Draft Voting Eligibility (Prisoners) Bill - Joint Committee on the Draft Voting Eligibility (Prisoners) Bill Contents


7  Proportionality

Introduction

195. In Chapter 3 we noted that the Court, in assessing the extent of the "margin of appreciation" enjoyed by member states in interpreting Convention rights, inevitably goes on to consider what it describes as the "proportionality" of the measure in question. This assessment of proportionality was at the heart of the Court's finding in Hirst, in which the Court accepted the Government's argument that section 3 of the Representation of the People Act 1983 pursued the "legitimate aim" of "sanctioning the conduct of convicted prisoners and also of enhancing civic responsibility and respect for the rule of law", but held that it was "arbitrary in its effects". In reaching this conclusion the Court also held that there was "no evidence that Parliament has ever sought to weigh the competing interests or to assess the proportionality of a blanket ban on the right of a convicted prisoner to vote."[204]

196. It follows therefore that if Parliament were to decide to change the law with a view to complying with the Hirst judgment, and in the very likely event that further litigation were to follow, the ECtHR would not only assess whether the new law was, in its view, "proportionate", but as part of that assessment would consider the extent to which Parliament, and this Committee, had conducted a similar assessment.

197. In this chapter we accordingly consider which of the options for compliance proposed in the course of this inquiry, either by the Government or by witnesses, would be regarded as "proportionate". In so doing, we do not pre-judge Parliament's decision on whether or not to comply with the judgment, which is a matter for Parliament. Instead we seek to identify a single compliant option, which we believe to be proportionate, for Parliament to consider alongside the option of non-compliance.

The meaning of "proportionality"

198. The term "proportionality", like so many we have encountered in this inquiry, has a specific meaning in the context of ECtHR case law. As Lord Faulks QC observed, "rationality and proportionality are rather in the eye of the beholder … We are speaking a great deal with the language of the European court, which is very evolved—it has terms of art and nuances—but not all constituencies are familiar with the nuances of the European court."[205]

199. What does proportionality mean? In the context of ECtHR jurisprudence, that Court has regard to a series of factors when considering whether an interference can be justified. These will usually include whether the interference with the right is in accordance with law and is necessary in a democratic society to pursue a legitimate aim. In such cases, the Court will consider whether the extent of the encroachment is in reasonable proportion both to the seriousness of the interest being protected and the importance of the legitimate aim pursued.

200. Another way to describe the test of proportionality, in the context of sanctions imposed on offenders, is to ask whether the punishment (in this case, disenfranchisement) fits the crime. Such a test has ancient origins, as the Archbishops' Council of the Church of England reminded us: "The Bible contains insistence on proportionality in punishment—the limits of the lex talionis are set at 'an eye for an eye'".[206] We have adopted this simpler test, whether the punishment fits the crime, in considering the issue of proportionality in the remainder of this chapter.

Does proportionality require individual consideration?

201. The difficulty is to apply even a basic conception of proportionality to the multitude of unique individual cases that come before the courts. As we have noted, the ECtHR held in Hirst that "the principle of proportionality requires a discernible and sufficient link between the sanction and the conduct and circumstances of the individual concerned". Such individual assessments are of course already made in the context of the primary sanction imposed by the sentencing judge, whether custodial or non-custodial. In the words of Professor Julian Roberts:

    "A sentencing court in this or any common-law jurisdiction will consider all the factors relevant to the case in terms of culpability and harm, decisions from the Court of Appeal, the sentencing guidelines and so on. Those factors will be taken into account. They will be explicitly identified in the guidelines and in appellate judgments and they are part of the case law of common law. To assist judges in this task detailed sentencing guidelines are published by the Sentencing Council for England and Wales and analogous bodies in Scotland and Northern Ireland."[207]

202. Thus every sentencing judge is required to link the harm done by a convicted criminal to a particular point on a complex scale of punishment, including fines, community orders, suspended sentences and custodial sentences ranging from five days to life. Martin Howe QC argued that "prisoners are sent to prison for offences which vary greatly in nature and seriousness, [and] these factors are reflected in the sentence imposed. The voting disqualification lasts for the length of the sentence, and so in that respect the period of voting disqualification is proportionate to the offence."[208]

203. The difficulty in this argument lies not in the proportionality of the judge's decision to impose a custodial sentence per se, but in the proportionality (which has been rejected by the ECtHR) of adding loss of voting rights as an automatic consequence. Not only is there no reference within the sentencing guidelines to loss of voting rights as a relevant factor in deciding between a custodial and non-custodial sentence, but, as Aidan O'Neill QC noted, "it is not the length of the sentence that determines the right to vote, it is the length of detention. That means that somebody sentenced to life will regain their right to vote once they are out of prison on licence."[209] Since sentencing judges cannot anticipate the facts that will ultimately determine an individual's release date (good or bad behaviour, psychological assessment, expressions of remorse, and so on), nor can they, at the time of sentencing, predict the effect of that sentence in respect of the franchise.

