NOTES ON THE
DRAFT MENTAL
HEALTH BILL
Professor Anselm Eldergill
This paper was drafted
for the Institute
of Mental Health Act Practitioners,
in order to assist the Institute with its submissions on the draft Mental
Health Bill.
Passages which were not incorporated in
IMHAP’s submission are marked in red.
Each of the
following headings refers to a theme on which the Committee has indicated it
particularly wishes to receive evidence:
§1
|
Basic Principles
|
Page 2
|
§2
|
Definition of Mental Disorder and Related
Definitions
|
Page 2
|
§3
|
Conditions for Compulsion and Detention
|
Page 4
|
§4
|
Separation of Powers and the Executive
|
Page 8
|
§5
|
Safeguards concerning Forced Medication
and ECT
|
Page 8
|
§6
|
Safeguards against Abuse
|
Page 10
|
§7
|
Safeguards — Abolition of Mental Health
Commission
|
Page 14
|
§8
|
Omissions
|
Page 17
|
§9
|
Compliance with the Human Rights Act
|
Page 17
|
§10
|
Balance between Collective and Individual
Rights
|
Page 18
|
§11
|
Integration with the Mental Capacity Bill
|
Page 19
|
§12
|
Practicality of the Proposals
|
Page 19
|
§13
|
Concluding Remarks
|
Page 22
|
§14
|
Contact Details
|
Page 22
|
|
Appendix A — Principles of Mental Health
Legislation
|
|
|
Appendix B — The Principles of
Legislating for Risk
|
|
|
Appendix C — Legislating for Personality
Disorder
|
|
§1 THEME — BASIC PRINCIPLES
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘1. Is the Draft Mental Health Bill rooted in
a set of unambiguous basic principles? Are these principles appropriate and
desirable?’
The Government has not set out a set of ‘unambiguous basic
principles’.
It has stated that the existing Act does not adequately
protect people from ‘the significant risk posed by a minority of patients’, and
that it ‘remains based on treatment in hospital, and too often has allowed
severely ill people outside hospital to drift out of contact with services.’
However, the proportion of violence in society attributable
to mental illness remains low, and people are better protected from violence of
this kind than from most other kinds. Violence has much more to do with
education, upbringing, alcohol, drugs and testosterone than mental illness.
That is not to say that it is appropriate to detain and treat people in these
classes under mental health laws.
The principles upon which any new legislation is based should
include those set out in Appendices:
- A (‘Principles of Mental Health
Legislation’)
- B (‘The Principles of Legislating
for Risk’) and
- C (‘Legislating for Personality
Disorder’).
§2 THEME — DEFINITION OF MENTAL DISORDER AND
RELATED DEFINITIONS
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘2. Is the definition of mental disorder
appropriate and unambiguous?’
The definition of ‘mental disorder’ must be
understood together with the definitions of ‘medical treatment’ and ‘hospitals’,
and it is necessary to consider their combined effect.
The approach taken in the Bill is essentially
a reworking of the consultation document on ‘dangerous severe personality
disorder’ that was published by the Home Office and the Department of Health in
July 1999.
In this document, the two departments advocated
that risk alone, as well as mental disorder and criminal punishment, can
justify detention. As a result, consideration was given to detaining such
people in ‘third units’, in essence adult secure accommodation of the kind
presently provided for some behaviourally-disturbed children.
The ‘third-unit’ option seems to have been
abandoned, probably because it was thought that indefinitely detaining
non-offenders in civilian accommodation risks infringing the European
Convention on Human Rights.
Article 5(1) permits the detention of
convicted persons and those of unsound mind in appropriate facilities (prisons
and hospitals, respectively), but does not in clear terms permit the detention
of citizens who have not offended merely because there is a risk they will do
so in future.
Detention in secure non-hospital
accommodation rather rules out pleading mental disorder, and a need for
treatment, as the justification, and nor can punishment or lawful sentence be
pleaded, because the individuals are not serving a term of imprisonment.
Probably for these reasons, therefore, the
Government seems to have retreated, at least for the present, to the
justification that such people are mentally disordered: they require medical
treatment in hospital or medical treatment under supervision in the community.
Meaning of ‘mental disorder’
|
Key Point
The definition of ‘mental disorder’ is too broad.
|
Further Explanation
Unlike the present Act, the Bill does not
provide that no one may be dealt with as mentally disordered by reason only
of promiscuity, immoral conduct, sexual deviancy or dependence on alcohol or
drugs. Thus, one is entitled to assume that the Government intends that it
will be lawful to compulsorily treat individuals on the sole ground that
their behaviour is of such a kind. See Clause 2(5).
|
Meaning of ‘medical treatment’
|
Key Points
The definition of ‘medical treatment’, which
includes education and work training, is too broad.
|
Further Explanation
References
in the Bill to ‘medical treatment’ are references to treatment for mental
disorder provided under the supervision of an ‘approved clinician.’ The term
‘treatment’ includes education, work training, and training in social skills.
See Clause 2(7).
|
|
Consequently, a person who is
drug-dependent and whose behaviour is anti-social and alarming may be said to
have a mental disorder that warrants providing medical treatment, in the form
of work training or social skills training, under psychological supervision.
|
Meaning of ‘a hospital’
|
The definition of
‘a hospital’ includes private houses that provide compulsory education, work
training or social skills training under psychological supervision to people
with personality, alcohol or drug dependency problems.
|
What
constitutes a hospital is broadly defined: see Clause 2(3). A private
establishment, such as a converted Edwardian house, is a hospital if its main
purpose is to provide medical treatment for mental disorder to persons
subject to Part 2 or 3.
Because people
with ‘personality disorders’, substance abuse problems or sexual deviancy may
now be categorized as having a mental disorder, and education or training
under psychological supervision constitutes medical treatment, an establishment
offering such a service is a ‘hospital’.
Provided it is
suitably registered, it may detain people who meet the conditions for
compulsion.
|
Combined effect of the new
definitions
|
The consequence is
that social interventions that most people do not think of as medical
treatments, given to individuals who most people do not regard as mentally
disordered, constitute medical treatments for mental disorder.
|
Defining
anti-social people as mentally disordered, supervised social interventions as
medical treatments, and establishments which detain such people or provide
social services as hospitals, enables adult secure accommodation to be
dressed up for European Convention purposes as hospital treatment for persons
of unsound mind.
|
§3 THEME — CONDITIONS FOR COMPULSION
and DETENTION
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘2. Are the conditions for treatment and care
under compulsion sufficiently stringent? Are the provisions for assessment and
treatment in the community adequate and sufficient?’
For obvious
reasons, this part of the paper is divided into three parts:
·
The conditions for short-term compulsion (up to
72 hours)
·
The conditions for compulsory assessment and
treatment under Part 2
·
The conditions for compulsory treatment under
Part 3 (criminal provisions)
The new short-term powers
|
Key Points
It is constitutionally inappropriate that a doctor
may detain someone s/he believes requires assessment in the community.
|
Further
Explanation
The Bill
provides that a doctor may authorise the detention for up to 72 hours of an
informal in-patient who appears to require, not detention in hospital, but
assessment in the community. See Schedule 6.
|
It is constitutionally inappropriate that who is
authorised to detain an informal patient is not defined and left to
regulations.
|
A ‘person
falling within a description described … in regulations’ may likewise detain
such a person for up to six hours: See Schedule 6. Who is authorised to use
this power will therefore be determined by the Minister after Parliament has
enacted the legislation. It may be that the power will remain reserved to
suitably qualified nurses. However, the Bill does not require this.
|
It is constitutionally inappropriate that a single
doctor may authorise a citizen’s compulsory admission and detention if the
approved mental health professional accompanying her/him is not also of the
opinion that detention is appropriate or that there is any urgent necessity
for this.
|
The new
‘section 4’ emergency hospital admission procedure is set out in Clause 17.
It provides that the patient shall be admitted to hospital if the doctor —
rather than both professionals, as at present — determines that the person’s
assessment is an urgent necessity, and that awaiting a second medical
examination would involve undesirable delay.
|
Because the professional opinion is evenly divided,
the citizen’s detention is not then founded on reliable evidence, which is a
Convention requirement.
|
This is
unsatisfactory. Although the approved mental health professional’s opinion is
that the relevant conditions for compulsion are met, it may also be their
opinion that admission and detention are inappropriate.
