Draft House of Lords Reform Bill - Draft House of Lords Reform Bill Joint Committee Contents



Professor Gavin Phillipson

Introduction

1.  I am writing this memorandum as a Professor of Constitutional Law who has published widely on this topic, and taught it for over 15 years at both undergraduate and post-graduate level. I also have expertise in the area of anti-terrorism legislation, in relation to which the relative performance of Lords and Commons when engaging in legislative scrutiny is illuminating. I wish to address the issue of the respective balance of appointed and elected members left open by the Bill and White Paper and in particular to argue in favour of the hybrid elected /appointed House.[126] I am concerned in particular to address what I believe is the simplistic view, which now appears to be gaining ground, that if 80% elected is 'good' than 100% is 'better'. My key purpose is to defend the idea of a hybrid House, with at least a 20% appointed independent element, from those who argue in favour of fully elected chamber by showing that it is not a poor compromise but rather a better intellectual solution.

The problem

2.  I have summarised the way in which all the main options for reform call forth equally virulent criticism, as follows:

'an appointed House is derided as a giant quango, representing rule by an elite, lacking an democratic legitimacy and ultimately ineffectual. A wholly elected chamber, on the other hand, is objected to on the basis that it would produce a clone of the commons, that could become its rival, thus producing the danger of legislative impasse and destroying the clear line of democratic accountability between parliamentary government and the people that is said currently to exist... Finally the seemingly obvious compromise, a mixed elected/appointed House, is scorned as a "hybrid nonsense" that simply represents a failure to decide the issue one way or the other and would be crippled by internal divisions between its elected and appointed members and the different degrees of legitimacy each would claim.'[127]

3.  Disagreement over the proper composition of a reformed House springs from the fact that politicians and commentators tend to emphasise only one key quality that a new chamber should have: thus those in favour of an elected House urge that democratic legitimacy must be overriding; those favouring an appointed House stress the importance of the House being able to make a distinctive contribution from the Commons in terms of providing independent and non-partisan scrutiny of legislation. In this memorandum I will suggest that when a balanced set of criteria, drawn from analysis of second chambers overseas, are applied to the problem, and the necessity of certain trade-offs accepted, then the hybrid solution emerges as the best one in the UK constitutional context. I believe that Parliament got this question broadly right in the report of the Public Administration Select Committee[128] some years ago (hereafter 'PAC'). While a 60/40 elected/appointed House would probably be the optimum balance, an 80/20 elected/appointed House would be hugely preferable to a fully elected House.

4.  In this memorandum I do not discuss the possibility of a wholly or mainly appointed House as such a reform is not suggested by the White Paper and nor is it supported by any of the three main political parties. I do however believe that leaving the House wholly appointed would fail to cure the main problem it has had for many years that much of its excellent policy work, including its proposed revisions to legislation, goes to waste because of its perceived lack of legitimacy. As Donald Shell has put it, the UK has for some time been working under a system of "de facto unicameralism",[129] mainly because of the conventional limits upon the exercise of the House's powers, which stem from its perceived lack of legitimacy.

5.  However, I also believe that if no agreement on radical reform to composition can be reached, the current House would be considerably enhanced were Prime Ministerial patronage to be appointed and an independent statutory Appointments Commission to take over the appointment of new members to the House. If necessary, this reform can and should be carried out even if no other change can be agreed.

Evaluation: key criteria

6.  There is general agreement that the reformed House will continue to carry out the same functions as the present House, and that is what the White Paper proposes. Meg Russell, in her authoritative comparative analysis of second chambers overseas, has identified three factors as crucial for judging the likely effectiveness of a second chamber.[130] As summarised by the PAC,[131] the reformed Lords should have the following qualities: distinct composition; perceived legitimacy; adequate powers. Parliament's previous Joint Committee on Lords reform[132] arrived at five key criteria, that I believe command wide acceptance: legitimacy; representative-ness; no domination by one party, independence and expertise. In substance, it is suggested, these coincide with the first two of Russell's criteria: representative-ness goes to legitimacy, while independence, freedom from party domination and expertise are all qualities that render the Lords distinct from the Commons. Moreover, the broadly agreed functions of the second chamber—particularly its special role in relation to technical scrutiny and protection of human rights and the constitution—reinforce the claim that the reformed chamber should seek to maintain those qualities of relative independence and expertise that are particularly suited to these types of scrutiny, in contrast to the partisan culture of the Commons.

