Draft House of Lords Reform Bill - Draft House of Lords Reform Bill Joint Committee Contents



Richard Douglas

Summary

  • Current proposals do not give due consideration to the prospect of constitutional gridlock.
  • The mantra of 'checks and balances' actually reflects a view that wishes to hamper government and undermine democracy, not improve it.
  • Some alternatives are proposed, mainly to highlight shortcomings of the Government's proposals, and caution against their adoption.
  • It is suggested that the Lords remain unelected, but be reformed—e.g. by creating two classes of peers, one with the right to sit in Parliament, one without.

Background

I do not represent any organisation, nor am I a specialist in constitutional affairs. I have some first-hand experience of the workings of Parliament, having worked as a committee specialist for the Environmental Audit Committee from 2006-09, in which capacity I was an Officer of the House of Commons. During that time I also supported a joint committee of both Houses, the Joint Committee on the Draft Climate Change Bill.

I am making this submission because I believe the prevailing debate concerning the primacy of the House of Commons overlooks an important argument. My concern is that, without greater thought, proposed reforms could undermine the democratic mandate of the Commons, and with that the idea of the state as acting in the public interest.

Primacy of the House of Commons

Most of the debate on the issue of primacy of the Commons focuses on the potential for legislative gridlock, should a reformed upper house be emboldened, through its democratic mandate, to challenge the Commons on equal terms. The responses to this tend to fall into two. One minimises this as a problem, by pointing to existing arrangements which limit the role of the Lords; these could simply be continued, it is said. The other says that gridlock would be no bad thing, if it represented the balance of opinion between two elected houses.

A characteristic example of the first is given in the 2007 white paper on Lords reform introduced by the then Leader of the House of Commons, the Rt Hon Jack Straw MP:

Although the primacy of the Commons is historically derived from its elected mandate, primacy no longer rests solely on this fact. Primacy is made real by the different functions exercised by the two Houses, and their different roles. The Government cannot govern without the support of the Commons, the Commons controls supply, and the Commons has the final say on legislation—this is how the primacy of the Commons is now expressed.

It is hard to believe that this was introduced by a Leader of the House of Commons. Read it, and we find the suggestion that the primacy of the House of Commons does not rest solely on its democratic mandate! On what does it rest, then? On … its terms of reference. As though it were some university admin committee.

Let us ask the important question: who sets its terms of reference? On whose authority are the powers and role of the House of Commons decided? If it is not the democratic authority of the people, then … what are we saying? That the democratic authority of the people can be outranked by some other authority? No. The primacy of the Commons results from its being the elected will of the people. If the House of Lords were also to be elected, then there would be another version of the Commons. Or rather its authority would be the same, even if its initial 'remit' were different.

After all, by what logic are governments formed in Britain? Whichever MP can command a majority in the House of Commons is invited by the head of state to form a government. This is what makes the government, the government: that it commands a working majority of the representatives of the people's will. If an upper house were elected, then it, too, would represent the people's will. By what logic or authority would whichever party or parties which commanded a majority within it not be entitled to form the government? If the answer to this is that the Commons has a different remit, then it is saying that the government's authority is not primarily derived from a democratic mandate, but some other rules. If rules can be used to outrank the democratic mandate of one house, what's to say there couldn't be other rules or conventions which outranked or undermined the democratic mandate of the other?

There appears to have been a certain amount of complacency among many MPs on this issue for a number of years. One can gain a further sense of this from a Public Administration Select Committee report on another iteration of these proposals, this time from 2002:

The Government, and some members of the Lords, have laid particular stress on the threat which would allegedly be posed to the pre-eminence of the Commons by a more legitimate reformed second chamber. We are satisfied that the Parliament Acts provide sufficient safeguards against that. The differences in powers between the Houses are already very clear. These have only to be identified for any argument on this point to be removed. The Commons can pass legislation without the consent of the Lords, after delay of about one year. But the Lords cannot pass legislation without gaining the consent of the Commons. The Commons only has to wait one month before passing a money bill without the consent of the Lords. Governments are formed, tested and held to account in the Commons. They have to retain the confidence of the Commons if they are to retain office. Only the Commons can make or break governments. We therefore do not believe that a reformed, more representative second chamber will pose a threat to that status. Moreover, our proposals are intended further to strengthen the distinctiveness of the second chamber, and so increase the effectiveness of Parliament as a whole.