204. These factors led some witnesses to conclude that the test of proportionality required individual case-by-case consideration, and an explicit decision by a judge distinct from that on sentencing—thereby adopting the approach of the ECtHR in the case of Frodl v Austria, an outcome which was significantly modified in the later case of Scoppola v Italy (No. 3). The AIRE Centre cited "the crucial importance of retaining some element of judicial discretion on the decision to disenfranchise a prisoner",[210] and Lord Ramsbotham said that "I would leave everything to do with length firmly in the hands of the judge."[211]

205. The Government, on the other hand, noted the "additional burden"[212] such a requirement would place upon sentencing judges, and invited us to consider whether decisions should be appealed. Professor Roberts opposed the introduction of a new element of judicial discretion relating to the seriousness of the offence: "the seriousness threshold … is problematic. Presumably, the courts would devise guidance as to the nature of the crimes … that were so egregiously wrongful as to justify this, but it would require the exercise of judicial discretion, and it would be tricky for a court to make those distinctions."[213]

Linking loss of voting rights to specific offences

206. There are some offences for which disenfranchisement, with or without imprisonment, could be regarded as obviously "fitting the crime"—notably those offences which might be seen as undermining the fabric of democratic social order. It is in fact already the case that individuals convicted of illegal or corrupt practices in the conduct of elections are subject to a disqualification from registering to vote of up to five years, irrespective of whether or not they have been sentenced to a term of imprisonment.[214] A similar approach, but extended to include, for instance, terrorism offences, has been adopted in Germany.[215]

207. Dr Dirk van Zyl Smit urged us to adopt the same approach in the UK: "If you were to recommend, say, that someone convicted of treason or a crime against the state, or of an electoral offence were to lose the right to vote … I would be very surprised if that did not stand up [in the ECtHR] because you could say that this is an appropriate punishment for that sort of offence." He did not envisage such punishment extending to other serious offences such as rape: "I would say that we are talking not about the moral blameworthiness of the offender but the appropriateness of removing the right to vote for a particular offence."[216]

208. The implication of Dr van Zyl Smit's approach is, as the Government put it, that "offenders who might potentially be serving long sentences [would] retain the vote on the basis that they were not convicted of a particular offence."[217] In other words, an offender convicted of a relatively minor offence relating to the conduct of elections would lose the right to vote, whereas someone convicted of murder would not.

209. We have noted, in chapter 5, the argument of Professor Waldron that the vote should be regarded as a "power", and that there is a legitimate discussion as to "whether people who have shown disregard for the rights and interests of others should, for the time being, be entrusted by their fellow citizens with that minuscule power over them."[218] This consideration is, we believe, a factor underlying the strong public opposition to giving convicted prisoners the vote, and we therefore do not consider that an outcome which would result in those convicted of the most heinous crimes being able to vote would be acceptable to either Parliament or the electorate. This in turn lends support to an approach involving an element of automaticity, whereby those convicted of crimes of a certain level of seriousness, who have shown utter disregard for the rights of others, would be temporarily disenfranchised without the need for separate judicial decision-making.

Linking disenfranchisement to sentence length

210. The Government's proposal, as set out in the draft Bill, is to link loss of voting rights to sentence length, with the three options setting the threshold at 4 years, 6 months, or the imposition of any custodial sentence, respectively. In each case this means, as Professor Roberts noted, linking loss of voting rights to the seriousness of the crime, and using "sentence length as a proxy for crime seriousness."[219]

211. The evidence cited in Chapter 6 suggests that a cut-off which takes effect at the point an offender is given an immediate custodial sentence may be somewhat arbitrary in its effects. But the same will be true of any other cut-off set by reference to sentence length—sentence length will always be, as Dr Susan Easton put it, a "rudimentary measure with which to distinguish offenders and offending."[220] Aidan O'Neill QC noted that "there are going to be people who fall on the wrong side or the right side of that … rule."[221] The Government acknowledged accordingly that any ban based on sentence length risked being regarded by the ECtHR as "general, automatic and indiscriminate."[222]

