Advanced genetic techniques for crop improvement: regulation, risk and precaution - Science and Technology Committee Contents


5  Precaution, risk and uncertainty

96. In attempting to better understand the reasons for the current EU regulatory situation with regard to genetically modified organisms (GMOs), we paid particular attention to the way in which the precautionary principle had been interpreted and applied. Speaking in general terms, the Government Chief Scientific Adviser, Professor Sir Mark Walport, told us that he was "afraid" that:

    the precautionary principle has been used as a method of putting a red stop light in front of innovation rather than recognising that innovation is something where you need to consider both the benefits and risks. Sometimes there may be an amber light and it may be necessary to collect more evidence; on other occasions it may be that the balance of not doing something is worse than doing something.[329]

In this chapter, we explore the extent to which Sir Mark's characterisation of the precautionary principle as a potential barrier to innovation is justified and consider how the balance between precaution and innovation might be better managed.

EU GMO regulation: a misuse of the precautionary principle?

97. As was previously described (see paragraphs 49-51), the precautionary principle is generally considered to have played a significant role in informing the current EU regulatory framework for genetically modified organisms. This framework was initially developed in the 1990s, at a time when, according to the Royal Society, there was "an absence of evidence of whether GMOs posed different or greater risks to human health and/or the environment than organisms developed using existing methods".[330] However, it stated that "our understanding of genomes and experience of using GM crops has expanded considerably" since then and added that, "where risks have been identified", they have been shown to "relate to the trait that has been introduced rather than the method by which it was introduced".[331] It added:

    the consensus of scientific bodies is that the scientific evidence no longer justifies the precaution of controlling organisms specifically because they were generated using recombinant DNA technology.[332]

Professor Joyce Tait, Innogen Institute, agreed that while precaution may have been justified "when we were first considering how to regulate GM crops", when "we did not have very much information about their risks and benefits", it would now "be very reasonable to relax the precautionary principle and make the regulatory system adaptive in the context of the new knowledge we now have about GM crop development".[333] GM Freeze, however argued that the EU's precautionary approach to GMO regulation remained "entirely appropriate because a number of negative effects have been identified", including "the documented environmental impact of planting Roundup Ready crops, and other effects for which it is not currently possible to evaluate either the likelihood or impact to an acceptable level of certainty".[334] Professor Paul Nightingale, University of Sussex, agreed that the principle was "being properly applied" in the case of GMOs because "the conditions for its application are met": that is, scientific uncertainty and the potential for serious and irreversible harm.[335]

98. In attempting to unpick these arguments and establish whether or not continued recourse to the precautionary principle is appropriate for all products generated via genetic modification, we drew on the European Commission's own 2000 Communication on the topic, which aims to establish guidelines for the principle's application. This document stresses that "the implementation of an approach based on the precautionary principle should start with a scientific evaluation" and that recourse to the principle "presupposes that potentially dangerous effects deriving from a phenomenon, product or process have been identified".[336] It stipulates that "the precautionary principle can under no circumstances be used to justify the adoption of arbitrary decisions" and that subsequent risk management measures "may not be of an arbitrary nature".[337] The European Commission does not precisely define the precautionary principle in this document; however, it stipulates its relevance to:

    those specific circumstances where scientific evidence is insufficient, inconclusive or uncertain and there are indications through preliminary objective scientific evaluation that there are reasonable grounds for concern that the potentially dangerous effects on the environment, human, animal or plant health may be inconsistent with the chosen level of protection.[338] [Emphasis added.]

99. The evidence that we have detailed elsewhere in this report enables us to demonstrate that not one of these requirements continues to be universally met for crops produced via genetic modification. Taking these in turn:

·  As we have previously concluded, the weight of scientific evidence collected over many years demonstrates that the premise that genetically modified crops pose greater risk than their conventional counterparts is unjustified (see paragraph 61-62). We are satisfied that the scientific evidence relating to the use of genetically modified crops is neither insufficient, inconclusive nor uncertain.

·  We have also concluded that any risk that genetically modified crops have been shown to pose derives from the trait displayed rather than any inherent risk posed by the technology itself (see also paragraph 63-64). In other words, objective scientific evaluation has provided no indication that there are reasonable grounds for concern that these products might lead to potentially dangerous effects on the environment, human, animal or plant health.