If so, the
individual’s detention is then founded on one medical opinion with which the
approved professional disagrees, and that possibly from a general
practitioner, or a doctor with no previous acquaintance of the patient.
Furthermore,
even if the approved professional believes that detention is appropriate,
s/he may not agree that detention or assessment is urgently necessary, or
that it is undesirable to await the second medical examination, for example from
a consultant psychiatrist.
|
|
The conditions that govern when a warrant to remove
a citizen to a place of safety may be issued require amendment, in order to
bring them into line with practice.
|
The new section 135(1) power (Warrant to remove a person to a
place of safety) is set out in Clause 227. It adopts the existing statutory
grounds and, because they remain unchanged, so they remain defective. Whether
a person can care for themselves, or is being ill-treated or neglected, is
not the same issue as whether the only way in which a statutory assessment
can be undertaken is by forced entry and removal. Although this is the usual reason
for using the power in practice, it continues not to be a ground for issuing
the warrant.
|
It is constitutionally inappropriate to use mental
health legislation to allow constables to remove citizens who are drug or
alcohol dependent from their homes without any need for a warrant. We are
concerned that the power may be misused.
|
The most controversial short-term provision is the urgent
removal power in Clause 228. Necessarily, this power, as with all of the others,
extends to people who are alcohol or drug dependent, or ‘sexually deviant’.
In other words, they too are liable to be removed to a place of safety by a
constable acting without a warrant.
|
The ‘relevant conditions’ for
compulsion under Part 2
|
The relevant conditions for compulsion must be
understood in the context of the statutory definitions of ‘mental disorder’
and ‘medical treatment’
|
The statutory criteria for compulsion
under the civil provisions in Part 2 are called ‘the relevant conditions’. See
Clause 9.
The conditions for compulsion must be
understood in the context of the very broad definitions of ‘mental disorder’
and ‘medical treatment’ referred to above.
|
The meaning of the word ‘lawfully’ in Clause 9(5)
needs to be clarified.
|
In most cases, compulsion under Part
2 is only permissible if ‘medical treatment cannot lawfully be provided to
the patient without him being subject to the provisions of this Part.’
The word ‘lawfully’ has been added
here, and it is ambiguous.
Is it intended to mean that the
person cannot be ‘sectioned’ if s/he consents to informal treatment, or does
it mean that an incapacitated person cannot be ‘sectioned’ if s/he can be
treated instead under the Mental Capacity Bill or the common law doctrine of
necessity? This is an important point that needs to be clarified.
|
In contrast to the present Act, the Bill allows for
the compulsory treatment of people who are not treatable. If they are not
treatable why force treatment on them?
|
The Bill abolishes the existing
‘treatability test’.
In other words, where a person has a
learning disability or personality disorder, it will no longer be a condition
of longer-term compulsory treatment that treatment is likely to alleviate
their condition or prevent its deterioration.
The equivalent condition in the draft
Bill is that ‘appropriate medical treatment is available’. This ‘appropriate’
medical treatment may, of course, consist of nothing more than education or
work training not provided under any medical supervision.
‘Appropriate’ is a very general word,
and the Bill does not say that treatment is only appropriate if it is likely
to alleviate the patient’s condition or prevent its deterioration.
|
Because what constitutes ‘medical treatment’ may be
extended by making regulations that extend who is an ‘approved clinician’
under the Bill, so the relevant conditions for compulsion may be extended by
regulations.
|
Because ‘treatment’ only constitutes
‘medical treatment’ if it is ‘provided under the supervision of an approved
clinician’, and who is or may be approved will be determined by the Secretary
of State after the legislation has been passed, it can be seen that the
grounds for compulsion can periodically be varied by secondary legislation.
This is unsatisfactory, and may be
unlawful. For example, because it enables the conditions for compulsion to be
varied periodically by Ministers without going back to Parliament.
|
The criteria for detention in
hospital under Part 2
|
Provided a citizen meets the relevant conditions for
compulsion, the Bill leaves to regulations the issue of whether s/he should
be liable to be detained in a hospital. This is constitutionally
inappropriate, and is unlikely to comply with the European Convention.
|
The new Clause
15(2) provides that, ‘If the patient falls within a description specified by
the appropriate authority in regulations, each of the examiners must, in
carrying out an examination, also determine whether it is appropriate for the
patient to be detained in a hospital while an assessment of him is carried
out.’
It is therefore
proposed that Parliament should be silent as to the circumstances in which
citizens will be liable to detention, imposing no conditions or safeguards,
entrusting instead the ‘liberty of the subject’ to the executive and
regulations made by the Minister from time to time.
|
The Bill provides that a citizen may be detained
even though the medical evidence is evenly divided as to the need for
detention. Again, we are sure that this does not comply with the European
Convention, which requires that detention is founded on reliable evidence.
|
Clause 16(5)
then provides that provides that a person who meets the conditions for
compulsion may be detained in hospital if an approved mental health
professional and one doctor consider it ‘appropriate’, notwithstanding that
the other doctor, who may have special expertise in psychiatry, considers it
to be inappropriate. Thus, the individual’s detention is authorised even
though the medical opinion is evenly split, with the expert opinion being
against detention.
The test for
detention is as subjective as such tests can be. Not ‘is the individual’s
mental disorder sufficiently severe to warrant deprivation of liberty?’, or
‘is depriving this individual of their liberty justified by the risk of
harm?’, but ‘does a professional person think it is appropriate to detain
them while an assessment is carried out?’
|
Admission to hospital of non-resident
patients
|
In certain circumstances, the Bill authorises the
detention of a citizen to be founded upon a single medical opinion, and this
an opinion that may conflict with the determinations previously made by three
practitioners. Again, having regard to Convention requirements, the
lawfulness of this must be doubtful.
|
The Bill
provides that the consultant of a non-resident patient may sign a statutory
form, upon the completion of which the patient may be conveyed to hospital
and detained there: See Clauses 28, 48 and 51.
Thus, although detention at the time of the original examination is
only possible if an approved mental health professional agrees it is appropriate,
once that examination has been completed the patient’s detention may be
founded on one medical opinion — an opinion which conflicts with, and
overturns, the decision of three examiners or a tribunal as to its
inappropriateness. Reexamination by three examiners would be preferable.
|
Imposing conditions on non-resident
patients
|
The conditions which may be imposed on a
non-resident patient are not properly specified.
|
The conditions
that may be imposed on a non-resident patient include those specified in
Clause 15(4). The use of the word ‘include’ leaves open, and unclear, what
other conditions may lawfully be imposed, and this is unsatisfactory.
|
The conditions for compulsion
under Part 3
|
The conditions for
compulsion under Part 3 are too lax. It suffices that the offender has a
mental disorder (e.g. substance dependency) of a nature that warrants
providing medical treatment under psychological supervision (e.g. social
skills training) and that this ‘appropriate treatment’ is available.
|
The conditions
for imposing longer-term compulsory treatment under the criminal provisions
in Part 3 are much laxer. It suffices that the individual has a mental
disorder of a nature or degree that warrants providing medical treatment to
them, and that appropriate medical treatment is available (Clause 116).
|
|
This is a matter that requires the most
careful consideration, given the broad definitions of mental disorder and
medical treatment, and the number of people with personality or
substance-dependency problems who appear in court.
|
§4 THEME — SEPARATION OF POWERS AND
THE EXECUTIVE
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘7. Is the balance struck between what has
been included on the face of the draft bill, and what goes into Regulations and
the Code of Practices right?’
Balance between legislation and
regulations
|
Key Points
The drafting of the Bill is ‘back-to-front’ and
reserves constitutional issues affecting ‘the liberty of the subject’ to
regulations made by the Secretary of State.
|
Further
explanation
The drafting of
the Bill is ‘back-to-front’. It is silent about matters that one would expect
to find defined by Parliament, such as the grounds upon which a citizen can
be detained, and prescriptive about matters that are probably not intended to
be legally enforceable, e.g. the numerous requirements to consult and notify
people and to keep the status of patients under review.
|
|
As already
noted, who may detain an informal in-patient for up to six hours, when a
person is liable to detention for assessment under Part 2, and who is an
‘approved clinician’ (and, therefore, what constitutes medical treatment) are
all matters left to regulations.