7.  Distinct composition for the House, as well as enabling it to perform the particular scrutinising role that all agree it should have, also ensures that the second chamber makes a worthwhile addition to the legislative scrutiny carried out by the first. Thus it is also vital to ensure that the party balance in the chamber is different, and more proportional from that in the Commons, to prevent one-party domination, and ensure that the House has an alternative and more broadly-based perspective on the development of public policy. Russell's research clearly indicates that while Government control of the second chamber can render it too weak and Opposition control too likely to result in deadlock with the first chamber, the option of no overall control, is "the most effective option;"[133] "a powerful upper house which is controlled by forces independent of government can help create a form of consensus politics which results in better political outcomes in the longer term."[134] The proposed STV electoral system would be likely to achieve this in practice. The use of First Pass the Post would not be suitable for the second chamber, as likely to produce either Government or Opposition control.

8.  The third criterion for an effective second chamber is perceived legitimacy. As the PAC put it: "In order to use its powers, the new chamber—unlike the existing House of Lords—will need to be seen to have legitimacy, and be able to carry public support."[135] What counts here is percieved legitimacy: in other words, a perception in the minds of the public and the government that the power and position of the House are justifiable in a democracy; without this, the House will lack the confidence and extra-parliamentary support to oppose the government effectively. In a democracy, the starting point is that political power must derive from the people, via election, though this is a matter that will be explored further below, in the context of the detailed arguments about the merits of the balance between appointed and elected members.

A general objection to all mixed Houses.

9.  The Royal Commission, successive White Papers and the PAC have all recommended a mixed House; however opposition to it continues, as the quotation above indicates. Determining the force of this objection, is, however, crucial: if any form of mixed House is rejected on these grounds, then the only options left will be the polarised positions of a wholly elected or wholly appointed House, ruling out any form of compromise.

10.  There appear to be two main strands to the objection. The first main argument is the so-called "Strathclyde paradox:"[136] "If election is so good, why should the public not elect all our political Members? If it is bad, why elect any at all?"[137]. This piece of apparent logic has gained considerable support in the Lords. It is however flawed because it rests upon the false premise that electing members is straightforwardly either good or bad. Thus those we believe that election is 'good' believe that 100% elected is better than 80% elected. In fact, if the three criteria for an effective second chamber noted above are borne in mind, it becomes apparent that election to the second chamber has some advantages and some drawbacks. Election is "good" in terms of legitimacy: if there were to be no elected members, this would prevent the House from having sufficient democratic legitimacy to assert itself effectively against the Executive-dominated Commons. However, the issue of the composition of the Lords does not rest solely upon legitimacy. As canvassed above, in addition to being legitimate, it should also be distinct from the Commons, more independent from party control and have the expertise to aid it in its sometimes highly technical work. Once these factors are considered, we can see why we might not want all the chambers members to be elected, desirable though this would be in terms of legitimacy: such a course of action would preclude the appointment of members who would add expertise, independence and thus distinctive value to the House. Having different classes of members—in other words a hybrid House—ensures that these different requirements are all met. These arguments show why, on a balanced view, the majority-elected solution comes out as the best one. In contrast, the so-called Strathclyde paradox only has any force if it is assumed that reform of the Lords is to be judged by one criterion alone.

11.  The second, and only plausible objection is that originally voiced by Professor Bogdanor:

"A mixed chamber would contain members enjoying different degrees of democratic legitimacy. The danger then is that any vote carried by a group with a lesser degree of democratic legitimacy will be seen as less valid than a vote carried by a group with greater democratic legitimacy…Who elected you? would be the cry directed at the hapless nominated members whenever they carried a vote against their elected colleagues." [138]

This point has been echoed in Parliament by some of the more thoughtful objectors to a mixed House. However, the extent to which this would be a problem for a hybrid House has been much too readily assumed and three points may be made against it.