·  Society has indicated, through its use of other technologies posing comparable risk, (for example, non-GM herbicide tolerant crops), that it considers the level of risk posed by genetically modified organisms to be acceptable (see paragraph 63). That is, the risk posed is not inconsistent with society's chosen level of protection

According to Dr Mike Bushell, Syngenta, "what we are seeing in many cases is not the application of the precautionary principle as defined in the Commission's own documents, but actually a smokescreen of uncertainty being put around technology to stop it happening for politically motivated reasons".[339]

100. We agree with the European Commission that a precautionary approach is appropriate in circumstances where scientific evidence is insufficient, inconclusive or uncertain and when there is reason to believe that potentially dangerous effects on the environment, human, animal or plant health might result if precaution is not exercised. However, it is clear from the evidence that we have received that these conditions are not met simply because a crop has been produced via genetic modification. Continued recourse to the precautionary principle in relation to all genetically modified crops is therefore no longer appropriate. Indeed, it has acted as a barrier to progress in this field.

101. The European Commission's Communication on the precautionary principle states that "reliance on the precautionary principle" is "no excuse for derogating from the general principles of risk management".[340] It lists these as:

·  Proportionality, which requires that "measures based on the precautionary principle must not be disproportionate to the desired level of protection and must not aim at zero risk";

·  Non-discrimination, which requires that "comparable situations should not be treated differently and that different situations should not be treated in the same way, unless there are objective grounds for doing so";

·  Consistency, according to which "measures should be consistent with the measures already adopted in similar circumstances or using similar approaches"'

·  Examination of scientific developments, followed by re-examination and modification of precautionary measures as appropriate; and

·  Examination of the benefits and costs of action or lack of action, from both economic and wider societal perspectives.[341]

Our work during this inquiry strongly suggests that these requirements are not being met in the case of GMO regulation. We have already referred to the strong scientific consensus regarding the comparative safety of existing GMO products relative to their conventional counterparts. In light of this, several witnesses considered the current regulatory regime to be both "disproportionate" and inflexible to scientific developments.[342] Witnesses also pointed out the rigorous risk assessment required for GMOs compared with other plant technologies (for example, non-GM herbicide-tolerant crops)[343] and the stringent risk management measures applied to these products compared with other comparable products (for example, pesticides).[344] This suggests a breach of the principles of both non-discrimination and consistency. The failure of the current regulatory system to take into consideration the benefits of action or costs of inaction was also frequently highlighted (see paragraph 72-74).

102. There are vast discrepancies between the European Commission's stated approach to applying the precautionary principle and its adoption in practice. Uncertainty about how the principle is being used at EU level is not helped by the lack of a consistent definition. We recommend that the European Commission consult with stakeholders in order to update its 2000 'Communication' on the precautionary principle. The updated document should include a clear definition of the principle and should stipulate the necessary conditions for it to be used as a basis for EU policy. In future, when the European Commission draws upon the precautionary principle in its policy making, it should publicly state: a) how the controlled activity meets its specified conditions for recourse to the precautionary principle; b) how measures adopted in response align with the general principles of risk management (described above), and c) what is being done to resolve uncertainties and render continued precautionary measures unnecessary.

103. We remind the Commission that any legislation guided by the precautionary principle must allow for an exit from precautionary measures once there is strong scientific consensus that any risks are low.

Responding to uncertainty

104. As the above evidence indicates, Sir Mark's claim that the precautionary principle has, in some instances, acted as "a red stop light in front of innovation" appears to be borne out in the case of EU GMO regulation.[345] In part, this appears to be due to a lack of clarity and consistency in its interpretation and application. However, appropriate use of the precautionary principle also appears to be confounded by another factor: a blurring of scientific and other forms of uncertainty.

105. As previously stated, in 2005 the UN World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology described the precautionary principle as the belief that:

    When human activities may lead to morally unacceptable harm that is scientifically plausible but uncertain, actions shall be taken to avoid or diminish that harm.[346]