The Bill even
states that the Secretary of State may prescribe matters that must be dealt
with in tribunal applications (see, e.g., Clause 39), a function that surely
belongs to the Lord Chancellor.
|
|
It also enables
the Secretary of State to regulate the giving of ECT without the usual
certificates (see Theme 5).
|
§5 THEME — SAFEGUARDS CONCERNING FORCED
MEDICATION AND ECT
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘Are there enough safeguards against misuse of
aggressive procedures such as ECT and psychosurgery?’
Safeguards concerning medication
given without consent, etc
|
Key Points
The Bill abolishes the existing right of patients to
an independent, binding, second-opinion concerning the appropriateness of the
medication they are forced to take. This seems contrary both to common-sense
and recent court decisions, so that it is doubtful whether it complies with
the European Convention.
|
Further
Explanation
Fairness and
commonsense dictate that decisions to authorise treatments that can be given
by force should be subject to safeguards.
|
The
Government’s intention appears to be that anti-psychotics and other drugs
given for mental disorder constitute ‘Other medical treatment’, and will be
governed by Clauses 198 to 200.
|
|
Clauses 199 and
200 provide that the consent of a patient who is liable to assessment or
treatment under Part 2 or 3 is not required in respect of any medical
treatment of such a kind provided it is described in her/his care plan (or
care plan as approved by the tribunal with modifications).
|
The Expert Panel should be given this function to
perform.
|
Because a
tribunal can only modify the medical treatment in a care plan with the
patient’s consultant’s consent, this amounts to abolishing the right that
patients detained for treatment presently have to a binding second-opinion on
their drug treatment from an independent consultant psychiatrist appointed by
the Mental Health Act Commission. The Bill could, but does not, transfer this
protective function to the new Expert Panel.
|
Administering medication without
consent in ‘hospital settings’
|
The broad definition of what constitutes a hospital
leads to a correspondingly broad list of places where citizens may be held
down and given medication by force.
|
The Bill allows
for administering medication without consent in a hospital (Clause 198). Medication
may be given without consent in an NHS clinic, in small ‘mental nursing
homes’ that are willing to provide this service, and small private
establishments that constitute ‘hospitals’ for legal purposes.
|
Administering medication without
consent in non-hospital settings
|
If one takes ‘patient consent’ to mean that that the
patient freely consents to treatment then it is inevitable that drug
treatments will often be given to people in their own homes without their
consent. After all, if they accept the need for treatment there is no need
for it to be given under a compulsory order.
|
In practice, it
is likely that consultants or tribunals will impose a requirement or
condition that the patient takes prescribed medication, in addition to a requirement
that s/he attends hospital as required. It will be pointed out that there
will be no need to require the patient to attend hospital, or to convey them
there, if an injection can be given at home. The patient has this option.
It may be objected
that any medicines given in such circumstances are not given with consent,
for if the person truly consented a compulsory treatment order would be
unnecessary.
|
|
Against this,
the procedures for patients liable to compulsory treatment under the 1983 Act
provide for medicines being given with or without consent. The current statutory
position is therefore that a patient may give a valid consent to medication
notwithstanding that a refusal may result in administration by force.
If this is the
case, home treatment and assertive outreach teams will be giving medication
within the home to people who would refuse it if free to decide. To the
non-lawyer, this amounts to administering medication without the person’s
consent outside hospital settings.
|
Safeguards concerning ECT given
without consent, etc
|
It will be too easy in practice for consultants to
by-pass the protective scheme set out for ECT.
|
The safeguards
concerning ECT, though modified, remain unsatisfactory. They are set out in
Clauses 177 to 190.
|
|
Under Clauses
182 to 184, a patient may effectively be given a whole course of ECT if their
consultant certifies at the outset of the course of treatment that the
treatment is immediately necessary to alleviate serious suffering. That being
so, it is unclear how often consultants will decide that it is necessary to
apply to a tribunal for authorization.
|
|
Here again, the
Secretary of State has reserved to himself the power to regulate the scheme
although, by constitutional convention, all significant encroachments on the
liberty and security ‘of the subject’ should be determined by Parliament and
entrenched in statute law.
|
§6 THEME — SAFEGUARDS AGAINST ABUSE
The
Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive evidence on the following
theme: ‘6. Are the safeguards against abuse adequate?’
Many safeguards
against the poor or inappropriate use of compulsion are abolished. In addition
to those already mentioned: The Bill:
·
fetters the new Mental Health Tribunals;
·
revokes the powers of a patient’s nearest
relative;
·
provides that the guidance in the Code of
Practice may be qualified;
·
abolishes the statutory duty to provide long-term
after-care;
·
revokes the discharge powers of NHS bodies and
local authorities;
·
may endanger professional independence;
·
does not provide for an independent, standalone,
Mental Health Commission.
Mental Health Tribunals
|
Key Points
Tribunals should continue to have a discretionary
power to discharge people from compulsion.
|
Further
Explanation
The
powers of the new tribunals are limited. In particular, they have no
discretion to discharge a person who meets the statutory conditions for
compulsion. Here too, practitioners are prohibited from taking into account
matters not referred to in the Government’s test. As a result, more patients
will be subject to perennial compulsion, because some people with chronic
illnesses never satisfy the statutory test for discharge.
|
|
That is
not to say that they ought not to be discharged once they are functioning at
their optimum level, provided that neither they nor anyone else is at
significant risk.
|
The Bill should provide that a tribunal must release
a citizen from detention unless it is satisfied that clear grounds which
Parliament has determined justify depriving a citizen of her/his liberty are
met.
|
Whether
a patient who meets the conditions for compulsion is actually released from
detention is left entirely to the tribunal’s discretion, there being no
grounds which qualify when detention is or is not lawful.
|
If citizens who have not committed an offence are to
be subject to restrictions of the kind imposed on dangerous offenders then
similar protections should be put in place.
|
A
notable feature of the new scheme is that people who have not
committed an offence may be placed under restrictions on discharge, transfer
and leave of the kind now imposed by the Crown Court on offenders who pose a
risk of serious harm to the public.
|
Where a person applies to be discharged from
short-term compulsory assessment, it is undesirable that a tribunal should be
empowered not only to refuse their application to be released but also to
extend the period of compulsion by up to six months.
Because the rules will no doubt provide that where
two applications are outstanding they may be heard together, it is better to
leave it to the clinical supervisor to decide whether to apply for a further
order.
|
Where a person
who has been detained for up to 28 days asks the tribunal to review the
grounds for the detention, it can extend the period of compulsion by up to
six months.
Necessarily,
many patients will be wary of challenging their detention, given the purpose
and possible consequences of independent review. This wariness is likely to
be reinforced by the fact that their perception of tribunals will change.
Instead of being the independent body that can order their release, it will
be seen as the authority that imposes long-term compulsion. It must still be
doubtful that these provisions satisfy Article 5.
|
It is a matter of concern that a tribunal may
authorise a person’s further detention for up to eight weeks when it has just
determined that s/he does not satisfy the relevant conditions for compulsion,
let alone detention.
|
Where a detained Part 2 patient does not
meet the relevant conditions for compulsion in the community, the tribunal
must in some cases authorise her/his detention for a further eight weeks. See
Clauses 63 and 64.
|
Nearest relatives and nominated persons
|
Key Points
A
patient’s spouse or partner should retain their existing power to object
reasonably to admission to hospital. Why get rid of the right to lodge a
reasonable objection?
|
Further Explanation
A
person’s nearest relative has several important powers under the present Act,
two of which protect patients against the inappropriate use of compulsory
powers.
The
Bill abolishes the nearest relative as a legal entity, and with it the
family’s right to these protective powers.
|
That person should also retain the existing power to discharge
from detention a patient who is not likely to act in a manner dangerous to her/himself
or others.
If the patient has no spouse or partner, any relative who is
her/his ordinary carer (as defined in the Bill) should also have these
rights.