The weakness in these arguments it that all the powers to rein in the Lords cited in the above paragraph hail from the authority of the Commons; when it says Parliament can decide what role the Lords should play, it means (as is currently the case) the Commons, with advice (conforming to its current role) from the Lords. The Parliament Acts, hobbling one house, are only tenable in a democratic age if the upper house is not democratically elected.

Embracing the prospect of gridlock

Another prevailing view, that which embraces the potential outcome of legislative gridlocks, is well represented by an Unlock Democracy policy briefing:

Some people are concerned that an elected second chamber would want to use its powers more than the current House of Lords and that this would create more gridlock. As long as it is clear which is the more powerful chamber and how the dispute can be resolved, as it is in the UK, then gridlock is not necessarily a bad thing. It means the second chamber is doing its job: examining proposals for new laws and asking the government to think again.

Why is this wrong-headed? There are three, related, reasons. One, it would potentially lead to a chronic condition in which the effectiveness of the government to take action were undermined. Two, this would potentially discredit politics and the idea of state action. Three, while a proportion of those advancing this as a view will be classical liberals who are suspicious of government, probably the majority will be left-wingers who believe in a strong and active state.

The mantra of 'checks and balances' tends to get invoked in the aid of this, the flirting-with-gridlock, view. Where does this come from? The ideas of Locke, and the example of America. These are, let us remember, the ideas of moneyed classes who want the state to protect them, certainly, but equally want to be protected from the actions of the state. They do not identify themselves with the state. They see it as an alien power. The checks and balances in the American constitution were designed, and have worked with great success, to hamper the ability of any government to act. Such checks on state power have not abolished the abuse of power. They have, primarily (and increasingly so in recent years), reined in the state from curbing the wealthy from exerting power over those below them. In so doing they have encouraged a widespread cynicism about politics—fostered, of course, by those who stand to gain from such disengagement.

There is an alternative to the Lockean conception of government: the Hobbesian. Thomas Hobbes viewed those controlling the state as being the embodiment of all the people who comprised it. The government thus acted with the authority of the people in everything it did. Hobbes's views have been characterised as totalitarian, as justifying untrammelled exercise of power, and removing any basis on which the individual could protest against abuse by the state. In another way, his ideas are intrinsically democratic, since he makes the entire basis of state authority the (even if conjectured) agreement of the people to be represented by it. The closer the state is to the people, and the more democratic participation there is, the stronger and more legitimate the state becomes.

It is, I would argue, by virtue of these ideas that MPs gain their status and authority (or what should be their status and authority). Irrespective of who they are as individuals, as MPs they are something greater. They are not simply people who have happened to come first in some contest or other, even an important one. They are the representatives, the embodiments, of the people of their constituency; they speak and act in their constituency's name.

Under a Hobbesian concept of the state, it is a nonsense to create a second elected house of parliament. There aren't two peoples; there can't be two embodiments of the people. And if the second isn't an embodiment of the people, then the first isn't, either. At which point the idea of the state as acting in the people's name collapses; and you have instead the idea of the state as an alien thing, something run by professional politicians and civil servants for their own ends. An outcome which many on the liberal-left spectrum would surely deplore.

Whom is a second chamber for?

Most discussions of why we need a second chamber at all concentrate on the question of what it should do. Perhaps the right question to start with, however, is whom is it for? To ask this is to think about how we got here, why it is we have a House of Commons and a House of Lords?

To think about this is to remember that they were originally representing different estates, the gentry and then middle class (though always, to an extent, representing the common man), on the one hand; and the nobility and bishops, on the other. With the king above them. And how did the Commons come to achieve pre-eminence, first over the king, and then the Lords? Partly, of course, it's a reflection of the rise of the economic power of the middle classes from the seventeenth century onwards. But even more than this, it's because of the triumph of the democratic ideal. This dictated that governments would be formed by those parties which won elections; this dictated that the views and powers of elected representatives were greater than those of the unelected (and increasingly anachronistic) Lords; this dictated that the Lords accepted this state of affairs. As the democratic ideal has triumphed, so have all the old estates collapsed into one: the people. The Commons is the house which represents that estate, the people. The Lords has only survived because it has renounced its power.

Alternative proposals for an upper house

To pick up the question of whom might an upper house be for, we could begin by thinking about what other important interests are not represented, or not adequately represented, by the representatives of the people as a whole.