This definition, like several others,[347] hinges on the presence of scientific uncertainty. However, even when scientific uncertainty has been largely resolved, other forms of uncertainty can remain. According to Professor Andy Stirling, University of Sussex, value-based uncertainties—or "ambiguities"—can arise "even for events that are certain or have occurred already": in the case of genetically modified foods, for example, "ambiguities arise over ecological, agronomic, safety, economic or social criteria of harm", which are independent of scientific questions of relative risk.[348] Several witnesses argued that the EU's use of the precautionary principle had been driven by political concerns associated with these areas of ambiguity rather than by genuine scientific uncertainty. Dr Julian Little, Agricultural Biotechnology Council, referred to the case of maize 1507 (see box 5), in which he argued that the precautionary principle had been used to undermine science-based risk assessment "as a way of stopping this [product] getting to the market".[349] Dr Paul Burrows, Biotechnology and Biological Sciences Research Council, stated that "if the [European] Commission is applying the precautionary principle" to genetically modified crops, then "personally, I do not think it is applying it because of the science".[350] The Government and its Chief Scientific Adviser appeared to have similar concerns. Sir Mark stated that the principle had become "politicised with a small 'p'" and the Minister agreed that "the idea of precaution" was being "misused to block or deter innovations such as GM, which are politically controversial" and that the EU's "misuse of the precautionary principle" was "one instance" of "a poor approach to the formulation and implementation of science-based regulation".[351]

106. The evidence that we received suggested that the source of uncertainty about a given technology—and the extent to which it is science-based, as opposed to value-based—is key to establishing whether or not continued recourse to the precautionary principle is appropriate.[352] According to the Science Council:

    The precautionary principle is […] usefully applied when there remains uncertainty or no scientific consensus about the level of risks around a product or process. But when there is strong scientific consensus that the same product or process is considered to be low-risk then the precautionary principle is logically obsolete.[353]

Professor Stirling stated that the precautionary principle "comes into its own" under those "more intractable states of incertitude" where risk assessment is unable to provide a rational basis for decision-making.[354] While risk assessment can be a valid response to scientific uncertainty, Professor Stirling argued that it was "misleading to claim that single definitive science-based decisions"—such as those derived from risk assessment—were possible in such situations and suggested that other approaches, such as "substantive public engagement", offered an alternative approach to understanding and responding to these types of uncertainties.[355]

107. Several other witnesses also highlighted the importance of public engagement as an alternative response to uncertainty. The Royal Society stated that "public and stakeholder dialogue should be a part of all" risk governance frameworks and Sir Roland Jackson, Nuffield Council on Bioethics, agreed that "public engagement and […] wider stakeholder engagement" had "quite a role to play".[356] In its recent report on Emerging biotechnologies, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics also strongly emphasised the moral value of public discourse. According to this report, the "significant public interest" arising from emerging biotechnologies (such as advanced genetic breeding techniques) means that they should be subject to a "public ethics", based on securing public good, rather than a more "individualistic ethics that attempts only to protect the freedoms of individuals in ways compatible with the freedom of others within a society".[357] The report argued that, while "in a plural society there will not be a single vision of the public good that can be applied in all circumstances", the construction of a public discourse based on certain procedural and institutional virtues[358] could offer a "practical way of responding collectively" to the challenges posed by emerging biotechnologies through "'public' decision making, orientated by pursuit of the public good".[359]

108. Various models intended to more formally incorporate public and stakeholder engagement into the risk analysis process have been developed. One of these is the International Risk Governance Council's Risk Governance Framework, which modifies the traditional three-stage risk analysis process (risk assessment, risk management, risk communication) to include two additional stages: "risk pre-assessment", in which different potential framings of the problem are considered, and "characterisation and Evaluation", in which scientific data are considered alongside societal factors in order to evaluate whether the risk is "acceptable, tolerable (requiring mitigation), or intolerable (unacceptable)".[360] Professor Joyce Tait, Innogen Institute, described this framework as "quite an advanced approach to looking at these kinds of questions where value judgment comes into play".[361] Similarly, the final report of the EU-funded Safe Foods Initiative offered a structured approach to the assessment and management of food safety threats in which framing and consideration of societal factors played a more formalised role than is typical in current approaches.[362]

109. We have already acknowledged the considerable relevance of societal concerns to decision-making about risk and reiterate the need for non-scientific factors to be considered alongside scientific risk assessment during the risk governance process. However, the precautionary principle was designed primarily as a response to scientific uncertainty, not value-based ambiguity. Such ambiguities are common in emerging areas of science and technology and are also often intractable; recourse to the precautionary principle in these scenarios would therefore potentially act as a permanent barrier to the use of safe innovations. Where value-based ambiguities exist, public discourse, not scientific risk assessment, should be pursued as a route to greater legitimacy.