12.  First of all, the reaction of the elected members to such an eventuality is a matter of speculation. As Russell has pointed out, only two chambers out of 58 bi-cameral legislatures world-wide have a substantial amount of appointed members in the second chamber, so there is little evidence from which to predict with any confidence the dynamics of such chambers.[139] If a mixed House had been approved by both Houses of Parliament on a free vote, and so had received all-party endorsement, it would be difficult for elected members to carp at the presence and influence of the non-elected members which Parliament itself had agreed should be there.

13.   Second, there are ways of minimising the problem. Both the Royal Commission and the PAC[140] recommended that in a mixed House everything should be done to ensure that all members enjoy parity of esteem, whether elected or appointed. Thus as the Royal Commission put it:

Once members have arrived in the chamber, by whatever route, they should so far as possible serve the same terms, benefit from the same allowances and facilities and be treated in all respects identically.[141]

This very clear recommendation has been completely ignored by many of the opponents of mixed House in Parliament.[142]

14.  Finally, the proponents of this view miss a simple, but crucially important point: if the elected members constituted a large majority of the House, as the White Paper envisage, then the elected could never be defeated by the un-elected; thus the danger Bogdanor foresees would simply never materialise. A 20% un-elected contingent simply could never defeat an 80% elected one.

15.  Moreover, it is unlikely that any given issue would split the two groups of members squarely down the middle as Bogdanor suggests. In nearly all cases, there would be bound to be some elected members (particularly perhaps Liberal Democrat and non-partisan party members generally) siding with their independent colleagues. This would preclude the isolation and exposure of the un-elected members.

16.  However, a modified version of this objection, that could still apply where the elected members were in a majority, was advanced by Lord Butler, former Cabinet secretary, in debate:

Let us envisage that on a controversial issue the government of the day and the opposition parties are in conflict, but one side has a small majority which is overturned by the votes of the minority of appointed Members. If we have accepted election as a necessary condition for legitimacy, where is legitimacy then?[143]

17.  It is clear that in such a case, there would be no straightforward clash between the elected and the un-elected, as Bogdanor envisages. But the only response to Butler's question, "where would legitimacy be then?" is that legitimacy should be seen as a condition for the House as a whole: if it has a majority of elected members, it is House in which the democratic will can always prevail and thus a legitimate institution. Moreover, if the situation Butler envisages were to materialise, it seems plausible to believe that the public would view with relief the sight of the squabbling parties having the odd issue resolved by the dispassionate intervention of independent experts. Moreover, it is ironic that this objection is nearly always made by those who favour a wholly appointed House. Such a House, when it disagrees with the Commons, precisely pits the appointed, as a body, against the elected Commons, and therefore raises in a far more stark and extreme way the problem at issue.

18.  It is possible therefore that a mixed House could raise some legitimacy issues in this way, but this does not provide, as Bogdanor and others suggest, a conclusive argument against such a chamber. Rather it may represent the only real drawback in what is otherwise the best solution to a notoriously difficult problem; a drawback to be balanced against the numerous advantages to be discussed below.

Why not a wholly elected second chamber?

19.  In contrast to the position under the Blair government, it is the 100% elected House that has now emerged as the main rival to the hybrid option in the current proposals. The arguments in favour of such a House are clear and straightforward: that a democratic mandate should be the only way to political power in a democracy and that the greater legitimacy and so potency such a House would have would give it a much more prominent voice in the policy-making process.

20.  Many of the arguments against such a House are equally familiar. In essence they stem from the basic contention that, if proposals for a wholly appointed House tip the balance too far in favour of distinctiveness at the expense of legitimacy, a wholly elected House would do the opposite. Proposals for such a House strike a bad balance between the three criteria discussed above, because, while such a House would have very strong legitimacy, its distinctiveness would be almost entirely lost. A wholly elected House would face the loss of the distinctive expertise that, as discussed above, renders it such an effective scrutinizer of legislation and policy.