A scheme of this kind still
enables necessary treatment to be given as a non-resident patient.
|
The
existing powers recognise the importance of the family in people’s lives, and
the need to limit the circumstances in which the state may interfere with
individual and family life. A balance is achieved between the state’s claim
to provide protective compulsory care and the right claimed by families to
care for their loved ones, and to cope with and manage behaviour that mostly
affects only them.
|
It
is questionable whether the ‘nominated person’ is given a sufficiently useful
role to justify all of the consultation and notification requirements.
|
A
new ‘nominated person’ replaces the nearest relative. However, this person
has but one power, which is to apply to the tribunal for the patient’s
discharge.
|
The
functions of independent MHA Advocates include explaining things such as the
requirements imposed on the patient — who are they advocating for — and it is
not clear how their independence of the detaining authority (who may well be
paying them) is to be guaranteed.
|
Patients
and nominated persons have a right to help under the Bill’s advocacy
provisions. However, their statutory role
is as much concerned with explaining the consultant’s treatment, and why the
patient must comply with it, as it is with protecting or promoting the patient’s
legal rights.
Such advocates will be appointed by the NHS — and
probably often by the detaining trust in practice — and the detaining trust
may refuse the advocate access to the particular patient’s records. See
Clause 247.
|
The
rights given to carers by the Bill are welcome, but they are carers’ rights,
not patients’ rights.
|
Carers who provide regular and
substantial care must also be consulted about some decisions. However, by
definition, these rights are carers’ rights, and of course their advice may
be that the patient should remain subject to detention or compulsion.
|
Qualified Code of Practice
|
The Secretary of State has excluded her/himself from
having to comply with good practice requirements set out in a Code of
Practice, and that it is considered inappropriate in certain circumstances to
say what is good practice.
|
The
new Code of Practice may provide that one or more general principles shall
not apply in circumstances in which its application would be ‘inappropriate’,
or in relation to specified decisions or persons.
A
new sub-clause now also provides that certain matters are excluded from the
remit of the code. Almost all of these matters relate to functions of the
Secretary of State. In other words, the Secretary of State will not himself
be subject to the Code of [Good] Practice. See Clause 1 and Schedule 1.
|
Abolition of section 117
|
As a general principle, where a person has been so
ill as to require long-term detention and compulsory treatment in a
psychiatric unit, it a good thing that the after-care authorities should be
under a duty to provide them with such after-care as is reasonably necessary
to minimise the risk of relapse and readmission.
It is unfair to require people to pay for treatment
they are compelled to receive.
|
The Government indicated in the White Paper that
patients would not be charged for services they are compelled to receive.
Clauses 53 and 68 deal with free care services before
and after discharge.
Patients who are required to reside in accommodation
that is their ordinary place of residence may be charged all or part of the
cost of that accommodation.
|
Powers of hospital managers and others
|
The managers of a hospital should retain the power
to discharge a person detained by them if they are of the opinion that the
statutory conditions which make detention lawful are no longer met.
|
Hospital managers, Health Authorities, NHS trusts, and
local authorities all lose their powers to discharge individuals from
compulsion. Only the patient’s clinical supervisor or the tribunal may
discharge a patient.
The ‘independent’ MHA advocacy
service is not an adequate substitute for the protection presently afforded
to citizens by co-opted independent managers.
|
Professional independence
|
It is a matter of concern that all three examiners
may be employed by the prospective detaining authority.
|
The existing separation of powers, which requires that the
applicant is independent of the doctors recommending compulsion, is
abolished. Subject to regulations, in future examinations may be conducted by
three health service colleagues employed by the detaining body. See Clause
14.
|
Abolition of Mental Health Commission
|
|
This constitutional issue is so important that it is dealt
with under a separate major heading immediately below.
|
§7 THEME — Safeguards — Abolition
of Mental Health Commission
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘6. Are the safeguards against abuse
adequate?’
When
vulnerable people are subject to detention or compulsory medical treatment, the
law has usually sought to protect them by requiring that a specialist,
independent, legal body visits them periodically, in order to ensure that these
powers are not being abused.
Agreed
international standards now require governments to provide for this: See, e.g.,
Principles for the Protection of Persons with Mental Illness and the
Improvement of Mental Health Care, adopted by United Nations General Assembly
resolution 46/119 of 17
December 1991. Inspections must be sufficiently frequent to ensure
that the conditions, treatment and care of patients comply with international
principles.
The
Mental Health Act Commission presently performs this essential function.
However, the Bill provides for the Mental Health Act Commission’s abolition,
and it also abolishes the visiting function.
The Government proposes that henceforth the Commission for
Healthcare Audit and Inspection (CHAI) will exercise some functions in relation
to the new Act: see Clauses 256 to 277 and 289 to 292. However, the allocation of some functions
to a large agency like the Healthcare Commission fails to recognise the
importance of having an independent specialist inspectorate/agency to ensure
that the Act is being properly applied and administered for the benefit of
those individuals subject to it.
Functions of CHAI
[Healthcare Commission]
CHAI has eight main functions under the Bill:
1 To give
information and advice
But not advice to patients subject to compulsion, Mental Health
Tribunals, courts or the Secretary of State (in relation to the exercise of
her/his functions).
2 To
gather and publish information about the use of the new Act
This function is self-explanatory.
3 To keep
under review the exercise of relevant functions in relation to relevant
patients
But there is no duty to visit patients subject to compulsion. This
is, however, the way in which the 1983 Act ensures that the MHAC reviews that
way in which powers and duties are being exercised in practice.
The Home Secretary has excluded from review by CHAI the way in which
her/his functions are exercised.
The term ‘relevant patients’ excludes persons removed to a place of
safety, and informal in-patients who have been detained so that they can be
examined, and it may also exclude people who are examined by two doctors and an
approved mental health professional under Part 2.
4 To investigate the exercise of
relevant functions ‘in relation to relevant patients if it considers it
necessary or expedient to do so’
The phrase ‘in relation to relevant patients’ [plural] suggests that
this is a general power, not a power to investigate a particular patient’s
case. This interpretation is reinforced by the fact that a copy of any report
that is published must be made available to the Secretary of State and/or NHS
trust, but not to any patient or patients whose cases form part of the
investigation. According to the Bill, a patient who is affected by the
investigation may inspect the report at CHAI’s offices — which is impractical
if s/he is detained — or obtain one by post upon payment of a reasonable fee.
As before, there is no power to investigate the use of the
short-term powers referred to above, and the Home Secretary has excluded the
way in he exercises his functions from investigation. This is relevant to
decisions concerning restricted patients (leave, transfer, recall to hospital)
and those affected by the transfer from prison to hospital provisions.
5 To
investigate the death of a ‘relevant patient
This discretionary power applies only to ‘relevant patients’.
Regulations may provide that the relevant hospital publishes an action plan.
6 To
investigate complaints made by or in respect of relevant patients
But only if regulations so provide. Furthermore, such regulations
may require a patient who complains, or about whom a complaint is made, to pay
a fee specified in the regulations. The regulations may specify who may make a
complaint (and therefore who may not); complaints that need not be considered;
and matters excluded from consideration.
7 To
correct any minor defects in statutory documents
There is a limited power to correct any document that is found ‘to
be in any minor respect incorrect or defective’.
8 To
review decisions to withhold a patient’s correspondence
Where requested by the patient. This function is presently performed
by the MHAC, and is in similar terms.
CHAI’s functions under
other statutes
CHAI is also taking over the work of the Commission for Health
Improvement, the Audit Commission’s work on value for money, and the National
Care Standards Commission’s remit to inspect private hospitals.
It is to be responsible for inspecting NHS hospitals, the
Government’s star rating system, the imposition of special measures for failing
organisations, the licensing of private hospitals, the conduct of NHS value for
money audits, the scrutiny of patient complaints, and now way in which some Mental
Health Act functions are performed.
Keeping compulsory treatment powers
under review thus forms a relatively small part of an extensive remit, the
remainder of which is concerned with ensuring that trusts implement the
Government’s NHS Plan and modernisation agenda. Here, it may be observed that
the attention of public bodies which monitor standards focuses on one of two
things:
·
Quality standards (setting, monitoring and
enforcing quality standards; patient safety; implementing service reforms
designed to improve quality).
·
Legal standards (including the maintenance
of ethical standards that may not be legally enforceable).
Almost all of the public bodies that the Department of Health
has created, and for which it is responsible, exist in order to ensure or
improve the quality of care. They have been created, not to ensure compliance
with constitutional rights, but to drive forward the Government’s NHS agenda.