212. Wherever the threshold is set, there will be hard cases just above and just below. Nevertheless, we heard persuasive arguments in support of the Government's position that sentence length was the best indicator of the seriousness of the offence. Professor Roberts acknowledged that courts "think very carefully about the length of sentence; there is a custodial threshold prior to the imposition of a term of custody. It is a good index."[223] Asked about the use of sentence length as a measure of crime seriousness, Paul McDowell of NACRO said that "I do not think it is ideal, but I do not know of a better measure."[224] Lord Faulks agreed: "The particular facts of the case are much better reflected in the sentence than by the description of the offence. Although it is arbitrary … if you are going to have a cut-off point, it is better to do it by length of sentence."[225] We agree.

Setting the threshold

213. The Draft Bill proposes two possible thresholds: 6 months and 4 years. We have received much evidence on the advantages and disadvantages of these thresholds, but no conclusive logical case been made for either of them. In the words of Professor Mike Hough and Professor Julian Roberts, "there is no significance [in either]; both are arbitrary thresholds."[226]

214. A threshold of 6 months equates to the sentencing powers of magistrates' courts in respect of a single offence, though sentences of up to 12 months may be imposed by a magistrate in respect of multiple offences—indeed, Professor Hough and Professor Roberts confirmed that 810 individuals sentenced in magistrates' courts in 2012 were given custodial sentences of more than 6 months.[227] Moreover, as the Government pointed out, "it is possible for an offender sentenced in a Crown Court to be given a shorter sentence."[228] In reality, of 90,386 people convicted in the Crown Court in 2012 only 50,683 received custodial sentences at all, of whom 41,460 (just 46 percent of those sentenced) received sentences of over 6 months.[229] The link between the 6-month threshold and the sentencing powers of magistrates' courts is thus weak.

215. The arguments in favour of a 4-year threshold are little stronger. As the option in the draft Bill which would enfranchise the largest number of prisoners, it was preferred by many witnesses. For instance, Angela Patrick, while stating her preference for a system of judicial discretion, described 4 years as the "most likely to be considered proportionate" of the options in the draft Bill.[230] However, the choice of 4 years appears to be, in itself, arbitrary. The Government noted that both the Criminal Justice Act 1991 and the Legal Aid, Sentencing and Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 used 4 years as "an indicator of seriousness."[231] But this is a circular argument, against which must be set the relatively large number of serious offenders who, if such a threshold were adopted, would be enfranchised. We see no likelihood that either Parliament or the wider population will accept a 4-year threshold.

216. An alternative was proposed to us by Robert Walter MP, namely that the threshold should be set at 12 months. In defence of this proposal Mr Walter noted that, as we have shown in Chapter 2 of this Report, the Forfeiture Act 1870 tied the loss of voting rights to imprisonment for a felony leading to a sentence of more than 12 months. The result of this Act, and subsequent legislation, was that at the time the UK signed the ECHR prisoners sentenced to terms of imprisonment of 12 months or less were able to and did vote in elections. Mr Walter accordingly proposed that "we should go for a return to the situation that persisted at the time we signed the Convention."[232] Mr Walter also noted that 12 months was the maximum sentence length that can be imposed by a magistrates' court, in respect of multiple offences. This linkage would, in Mr Walter's view, be "easily understandable, both by our colleagues and the British public."[233] It would mean that no prisoner would lose the right to vote unless sentenced by a judge sitting in the Crown Court.

217. Another argument may be advanced in support of a 12-month threshold: at present, under section 1 of the Representation of the People Act 1981, any person sentenced to a term of imprisonment of more than one year shall be disqualified, while detained, shall be disqualified from sitting in or being elected or nominated to the House of Commons.[234] It could be argued that, if a prisoner who has been sentenced to a term of less than 1 year is entitled to sit as a Member of Parliament, or to stand for election, that prisoner should also be able to vote in a parliamentary election (including for himself, if standing as a candidate). Thus a 12-month threshold would help in bringing consistency across relevant statutory provisions.

Regaining the right to vote

218. The establishment of a threshold for disenfranchisement would not rule out the possibility that prisoners serving longer sentences could regain the vote as they approach the end of their detention. As we have noted in Chapter 5, such reinstatement of voting rights could help re-engage prisoners with their responsibilities to the wider community, thereby contributing to prisoner rehabilitation.