21.  Coupled with this loss would be the certain removal of the current House's relative independence from party, with the resultant danger that the second chamber would merely duplicate in character the Commons and thus add little to the legislative and scrutinising functions carried out by that House. While the second chamber, if elected by PR, would still have a different party balance from the Commons, essentially, we would have another chamber exclusively made up of professional politicians. This would give us a narrowly-based, rather than a pluralistic House and one that, though elected, was, paradoxically, not very representative of the concerns of the people: as Shell has pointed, out, in contrast to the strongly partisan character of British MPs, "the overwhelming majority of [the electorate] have at best no more than the weakest of party allegiance.[144] Representation of different interests from those of the lower chamber is one of the classic functions of a second chamber, as is the injection of more independent viewpoints in otherwise "party-dominated Parliaments."[145] Moreover, experience has shown that it is extremely difficult for independent candidates to gain election; even under a PR system, it may be expected that the political parties would retain their stranglehold on the second chamber. Independent members would become a rarity, as in the Commons. At a stroke, this would remove the distinctive contribution made by the cross-bench Peers at present.

22.  What may be added to these familiar arguments are perspectives gleaned from the respective performances of the Commons and the Lords in dealing with the large number of anti-terrorism Bills introduced into Parliament under the last Government. The response of both Houses to the 2001 Anti-Terrorism, Crime and Security Bill, introduced into Parliament in response to the perceived greater threat from international terrorism following the attacks on America on 11 September 2001, was particularly striking. The behaviour of the Commons in relation to this Bill, one of the most draconian pieces of legislation brought before Parliament in peace-time in this or the last century, was sobering, especially for the enthusiasts for a wholly elected second chamber as the guardian of our liberty. Whilst the Lords passed a series of important amendments to the legislation, ameliorating at least some of its worst aspects, the Commons passed a Bill some 124 pages long, which partially abrogated habeas corpus, and made the UK the only country in Europe to derogate from Article 5 of the ECHR, in just 16 hours; of the 135 clauses of the Bill, precisely 86 were debated in the Commons.[146]

23.  Despite powerful reports from the Joint Committee on Human Rights,[147] warning that the Bill as drafted, almost certainly violated the ECHR, the Commons imposed not a single amendment against the Government, and then, as and when instructed to by Government Whips, obediently and repeatedly overturned Lords amendments intended to safeguard human rights and keep the proposed new powers within reasonable, internationally-endorsed limits. Although there were small back-bench rebellions, in general, party discipline was rigidly maintained. The Common's spineless performance in relation to this Bill caused one respected commentator, Hugo Young, to remark: 'In a long record of shaming fealty to whips, never have so many MPs showed such utter negligence towards so impressive a list of fundamental principles.'[148]

24.  In the light of this experience, it is suggested that anyone with a concern for basic civil liberties should be deeply concerned at the prospect of a second chamber that more or less replicated the Commons dealing with such a Bill. While a chamber elected by PR rather than first past the post would be unlikely to contain an absolute government majority, the often close rapprochement between Labour and Conservatives on anti-terrorist and crime-fighting measures, due to the electoral imperative to appear "tough on crime", would mean that the combined, whipped Labour and Conservative members would probably be able to drive through such legislation with little difficulty.[149] For those of us, therefore, who care about civil liberties, and who would like to see such legislation given particularly close and penetrating scrutiny by Parliament, the retention of a strong independent element in the Lords is vital.

25.  Against this argument, it could be pointed out that, as Russell's research has established, wholly-elected second chambers overseas tend to take a more deliberative view of legislative measures, be less partisan and show greater concern for human rights and constitutional issues than their respective first chambers; governments are also more likely to concede amendments in second chambers, partly because, in the less confrontational atmosphere that is characteristic of them, such concessions appear less like political defeats. Reasons for this include a combination of longer terms of office and a greater average age of the members, and the fact that such chambers usually have no power to unmake governments and generally lesser powers over legislation than the lower House, resulting in the imposition of less strict party discipline.[150] These factors, then, tend to result in "mature and deliberative parliamentary chambers with a less adversarial atmosphere."[151] It could therefore be argued that the concern expressed in the preceding paragraph, that a directly elected second chamber would have had little more ameliorating impact on the Anti-Terrorism Bill than the Commons, is overdone.