In 1999/2000, the DoH’s 64 non-departmental and non-provider public bodies
employed 14,780 staff and received Ł715m in public funding. The Mental Health
Act Commission employed 32 of the 14,780 staff, and received just over Ł3m (or
0.4%) of this Ł715m.
Summary
Getting
rid of a small, standalone, semi-independent, specialist Mental Health
Commission will do enormous harm.
A much
better funded specialist Mental Health Commission, with a clearer and more
focused remit, would be a better and more positive development, rather than
hiving this function off to a large Healthcare Commission whose remit is far
too broad and politically sensitive to do justice to this relatively small and
vulnerable group of patients. These patients are citizens who are being
detained, and in most cases medicated against their will.
A
separate Commission is essential, given the number and range of people who will
be liable to compulsion; the fact that compulsion will now take place in the
community; the position of incapacitated people; and the overall reduction in
safeguards for those subject to compulsion.
The
danger is that the constitutional imperative will be consumed by the larger
political imperatives if the MHAC becomes one small division within a
super-Commission dedicated to monitoring compliance with the NHS programme.
When CHAI budgets are set, ‘mental health legal money’ will compete with NHS
performance-targets, and be diverted to the inspection of acute care — in the
same way that funds announced for mental health initiatives are now sometimes diverted
by Health Authorities to reducing waiting list times.
It must
also be doubtful whether any merger will achieve its stated aim of reducing NHS
bureaucracy. Visiting patients, and ensuring that they are being treated kindly
and lawfully, does not increase regulation. It is not a regulatory exercise.
CHAI does operate as a regulatory body, since it is a paper-heavy organisation concerned
with general management systems.
Furthermore,
merging ‘quangos’ so that they exercise their functions as divisions of one ‘super-quango’
does not reduce regulation. This requires reducing the range of functions
performed. Furthermore, one can only successfully join institutions that
perform similar functions.
Recommendation
There should continue to be an independent,
standalone, Mental Health Commission, the functions of which comply with agreed
international standards. This Commission should perform
the following functions:
1
To
review the care and treatment of patients, and to visit them.
2
To
review the exercise of the powers and duties in the Mental Health Act and the
Human Rights Act 1998 in respect of patients.
3
To
exercise protective functions in respect of persons who may be incapable of
adequately protecting their persons or their interests.
4
If
appropriate, to discharge from detention or compulsion a patient who is being
detained or subjected to compulsory assessment or treatment unlawfully (other
than patients whose detention, assessment or treatment has been authorised by a
tribunal).
5
To
inquire into any case where it appears there may be ill-treatment, deficiency
in care or treatment, or the improper detention, compulsion or supervision of
any person who may be suffering from mental disorder.
6
To
advise the Secretary of State and specified agencies on matters relating to the
Act.
7
Where
appropriate, to undertake formal inquiries, for example after a homicide.
8
To
publish an annual report and a code of practice.
9
To
investigate and prosecute offences under Part 11 of the new Act.
10
To
review decisions to withhold detained patients’ correspondence or to restrict
or interfere with their communication with other persons.
11
To
review, and where necessary terminate, solitary confinement (seclusion) and
mechanical restraint.
In 1982, Parliament amended the last Mental Health Bill by
strengthening the role of what was to be the new Mental Health Act Commission. It
is to be hoped that it will again perform a similar valuable service. If it
does, there is much to be said for placing the Mental Health Commission on the
same footing as the Health Service Commissioner: that is, accountable to and
funded by Parliament, or (if this is not possible) accountable to and funded by
the Department of Constitutional Affairs.
§8 THEME — OMISSIONS
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘Are there any important omissions in the
Bill?’
Seclusion and mechanical restraint
|
Key Points
The Bill should regulate the use of seclusion and
mechanical restraint
|
Further
Explanation
For reasons
that are obvious, the Bill should regulate the use of seclusion (solitary
confinement) and mechanical restraint.
|
Rehabilitation provisions
|
The
Bill does not include any rehabilitation provisions
|
The Bill does
not include any rehabilitation provisions of the kind set out in the Mental
Health (Northern Ireland)
Order 1986. If a person’s detention or compulsion does not exceed 28 days,
s/he should not be required to state in any future employment or insurance
application that s/he has been ‘sectioned’.
|
Offences
|
Who has the duty to investigate and prosecute
offences under the new Act should be made clear.
|
The Bill seems
to make no provision.
|
§9 THEME — COMPLIANCE WITH THE HUMAN RIGHTS
ACT
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘9. Is the Draft Mental Health Bill in full
compliance with the Human Rights Act?’
Non-compliance issues
|
Key Points
Some of the Bill’s provisions in relation to
detention and compulsory treatment are likely to breach the European
Convention.
|
Further
Explanation
These matters
have been dealt with above.
|
§10 THEME — BALANCE BETWEEN COLLECTIVE AND
INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘3. Does the draft bill achieve the right
balance between protecting the personal and human rights of the mentally ill on
one hand, and concerns for public and personal safety on the other?’
Whether the Bill achieves the right balance?
|
Key Points
No.
|
Further
Explanation
Patients are themselves members of the
public, so the law must ensure that members of the public are not
unnecessarily detained, and also that they are protected from those who must
necessarily be detained.
|
|
The Bill
removes many important protections against abuse that either have no impact
on the risk of self-harm or harm to others (such as the abolition of the
Mental Health Act Commission and its visiting function, of second-opinions
concerning antipsychotic drugs, of clear criteria for detention) or only a
minimal impact that is outweighed by the protection afforded to citizens
(such as the abolition of managers’ powers). It is this fact, perhaps more
than any other, that has given the impression of callous disregard and caused
such opposition to the Department of Health’s proposals.
|
|
Even if people
are inadequately protected from the actions of people who have a mental
disorder, this may not be a fault of our laws. It may be due to insufficient
resources, poor government, poor service management, poor risk management,
faulty practice, a faulty understanding of the law, or simply part of the
human condition. In other words, a limitation that is to a significant extent
replicated across a world full of different mental health laws.
|
|
Implicit in any
discussion about the need for new laws is the assumption that modifying their
content modifies outcomes. However, the extent to which this is true is
unclear. Legislation is actually a relatively ineffective means of modifying
behaviour. Although it can provide a framework for managing violence
associated with mental disorder, it cannot significantly reduce these risks.
That this is so is clear from the many homicide inquiry reports. Had the
professional carers foreseen what was about to happen, they already had power
under the present law to intervene. That they did not intervene was due, not
to any lack of legal powers, but to the fact that they did not foresee what
was about to occur. Yet no amount of new legislation can improve foresight.
|
§11 THEME — INTEGRATION WITH THE MENTAL
CAPACITY BILL
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme: ‘8. Is the Draft Mental Health Bill adequately
integrated with the Mental Capacity Bill introduced in the House of Commons on 17 July 2004?’
Mental Capacity Bill and common law powers
|
Key Points
The Bill does not refer to the Mental Capacity Bill
or to common law powers. That being so, it must be the case that it is not
integrated.
|
Further Explanation
The Draft Bill does not refer to the
Mental Capacity Bill introduced in the House of Commons on 17 June 2004.
It is clearly important that considerable
attention is given to the extent to which the various powers, duties and
rights concerning incapacitated patients set out in the Mental Health Bill,
the Mental Capacity Bill and the common law conflict. The interplay between
the different statutory and common law schemes is a potential minefield that
could take years to resolve, and be very expensive for healthcare providers.
|
§12 THEME — PRACTICALITY OF THE
PROPOSALS
The Committee has indicated that it wishes to receive
evidence on the following theme:
‘4.
Are the proposals contained in the Draft Mental Health Bill necessary, workable,
efficient, and clear?
5.
Is the proposed institutional framework appropriate and sufficient for the
enforcement of measures contained in the draft bill?’
10.
What are likely to be the human and financial resource implications of the
draft bill? What will be the effect on the roles of professionals? Has the
Government analysed the effects of the Bill adequately, and will sufficient
resources be available to cover any costs arising from implementation of the
Bill?’
Having regard
to these requirements, and the many demands already made on the time of Mental
Health Act administrators, doctors and other health service professionals, many
of the provisions may be unworkable.