219. We see two possible approaches to prisoner re-enfranchisement. The first would require prisoner to "earn back" the right to vote—in other words, a mechanism could be established whereby prisoners would be able to apply for reinstatement of the franchise, for instance at any point after becoming eligible to apply for parole. As part of the application, they would be required to demonstrate their suitability, either on the basis of general good conduct, or by completing particular educational programmes, such as a citizenship course.

220. An argument in favour of this approach is that, by introducing an element of individual consideration of each prisoner's needs (comparable in nature to the process whereby those stripped of voting rights in Italy are able to apply for their reinstatement), it would help meet the test of proportionality, as set out in ECtHR jurisprudence. It could also deliver benefits in terms of prisoner rehabilitation, by providing an incentive to prisoners to engage with their wider social responsibilities. Against this approach, on the other hand, is the cost and the drain on resources inherent in adding a new layer of judicial or other individual consideration. We also heard forceful objections from some prisoners to the suggestion that they should be required to "earn back" the right to vote.[235]

221. An alternative would be automatic reinstatement of the franchise as each prisoner approaches release—for example, at a point six months before the scheduled release date. This approach would be simple and cost-effective: the onus would be on the prisoner, having reached the scheduled point in their sentence, and on provision of a certificate to this effect by the prison authorities, to apply to be added to the electoral roll in the constituency into which they are scheduled to be released, on the basis of a declaration of local connection. There would be opportunities to use this reinstatement of voting rights as a means of promoting rehabilitation and civic responsibility in the months leading up to release.

222. The main disadvantage of this proposal is its unpredictability—scheduled release dates are by definition prospective, and can be pushed back if a prisoner is guilty of misconduct or some further offence. It would also require the use of a prospective address as the basis for establishing a local connection. As the Electoral Management Board for Scotland noted, "allowing 'local connection' to a future address will … involve a change to the legislation defining local connection."[236]

Conclusions of the Committee

223. The test of proportionality requires, in our view, that the punishment (disenfranchisement) should be a proportionate means of achieving the aim of sanctioning the conduct of convicted prisoners and also of enhancing civic responsibility and respect for the rule of law. This requires that the punishment should "fit the crime".

224. We do not believe that it is feasible to require judicial consideration of the possible loss of voting rights in each individual case. Judges already take full account of the particular facts of each case in passing sentence, and we see no case for duplicating this complex and laborious task in respect of voting rights.

225. We do not consider that linking loss of voting rights to specific offences seen as undermining the fabric of democratic social order, while allowing those convicted of the most heinous crimes, including murder, to retain the vote, would be acceptable to public opinion or to Parliament.

226. Sentence length, though arguably a rudimentary measure, remains the best indicator of the seriousness of each individual offence, and thus the best means of determining the point at which the prohibition on prisoner voting should take effect.

227. On balance, if some convicted prisoners are to be enfranchised, we find the arguments for a 12-month threshold, reinstating the pre-1967 position and bringing prisoner voting rights into line with their existing right to sit in or stand for election to the House of Commons, more persuasive than those advanced for either a 6-month or a 4-year threshold.

228. We believe that allowing prisoners to regain the right to vote as they approach the end of their sentence, by showing that the loss of the right to vote is supplemented by measures promoting prisoners' reintegration into society, would assist in demonstrating the proportionality of whatever approach is adopted to prisoner disenfranchisement.


204   Hirst, paragraph 79 Back

205   Q 41 Back

206   Written evidence from the Archbishops' Council, Church of England Back

207   Q 86 Back

208   Written evidence from Martin Howe QC Back

209   Q 34 Back

210   Written evidence from the AIRE Centre Back

211   Q 23 Back

212   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government Back

213   Q 91 Back

214   Sections 160 and 173 of the Representation of the People Act 1983 Back

215   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government; Q 51 Back

216   Q 48 Back

217   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government Back

218   Q 119 Back

219   Q 84 Back

220   Written evidence from Dr Susan Easton Back

221   Q 41 Back

222   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government Back

223   Q 85 Back

224   Q 129 Back

225   Q 33 Back

226   Written evidence from Professor Mike Hough and Professor Julian Roberts Back

227   Ibid Back

228   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government Back

229   Written evidence from Professor Mike Hough and Professor Julian Roberts Back

230   Q 43 Back

231   Written evidence from Her Majesty's Government Back

232   Q 138 Back

233   Q 138 Back

234   Erskine May, 24th Edition (2011), p 35 Back

235   See Appendix 5 Back

236   Written evidence from the Electoral Management Board for Scotland Back


 
previous page contents next page


© Parliamentary copyright 2013
Prepared 18 December 2013