26.  This argument, however, fails to take account of the unique constitutional arrangements and political culture of the UK, which, it is suggested, make the addition of independent members to its reformed second chamber of peculiar, compelling importance. Not only does the UK constitution offer no judicial protection against unambiguous legislation that abrogates fundamental human rights[152]—unusually amongst Western democracies—but there is no need for special majorities in Parliament or referenda in relation to such legislation,[153] so that, legally speaking, the overall constitutional arrangements of the UK, including its protection for fundamental rights, can be altered as easily as the dog-licensing laws. In short, within such a political and constitutional context, it is uniquely important that the composition of the UK's second chamber must guarantee the presence of members who will instil a particularly strong culture of mature, objective, and long-termist scrutiny of the wisdom and necessity of any such changes, in a chamber insulated to an extent from the short term political considerations which generally drive governments and political parties. A fully elected second chamber would be unlikely to provide such members in sufficient numbers to make a difference; it is suggested that it would for this reason not be a chamber apt for the UK constitution.


126   I draw in particular on my article '"The greatest quango of them all", "a rival chamber" or "a hybrid nonsense"? Solving the second chamber paradox' (2004) Public Law 352. Back

127   Ibid, at 353 Back

128   Fifth Report, H.C. 494-i (2001-2002). Back

129   Shell, D. 'The Future of the Second Chamber' (2004) 57(4) Parliamentary Affairs 852, 855. Back

130   M. Russell, Reforming the Lords: Lessons from Overseas (Oxford: OUP, 2000) esp. pp. 163-164 and 250-254.  Back

131   Op cit, para. 8. Back

132   Constitutional Reform: Next steps for the House of Lords, H.L. 17 H.C. 171 (2002-03).para 3. Back

133   Russell at 299.  Back

134   Ibid, at 164. Back

135   Op cit, para. 8 Back

136   After Lord Strathclyde, then Conservative Leader in the Lords. Back

137   H.L. Deb. col. 830 (22 Jan 2003). Back

138   V. Bogdanor, 'Reform of the House of Lords: a Sceptical View' (1999) 70(4) Political Quarterly 375. Back

139   "Second Chambers Overseas" (1999) 70(4) Political Quarterly 411, 417. Back

140   Op cit, paras 98-99. Back

141   A House for the Future, Cm 4534, para 12.5. Back

142   See, e.g. H.L. Deb. col. 648 (21 Jan 2003), Lord Sheldon: elected members "will still claim a greater legitimacy with secretaries, research assistants and offices." "Imagine the ill-feeling if you have a hybrid House and elected Members get salaries and appointed Members do not." (ibid, col. 649 (Lady Saltoun). See also the similar fears of Baroness Seccombe, ibid, col. 653 and of Lord Gilbert, ibid, col. 818 (22 Jan 2003).  Back

143   ibid, col. 770.  Back

144   D Shell, "The Future of the Second Chamber" (1999) 70(4) Political Quarterly 390, 393. Back

145   See M. Russell, "What are Second Chambers for?" (2001) 54 Parlt. Aff,.442, 443.  Back

146   See H.L. Deb. vol. 629 col. 1533, (13 Dec 2001), Baroness Williams. Back

147   Second Report, H.C. 37, H.L. 372 (2001-02); Fifth Report, H.C. 51, H.L. 420 (2001-02). Back

148   H Young, 'Once lost, these freedoms will be impossible to restore' The Guardian, 11 December 2001. Back

149   See e.g. the analysis by F. Klug, K. Starmer and S. Weir: "Civil Liberties and the Parliamentary Watchdog: the Passage of the Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994" [1996] 49(4) Parlt. Aff. 536,542.  Back

150   Russell, op cit, p. 103-104. Back

151   Ibid, p. 103. Back

152   Under the Human Rights Act 1998 such legislation remains of full effect, even if declared incompatible by the Courts(s 4(2)and public authorities may act under it: s 6(2). Back

153   See the table in M. Russell and R. Cornes, 'The Royal Commission on Reform of the House of Lords: A House for the Future?' (2001) 64 M.L.R. 82 at 86, which shows the special powers over constitutional legislation of the second chambers of the legislatures of Australia, Canada, France, Germany, Ireland, Spain, Italy, Japan, Switzerland and the USA. Back


 
previous page contents next page


© Parliamentary copyright 2012
Prepared 23 April 2012