Drafting ambiguities and errors
|
Key Points
The Bill would benefit from being redrafted.
|
Further Explanation
The Bill contains many drafting
ambiguities and errors, and it is certainly highly repetitive and unnecessarily
complicated. It would be sensible for the Department of Health to seek
further legal advice.
|
Implementation issues
|
If the Bill is viable, it will be necessary to allow
those who must implement it a lengthy induction period before it comes into
force.
|
The time
allowed should take the following considerations into account:
- The extension of compulsion to community settings.
- The extension of the population liable to compulsion.
|
|
|
|
- The transitional provisions in Schedule 14.
|
|
- The need for services that today are not involved in
compulsory procedures to familiarise themselves with practice in this
area, e.g. psychology departments and substance-dependency services.
|
|
- The need for hospitals to recruit additional staff in order
to comply with the Bill’s extensive consultation and notification
requirements.
|
|
- The anticipated increase in the
number of tribunal applications (applications for discharge, assessment
orders, treatment orders, further orders, applications relating to
transfers or leave, applications to vary orders).
|
|
- The need for the tribunals to reorganise and for the Legal
Services Commission to make the necessary arrangements for patients to
be legally represented.
|
|
- The requirement that NHS trusts determine whether a citizen
appears to meet the relevant conditions for compulsion every time it is
requested to do so by any person.
|
|
- The requirement that NHS trusts arrange for every person who
appears to meet these conditions to be examined by two doctors and an
approved mental health professional.
|
|
- The duty to record the many kinds of determinations provided
for by the Bill and the reasons for them.
|
|
- The need to organise the necessary
nominated person and advocacy services.
|
|
- The need to put into place systems
for approving clinicians and mental health professionals.
|
|
- The many formal
requirements imposed on the managers of hospitals, e.g. to ‘secure’ that
clinical supervisors make tribunal applications when required to do so
by the terms of the Bill, to appoint clinical supervisors, to secure
that patients are assessed and that care plans are prepared, to require
patients to comply with conditions imposed on them, to deal with
requests for determinations, to register patients, to record changes in
the status of resident and non-resident patients, to process tribunal
applications, to liaise with the new tribunals and the Expert Panel, to
furnish reports and other prescribed information, etc.
|
|
- The many formal
duties imposed on clinical supervisors, e.g. to review and amend
patients’ care plans, to make tribunal applications when required by the
Bill, to keep the legal status of all patients under review, to comply
with the consent to treatment provisions, etc.
|
|
- The need to
retrain all doctors, social workers, nurses, managers and other mental
health professionals who will be involved in implementing the new Act.
They will need to be familiar with the Act, regulations, statutory
forms, rules, Code of Practice, and the guidance issued by the
Department of Health, Home Office, CHAI and Mental Health Tribunals.
|
|
- The need to make
arrangements for the inevitable increase in NHS litigation, and to allow
the NHS and independent hospitals time to agree satisfactory legal cover
and insurance.
|
Training
|
Training is a crucial issue. Substantial time and
money will need to be set aside for training on the Bill.
|
It will be
necessary to retrain all those doctors, social workers, nurses, hospital
managers and other mental health professionals who will be involved in
implementing the new Act.
Services that
today are not involved in compulsory procedures will need to familiarise
themselves with practice in this area, e.g. psychology departments and
substance-dependency services.
They will all
need to be familiar with the Act, regulations, statutory forms, rules, Code
of Practice, and official guidance.
|
Sharing of information
|
The clauses that deal
with ‘information sharing on request’ (Clauses 286 to 288) are extremely
unhelpful.
|
Having set out
what seems to be a new set out statutory duties concerning the sharing of
information, this part of the Bill then ends with, ‘Nothing [above]
authorizes the provision of information if such provision would be prohibited
or restricted under or by virtue of any enactment or by any rule of common
law.’
In other words,
the poor practitioner is told to decide for her/himself whether any of the
‘duties’ in the Bill is a new duty or a breach of confidentiality.
|
§13 CONCLUDING REMARKS
The Government has attempted to
address the concern expressed by many people about the criteria for civil compulsion
contained in the original Bill, and the introduction of new safeguards for
children aged under 16 is a further welcome development.
Unfortunately, in most other respects the
contentious provisions of the original Bill remain unaltered. Indeed, the
relevant conditions aside, the new Bill is if anything less satisfactory in
terms of the constitutional balance it strikes between those persons in
positions of authority and those subject to their authority.
Of special concern are the abolition of a
specialist Mental Health Commission, the way in which central government
departments have excluded themselves from the Code of Practice and other
safeguards, the fact that matters such as the criteria determining whether a
citizen is detained are left to regulations, the length of the Bill, the
quality of the drafting, the practicality of the proposals and the complexity
and expense involved in administering it.
§14 CONTACT DETAILS
All correspondence
and enquiries concerning this paper should be addressed to:
Professor Anselm Eldergill
Solicitors Chambers
169 Malden Road
London NW5 4HT
|
Tel: 020 7284 1006 x28
Fax: 020 7916 2553
Mobile: 0797 119 8742
E-mail: medicolegal@email.com
www.mentalhealthlawyers.com
|

|
The Principles of Mental Health Legislation
Anselm Eldergill
|
1.
It
is unsatisfactory to seek to determine principles by reason only, without
regard for human experience of the world within which principles are formulated
and applied. Our value judgments are judgments about experienced objects.
2.
There
are many reasons to limit state intervention in people’s lives: errors in law
spread their negative effects throughout the nation as opposed to individual
errors that are limited in scope; the damage of erroneous laws affect citizens
more than legislators, who are thus less inclined to repeal them; it takes
longer to repair the damage done by legislation than the damage done by
individuals by their own private choices; because of the constant watch of
critics, politicians are less inclined to publicly admit error and undo the
damage done; politicians are more inclined than citizens to make decisions
based on political gain and prejudice, rather than principle.[1]
3.
The
British constitution separates powers, the aim being to keep executive powers
in check and under proper scrutiny, and so to secure good government. This is
necessary because the ‘whole art of government consists in the art of being
honest’,[2] and ‘it
is not by the consolidation, or concentration of powers, but by their
distribution, that good government is effected.’[3]
4.
Promoting
liberty, protecting individuals from harm caused by those at liberty, and those
not at liberty from abuse by those who are, alleviating suffering, and
restoring to health those whose health has declined, are all legitimate
objectives, in that they reflect values embraced by virtually all members of
our society.[4]
5.
We
are, however, ‘faced with choices between ends equally ultimate, and claims
equally absolute, the realisation of some of which must inevitably involve the
sacrifice of others.’[5] Whether
individuals ‘should be allowed certain liberties at all depends on the priority
given by society to different values, and the crucial point is the criterion by
which it is decided that a particular liberty should or should not be allowed,
or that its exercise is in need of restraint.’[6]
6.
When
enacting mental health legislation, Parliament has generally sought to erect a
balanced legal structure that harmonises three things: individual liberty;
bringing treatment to bear where treatment is necessary and can be beneficial;
the protection of the public.[7] Those we
describe as ‘patients’ are themselves members of the public, so that the law
must seek to ensure that members of the public are not unnecessarily detained,
and also that they are protected from those who must necessarily be detained.
7.
The
use of compulsion has been permitted when significant harm is foreseeable if an
individual remains at liberty. Its purpose is to protect the individual or
others from those risks that arise when a person’s capacity to judge risks, or
to control the behaviour giving rise to them, is impaired by mental disorder.
8.
Other
risks are, constitutionally, matters for citizens to weigh in their own minds.
The purpose of compulsion is not to eliminate that element of risk in human
life that is simply part of being free to act and to make choices and
decisions. A person who obeys our laws is entitled to place a high premium on
their liberty, even to value it more highly than their health. Subject to the
stated limits, people are entitled to make what others regard as errors of
judgement, and to behave in a manner which a doctor regards as not in their
best interests, in the sense that it does not best promote health.
9.
This
desire to determine one’s own interests is common to human beings, and so not
to be portrayed as an abuse of liberty. On the one hand stands liberty, a right
which Parliament and the law should always favour and guard, on the other
licence, a wilful use of liberty to contravene the law, which the law must of
necessity always punish.
10.
Any
power given to one person over another is capable of being abused. No
legislative body should be deluded by the integrity of their own purposes, and
conclude that unlimited powers will never be abused because they themselves are
not disposed to abuse them.[8] Mankind
soon learns to make interested uses of every right and power which they possess
or may assume.[9]
11.