110. We recommend that the Government give greater consideration to the value that participatory processes might contribute to its own treatment of risk and uncertainty in policy development. We particularly refer the Government to the Risk Governance Framework and Safe Foods Initiative and ask it to set out how the perspectives offered by these documents will inform its future approach to risk governance policy. The next chapter gives further consideration to the subject of public information and discourse.

Government use and interpretation of the precautionary principle

111. Our interpretation of the precautionary principle is broadly in line with both the stated position of the European Commission (see paragraph 95) and that of the UN's World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology, which stipulates that the principle should be applied where the risk of "morally unacceptable harm" is "scientifically plausible but uncertain".[363] However, the Government Chief Scientific Adviser, Professor Sir Mark Walport, offered a somewhat different interpretation. In an April 2013 opinion piece in the Financial Times, Sir Mark framed the precautionary principle not as a response to scientific uncertainty, but as a guide to evidence-based decision-making. According to Sir Mark:

    Decisions must be informed by the best evidence and expert advice. The application of the "precautionary principle" can help to guide this. This simple idea just means working out and balancing in advance all the risks and benefits of action or inaction, and to make a proportionate response. All too often, people citing this principle simply overreact: if there is any potential hazard associated with an activity, then it should not be done, or, if it is already being done, it should be stopped.[364]

Sir Mark described the precautionary principle to us in similar terms during this inquiry, stating that the principle "basically" means: "Do a full evaluation of the science before you make a decision" and "think about the consequences of both action and inaction".[365] The Minister stated that he "broadly agree[d]" with this definition and, like Sir Mark, stressed that the principle required that "a full science-based evaluation" be carried out before a decision be made.[366] In his first annual themed report, Innovation: managing risk, not avoiding it, Sir Mark expressed concern about an apparent "drift of interpretation of the precautionary principle from what was, in effect, a holding position pending further evidence, to what is now effectively a stop sign".[367] However, despite focusing heavily on the subjects of innovation, risk and uncertainty, this report contained no specific recommendations about how the principle might be more systematically applied.

112. Sir Mark's argument that the precautionary principle requires "all the risks and benefits of action or inaction" to be "work[ed] out and balanc[ed] in advance"[368] could be seen to vary significantly from those definitions that place the existence of scientific uncertainty at their centre.[369] In a chapter in the supporting case studies for Sir Mark's annual themed report, Professor Andy Stirling, University of Sussex, stated that although the precautionary principle "comes in many forms, a classic general expression of precaution is that scientific uncertainty is not a reason for inaction in preventing serious damage to human health or the environment".[370] He continued:

    By explicitly hinging on uncertainty rather than risk, precaution helps to promote recognition that social choices in innovation are not reducible to ostensibly precise, value-free, technical risk assessments.[371]

In another 2013 opinion piece, commentator George Monbiot criticised Sir Mark for his "misunderstanding of the precautionary principle"—a concept that he considered to be "fundamental to Walport's role" as Chief Scientific Adviser.[372] He rejected Sir Mark's focus on scientific evaluation and compared this with the definition of the precautionary principle offered by the Rio Declaration:

    where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation.[373]

Science policy experts Professor Roger Pielke Jr and James Wilsdon defended Sir Mark against Monbiot's claim that he had "misinformed the public about the scientific method, risk and uncertainty",[374] but stated that it was "fair to criticise Walport for a rather lazy caricature of the precautionary principle".[375]

113. The Government recognises the importance of properly understanding and applying the precautionary principle, but it is not clear that it has done so. Government explanations emphasise the need for decisions made under the guidance of the precautionary principle to be based on a "full science-based evaluation", but fail to recognise that such evaluations are often impossible in those circumstances when precaution is most needed—that is, in situations of scientific uncertainty or ignorance. The Government Chief Scientific Adviser's first annual themed report, on the subject of innovation and risk, has done little to clarify this situation. The Government should prepare a short document, informed by wider consultation, detailing its understanding of the principle and the circumstances in which it intends to use the precautionary principle as a guide to policy making. This should be made publicly available by the end of 2015.