This could be different peoples, in the sense of the alternative local, regional, or national communities we all belong to in addition to that of British society as a whole. The logic here would suggest creating an upper house with representatives with an explicit mandate to ensure the Government were considering the interests of their region or nation. This could potentially be done by indirect election, possibly meaning membership were automatically extended to local authority leaders, MSPs, AMs, and NIAMs, or their delegated representatives.

They could also be the people as defined and divided by important social identities. The logic here would suggest an appointed house made up of representatives from a variety of interest and representative groups, including religious faiths, professional associations, unions, business groups, and scientific and cultural bodies.

Another set of interests could be the people of the past and of the future, whose memories and prospects would not always coincide with the interests of the people of the present. The logic here might suggest an appointed house with members selected for their distinguished contribution to British society, especially in an intellectual capacity.

A final, and certainly radical proposal, would be for the roles of the Commons and Lords to be reversed, with a Lords 100% elected under pure PR, out of which the government would be formed, and the Commons made into the revising chamber with an explicit mandate to represent local interests. Although almost certainly unpalatably radical for most, this idea would have clear logic on its side. At the moment, there is a deficiency in the ability of the Commons to represent the people's will: the electorate does not vote as one people, and it does not vote for the government, simply for individual, local representatives. In practice, of course, voters, especially at general elections, overwhelmingly do vote for whichever party they want to from the government (or to help keep a different party out of government). But it is an imperfect arrangement.

Some people advocate switching to PR to remedy this. One of the drawbacks of this proposal is that it would lose the link between constituents and their local MP. PR enthusiasts tend to address this by pointing to varieties of PR which still allow people to vote for and be represented by individual MPs. But these systems suffer from one of two flaws: either you have large, multi-member constituencies, in which the mechanics of the system are difficult to understand and the link with a local representative is weakened; or you have a top-up system, which creates two classes of politician, those with a direct mandate (and casework), and those without.

For these reasons, I'd suggest retaining the essential structure and voting system of the Commons, but making the Lords elected on pure PR (voting for parties, not people), whose outcome would determine the executive. The Commons would then perform the role of scrutinising and revising chamber (though with greater powers than the current Lords), to which MPs as backbenchers, with personal mandates and high profiles, are well-suited. To help avoid gridlock it would make sense to elect MPs in tranches, say, a quarter a year (e.g. if general elections were made every four years).

Conclusion

All of these proposals are, of course, far too radical to be of any immediate use in the Committee's deliberations. I offer them by the way of criticising what is proposed, and to caution against its adoption—since a reformed Lords, with a democratic mandate, would be much harder to fundamentally alter, even if highly flawed.

My final remarks on the proposed reforms are that the proposals for election by STV are misguided, for reasons touched on above: the mechanics are impossible to explain on the doorstep, and the constituencies far too big for there to be any personal link. The White Paper even likens the system to European elections: but MEPs hardly have any personal link to their electorates. For this reason, elected members are likely not to have a personal mandate, and since unable to win a seat as an MP, be party apparatchiks, less able to provide scrutiny than the Lords today. The rest of the house would be made up of the entire leadership of minority parties: nothing wrong with their being represented in Parliament, but their interest would not primarily be in scrutinising legislation but grandstanding and campaigning.

A further reflection on the current proposals is that the majority of those voting will not particularly understand or care about the role of the upper chamber: most will simply vote for the same party they vote for in all elections, with some voting for a different party out of the knowledge that this election is less important and that party will never form the government (e.g. they might UKIP or Green, out of a sense that the main parties were not representing certain points of view). Either way, it will have an imperfect mandate: most will still just be voting for whom they want to form the government, with the rest not casting their actual first preference vote. Of course, one could try to minimise this by holding elections separately from general and national elections—but then turnout would likely be dismal.

I would suggest the best course of action would be to reform the current Lords, but leave it unelected. My main suggestion would be to reduce numbers, and make two classes of peers, one with the right to sit in Parliament, one without—so that those in Parliament were specifically chosen for that role, while others could still be honoured with titles for whatever reason, but did not have a parliamentary role. And, if we are going to retain Church of England bishops in the House, representatives of other faiths—and some philosophers—ought to be made members automatically.

Finally, I would suggest that consideration of a more radical reform of the Lords not be abandoned, but be subjected to more thought.

8 January 2012


 
previous page contents next page


© Parliamentary copyright 2012
Prepared 23 April 2012