This
risk of abuse is multiplied if the individual is not free to escape abuse, is
incapacitated or otherwise vulnerable, or their word is not given the same
weight as that of others. Children and adults with mental health problems are
particularly at risk, and the law has usually afforded them special protection.
12.
This
protection involves imposing legal duties on those with power, conferring legal
rights on those in their power, and independent scrutiny of how these powers
and duties are exercised. The effectiveness of such schemes depends on whether,
and to what extent, they are observed.
13.
This
is a matter of constitutional importance, for the observance of legal rights
and the rule of law are the cornerstones of all liberal democracies. The rule
of law ‘implies the subordination of all authorities, legislative, executive
[and] judicial … to certain principles which would generally be accepted as
characteristic of law, such as the ideas of the fundamental principles of
justice, moral principles, fairness and due process. It implies respect for the
supreme value and dignity of the individual.’[10]
14.
In
any legal system, ‘it implies limitations on legislative power, safeguards
against abuse of executive power, adequate and equal opportunities of access to
legal advice and assistance, … proper protection of the individual and group
rights and liberties, and equality before the law … It means more than that the
government maintains and enforces law and order, but that the government is,
itself, subject to rules of law and cannot itself disregard the law or remake
it to suit itself.’[11]
15.
In
framing these principles and laws, Parliament has sought to be just, justice
being ‘a firm and continuous desire to render to everyone that which is his
due.’[12]
16.
If
new laws are necessary, they should impose
minimum powers, duties and rights; provide mechanisms for enforcing duties and
remedies for abuse of powers; be unambiguous, just, in plain English, and as
short as possible.
17.
Because
there is a long record of experimentation in human conduct, cumulative
verifications give these principles a well-earned prestige. Lightly to
disregard them is the height of foolishness.[13]

|
The Principles of Legislating for Risks
Anselm Eldergill
|
It is impossible for mental health services
to be totally safe, and Governments should take account of the natural limits
of practice before they introduce legislation:
·
Risk
cannot be avoided and even a very low risk from time to time becomes an
actuality. However careful the assessment, it is inevitable that some patients
will later take their own lives or commit a serious offence.
·
Any
decision to detain an individual, or to compel them to have treatment, involves
balancing competing risks, of which the risk that others may suffer physical
harm is but one. For example, detention and compulsory treatment risk loss of
employment, family contact, self-esteem and dignity; unnecessary or unjustified
deprivation of liberty; institutionalisation, and disabling side-effects.
·
The
purpose of compulsory powers is not to eliminate that element of risk in human
life which is a consequence of being free to act, and to make choices and
decisions; it is to protect the individual and others from risks that arise
when a person’s judgement of risk, or their capacity to control behaviour
associated with serious risk, is significantly impaired by mental disorder.
·
Good
practice relies on good morale and a feeling amongst practitioners that they
will be supported if they act reasonably; it is unjust to criticise them when
decisions properly made have unfortunate, even catastrophic, consequences.
·
The
occurrence of such tragedies does not per
se demonstrate any error of judgement on the part of those who decided that
allowing the patient their liberty did not involve unacceptable risks.
·
An
outcome is often the result of a complex series of events, and the choice of
one particular causal factor may be arbitrary.
·
Small
differences in one key variable can result in vastly different behaviours and
outcomes: just as a sudden change in the physical state of water into steam or
ice occurs with the rise or fall of temperature beyond a critical level, so the
addition of a small additional stress on an individual may have a profound
effect on their mental state or behaviour.
·
All
violence takes place in the present, and the past is a past, and so unreliable,
guide to present and future events.
·
Understanding
the situations in which a person has previously been dangerous, and avoiding
their repetition, can give a false sense of security about the future. Although
life is understood backwards, it must be lived forwards, and the difference
between explanation and prediction is significant: explanation relies on
hindsight, prediction on foresight, and the prediction of future risk involves
more than an explanation of the past.
·
Unless
the individual’s propensity for violence has a simple and readily
understandable trigger, it is impossible to identify all of the relevant
situations; some of them lie in the future, and will not yet have been
encountered by the patient.
·
Predictions
are most often founded not on fact but on ‘retrospective predictions’ of what
occurred in the past (‘retrodiction’).
·
A
risk can in theory be measured and is the basis of actuarial prediction — in
theory because in practice all of the critical variables never are known. The
risk depends on the situation but the situations in which the patient may find
themselves in the future can only be speculated upon.
·
Because
future events can never be predicted, it is important to put in place an
adequate system for supervising an individual whose own safety may potentially
be at risk or who may pose a threat to the safety of others. However, this
approach is not fail-safe: it is based on the assumption that most attacks do
not erupt like thunderstorms from clear skies. In reality, as with weather
systems, only the pattern of events for the next 24 hours can usually be
forecast with some accuracy; and contact with supervisors is less regular.
·
All human beings, regardless of their skills, abilities and
specialist knowledge, make fallible decisions and commit unsafe acts, and this
human propensity for committing errors and violating safety procedures can be
moderated but never entirely eliminated.
Whether
our laws are at fault
Even if
people are inadequately protected from the actions of people who suffer from
mental disorder, this may not be a fault of our laws. It may be due to
insufficient resources, poor government, poor service management, poor risk
management, faulty practice, a faulty understanding of the law, or simply part
of the human condition. In other words, a problem or limitation that is to a
significant extent replicated across a world full of different mental health
laws.
Implicit in any discussion about the need for new laws
is the assumption that modifying their content modifies outcomes. However, the
extent to which this is true is unclear. Legislation is actually a relatively
ineffective means of modifying behaviour. Although it can provide a framework
for managing violence associated with mental disorder, it cannot significantly
reduce these risks. That this is so is clear from recent homicide inquiry
reports. Had the professional carers foreseen what was about to happen, they
already had power under the present law to intervene. That they did not
intervene was due, not to any lack of legal powers, but to the fact that they
did not foresee what was about to occur. Yet no amount of new legislation can
improve foresight. Nor can it improve insight, for ‘he that complies against
his will, Is of his own opinion still.’[14]
The key to progress
must rest with improving government, resources, diagnostic tools, treatments
and training, and, most fundamentally of all, with education:
‘I
believe that education is the fundamental method of social progress and reform.
All reforms which rest simply upon the law, or the threatening of certain
penalties, or upon changes in mechanical or outward arrangements, are
transitory and futile.... But through education society can formulate its own
purposes, can organize its own means and resources, and thus shape itself with
definiteness and economy in the direction in which it wishes to move....
Education thus conceived marks the most perfect and intimate union of science
and art conceivable in human experience.’[15]

|
Legislating for Personality Disorder
Anselm Eldergill
|
Who is mentally
disordered?
It is
necessary to define or describe who within a population is mentally disordered
before it is possible to estimate the level of violence for which they are
collectively responsible.
If
persons with anti-social or psychopathic personalities are categorised as being
mentally disordered, it is necessarily true that other people are relatively
more at risk from the mentally disordered than if they are excluded.
Furthermore, if our definition of a psychopathic disorder requires abnormally
aggressive or seriously irresponsible conduct, as it does under the 1983 Act,
it is inevitable that people within the definition will often have been
violent. Such a concept is bound to produce such a statistical finding, the
whole aim being to detain those who, though not mentally ill, put others at
significant risk. Conversely, if such people are excluded, the level of
violence committed by what may be called the anti-social element in society
will be that much greater, and the contribution of the mentally disordered that
much less.
The
definition of mental disorder in the 1983 Act includes people categorized as
having a psychopathic disorder, but does not include people by reason only of
promiscuity, immoral conduct, sexual deviancy or dependence on alcohol or
drugs. It is clear, however, from the draft Bill that the Government considers that
such persons have a mental disorder. By implication, it counts them as part of
the group of mentally disordered persons who commit violence, violence from
which the public are inadequately protected. It will later be argued that this
all-inclusive approach is artificial and unjustified ….
Whether the human
personality is a proper subject for medicine
The Home
Office and the Department of Health have for some time now been considering the
introduction of new laws aimed at protecting the public from individuals who
have a ‘dangerous severe personality disorder’.
