the controversy despite its 2005 Pontifical Academy conference which came out against "brain death" (see Finis Vitae - is brain death still life? Ed. Roberto de Mattei, published by Rubbettino for the National research Council of Italy, 2006).

14.  I have laboured the matter of the necessarily premature diagnosis of death for organ procurement purposes because it is the fundamental problem for those who seek transplantable organs of the highest quality. It is intrinsic to all systems for their so-called post-mortem acquisition but it has never been fairly presented to the public generally or to individuals considering prospective donation or to relatives of those identified as potential donors. Any move towards "presumed consent" highlights that problem and demands that it be addressed squarely.

David W Evans MD, FRCP

Sometime Consultant Cardiologist at Papworth and Addenbrooke's Hospitals

February 2011



 
previous page contents next page


© Parliamentary copyright 2011
Prepared 4 April 2011