329   Q288 Back

330   GMC044 [Royal Society] para 20 Back

331   GMC044 [Royal Society] para 21 Back

332   GMC044 [Royal Society] para 21 Back

333   Q220 [Professor Tait] Back

334   GMC020 para [GM Freeze] 1.5 Back

335   GMC045 [Professor Nightingale] para 33 Back

336   European Commission, Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle, COM(2000)1, February 2000, p.4 Back

337   European Commission, Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle, COM(2000)1, February 2000, p.13 Back

338   European Commission, Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle, COM(2000)1, February 2000, p.10 Back

339   Q187 [Dr Bushell] Back

340   European Commission, Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle, COM(2000)1, February 2000, p.18  Back

341   European Commission, Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle, COM(2000)1, February 2000, para 6.3 Back

342   See, for example, GMC037 [ADHB] para 9, GMC029 [SCIMAC] exec summary, GMC027 [Professor Baulcombe] para 3 and GMC013 [Professor Pollock] exec summary Back

343   See, for example, Q418 [Professor Hails]; Q22 [Professor Leyser] Back

344   See, for example, Q318 [Professor Perry] Back

345   Q288 Back

346   United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology, The Precautionary Principle, March 2005, p.14 Back

347   For example: that of the European Commission (precaution is appropriate in "those specific circumstances where scientific evidence is insufficient, inconclusive or uncertain", see paragraph 96), the Rio Declaration ("lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation"), the Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety (which draws on the Rio definition), and the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change ("where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty should not be used as a reason for postponing" measures to "anticipate, prevent or minimise the causes of climate change and mitigate its adverse effect"). Back

348   Andrew Stirling "Risk, precaution and science: towards a more constructive policy debate", EMBO reports, vol 8 (2007), pp.310 Back

349   Q187 [Dr Little] Back

350   Q165 Back

351   Q291; Q471; GMC051 [Gov] para 38 Back

352   See also Andrew Stirling "Risk, precaution and science: towards a more constructive policy debate", EMBO reports, vol 8 (2007), pp.309-315 Back

353   GMC047 [Science Council] para 5.4 Back

354   Andrew Stirling "Risk, precaution and science: towards a more constructive policy debate", EMBO reports, vol 8 (2007), pp.312 Back

355   Andrew Stirling, "Opening Up the Politics of Knowledge and Power in Bioscience", PLoS Biology, volume 10 (2012), p.4 Back

356   GMC044 [Royal Society] para 5; Q227 [Sir Roland Jackson] Back

357   Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Emerging biotechnologies: technology, choice and the public good, December 2012, para 17; executive summary, chapter 4 overview Back

358   The report defined these virtues as openness and inclusion, accountability, public reasoning, candour, enablement and caution. Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Emerging biotechnologies: technology, choice and the public good, December 2012, para 23 Back

359   Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Emerging biotechnologies: technology, choice and the public good, December 2012, para 23; executive summary, chapter 4 overview Back

360   International risk governance council, 'IRGC risk framework', irgc.org, accessed 26 January 2015. Back

361   Q258 [Professor Tait] Back

362   Marion Dreyer, Ortwin Renn, Adrian Ely, Andy Stirling, Ellen Vos and Frank Wendler, 'A General Framework for the Precautionary and Inclusive Governance of Food Safety in Europe', Final Report of subproject 5 of the EU Integrated Project SAFE FOODS, June 2008. Back

363   United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology, The Precautionary Principle, March 2005, p.14 Back

364   "There is no easy solution to the problem of the bees", Financial Times, 26 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015. Back

365   Q288 Back

366   Q471 Back

367   Government Office for Science, Innovation: managing risk, not avoiding it, Annual Report of the Government Chief Scientific Adviser, November 2014, p.8 Back

368   "There is no easy solution to the problem of the bees", Financial Times, 26 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015. Back

369   For example, that of the United Nations World Commission (paragraphs 49), the European Commission (paragraph 95)  Back

370   Government Office for Science, Innovation: managing risk, not avoiding it, Evidence and Case Studies, 'Chapter 4: Making choices in the face of uncertainty: strengthening innovation democracy', November 2014, p.59. Back

371   Government Office for Science, Innovation: managing risk, not avoiding it, Evidence and Case Studies, 'Chapter 4: Making choices in the face of uncertainty: strengthening innovation democracy', November 2014, p.59. Back

372   "Beware the rise of the government scientists turned lobbyists", Guardian Online, 29 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015. Back

373   "Beware the rise of the government scientists turned lobbyists", Guardian Online, 29 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015 Back

374   "Beware the rise of the government scientists turned lobbyists", Guardian Online, 29 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015 Back

375   "Why Monbiot's attack on Walport misses the mark", Guardian Online, 30 April 2013, accessed 26 January 2015 Back


 
previous page contents next page


© Parliamentary copyright 2015
Prepared 26 February 2015