In July
1999, the two departments published a consultation document, setting out
proposals intended to ensure ‘that DSPD people are kept in detention for as
long as they pose a high risk. The approach the Government has developed …
involves the idea of detention based on the serious risk such people present to
the public.’[16]
The
Government was therefore advocating that risk alone, as well as mental disorder
and criminal punishment, can justify detention. As a result, consideration was
given to detaining such people in ‘third units’, in essence adult secure
accommodation of the kind presently provided for some behaviourally-disturbed
children.
This is a
quarantine argument; one which holds that, subject to problems of
identification, the civil detention of dangerous people is justified even if
they have not committed any violent offences. The contrary argument is that the
civil detention of dangerous non-offenders is never warranted, because it is a
fundamental principle that citizens who obey our laws have a right to be at
liberty. To imprison a person who has not yet committed the offence one fears
is the criminal justice system of Alice’s
Wonderland: ‘”No, no!” said the Queen. “Sentence first — verdict afterwards.”’
The
‘third-unit’ option seems to have been abandoned, probably because it was
thought that indefinitely detaining non-offenders in civilian accommodation
risks infringing the European Convention on Human Rights. Article 5(1) permits
the detention of convicted persons and those of unsound mind in appropriate
facilities (prisons and hospitals, respectively), but does not in clear terms
permit the detention of citizens who have not offended merely because there is
a risk they will do so in future. Detention in secure non-hospital
accommodation rather rules out pleading mental disorder, and a need for
treatment, as the justification, and nor can punishment or lawful sentence be
pleaded, because the individuals are not serving a term of imprisonment.
Probably
for these reasons, therefore, the Government seems to have retreated, at least
for the present, to the justification that such people are mentally disordered:
they require medical treatment in hospital or medical treatment under
supervision in the community.
It is, no
doubt, with the anti-social in mind that the criteria for compulsion, and
various key statutory terms — such as mental disorder, medical treatment,
hospital and clinical supervisor — are defined as they are. Indeed, the
proposals for the compulsion of civilians seem designed to deal with people who
habitually threaten, harm or alarm others, whatever the cause. It is in effect
a ‘well dodgy’ Act, designed to sweep from the streets, or to supervise and
control, anyone whose conduct causes the public significant concern, but whose
behaviour — in the absence of actual evidence or proof of serious offending —
does not allow the police or the courts to place them in custody.
Much of
the recent debate has centred on whether or not the NHS and other agencies are
resourced to provide such an extensive service. However, this assumes that such
people may properly be dealt with on the basis that their conduct is evidence
of a medical condition that requires medical intervention. The arguments for
not permitting this are compelling.
Kurt
Schneider defined personality as, ‘the unique quality of the individual, his
feelings and personal goals; the sum of his traits, habits and experiences and
the whole system of relatively permanent tendencies, physical and mental, which
are distinctive of a given individual.’[17] In
short, personality is what makes one individual different from another. It is
who I am.
This
observation immediately gives rise to two important questions: Are people said
to have disordered personalities injured, ill or diseased? And, is the human
personality a proper subject for medicine?
The
evidence suggests that present medical interventions have, like liberal prison
regimes, the reformation of the individual as their aim. This is unacceptable
because the proper function of medical science and practice is to treat
individual suffering attributable to disease or injury, not to alleviate the
suffering of society; and, in the field of mental health, to treat those
diseases or injuries which interfere with the development or expression of an
individual’s personality, not to reform her or his personality by reference to
some social or political norm.
The
mental state and behaviour of an individual said to have a personality disorder
is abnormal, in the sense that it deviates from the social norm, but normal in
relation to their own individual norm: that is, it is consistent with what is
known about their development and functioning over time. Here then, the
individual is only abnormal by reference to a social norm, and such a deviation
cannot be said to constitute a disease because mere social deviation is not
evidence of biological disorder. This requires evidence of injury or deviation
from the individual norm. If there is no evidence of either then one is simply
confusing individuality with ill-health: treating as biologically abnormal an
undiseased, uninjured, creature living its natural life, so that medicines are
pesticides.
The
motivation for this social control is transparent. People want to live in a
cultivated society, and they cultivate society in much the same way they
cultivate nature in their gardens. This involves eradicating disease in the
garden, but also weeding it and controlling pests, that is containing or
destroying organisms which are doing nothing more than expressing their
natures. There is nothing unique in this, for the same power is claimed over
animals and unborn life, and most other things that interfere with personal
survival or fulfilment. But it is why CS Lewis wrote that, ‘To be cured against
one's will and cured of states which we may not regard as disease is to be put
on a level with those who have not yet reached the age of reason or those who
never will; to be classed with infants, imbeciles and domestic animals. But to
be punished ... because we have deserved it ... is to be treated as a human
person made in God's image.’[18]
Although
many people would not today understand the issue in religious terms, the
argument retains its inner strength: there is more human dignity in punishment
than in medicalizing anti-social or violent behaviour.
This is
an uncomfortable message for an age that is uncomfortable with the notion of
punishment, the more so when the debate involves issues of responsibility and
free will, and the extent to which some people’s personalities do not enable
them to refrain from anti-social behaviour. However, our conscious thinking and
deciding are embodied in the workings of our brains, and consequently our
behaviour is determined by our thinking and choosing. While determinism
provides an explanation for our choices and actions, it is humans beings, not
deterministic rules, that cause events. The fact that an individual’s
personality, as determined by their genes and previous experiences, dictates the
choice s/he makes does not mean that s/he has not chosen between alternatives.
Furthermore, whilst not everyone has the same capacity to eschew the wrong,
this does not preclude us from judging their actions, because whether an action
is harmful is not affected by its antecedents. In short, our conscious
decisions and actions are matters of personal choice: each chooses what suits
their personality, not that of others, and must be accountable to others for
their choice. The counterpart of freedom and autonomy is accountability for
acts freely and autonomously done.
The view
presented here therefore is that those persons presently categorized as
psychopaths are not mentally disordered, and they should be excluded from
mental health legislation. We are simply medicalizing ‘deviant behaviour’.[19]
Believing this, there is no inhumanity in holding that they should be
imprisoned if their offence and forensic history merits it. If we are satisfied
that our prison system is the best that can be devised for the prevention of
crime, and the reformation of the criminal, then we may rest satisfied that it
is the best treatment for the sort of insanity from which criminals suffer. If,
on the other hand, we are not satisfied that prisons are reformative then why
this is so needs to be the principal focus of our attention.[20]
What
cannot be justified are mental health or social protection laws that permit the
preventive detention of law-abiding citizens who are free of injury or disease.
It would be unjust to detain them for crimes they have not committed and are
actuarially unlikely to commit. It would be immoral, because the old maxim that
'you shall not do evil that good may come' is applicable in law as well as in
morals. It would be inutile, because any impact on the rates at which serious
offences are committed is likely to be marginal. There is little gain in
detaining a handful of notionally dangerous civilians each year when guilt in
criminal proceedings must be proved beyond all reasonable doubt, because every
year we release without penalty thousands of rapists and other violent
offenders. Lastly, it would be unwise. For, when the public perceives that they
are no safer despite such a reform, rather than realise and learn from their
folly, they will demand that basic freedoms be further curtailed and the
penalties made more severe.
Such
demands misunderstand the functions of the law and its natural limits. It is
not within the power of the law, given the venality of the times, to cleanse
the Augean stable. As Montesquieu observed, in ‘moderate governments, the love
of one’s country, shame, and the fear of blame are restraining motives, capable
of preventing a multitude of crimes. Here, the greatest punishment of a bad
action is conviction ... In those states a good legislator is ... more
attentive to inspire good morals than to inflict penalties.’[21]
Only
those who know the cost but not the value of our freedoms would embark upon
such a journey. Nothing which has great value is without cost, and the value of
anything is what one is prepared to sacrifice for it. The value attached to
trial by one's peers is the financial cost of the jury system; the value of
justice is demonstrated by a willingness to see the guilty go free rather than
risk convicting the innocent; and the value of liberty is demonstrated by
stoically bearing the many evils which liberty permits. If the defence of these
freedoms was worth the sacrifice of millions during two wars then, unless
society has become wholly degraded, it must withstand the death of a few during
peacetime. Such a scheme has no utility which can justify its innate immorality
and the infliction of such great injustice; and it would be highly imprudent to
interfere with public liberties in the name of public safety when the necessity
of such a scheme has not been firmly established.[22]
APPENDICES —
ENDNOTES