Memorandum from the National Secular Society
PREAMBLE
1. The Executive Director of the Society
and Dr David Nash gave evidence at the Committee's hearing on
18 July 2002. The following written evidence on the Society's
behalf is also submitted, comprising three parts.
2. Below are considerations from a legal
perspective of criminalising offence to "feelings".
They were prepared at our request by Colm O'Cinneide, lecturer
in law at University College London.
3. Informal discussions following the hearing
led us to understand that the suitability of the relevant provisions
of the Indian Penal Code were being examined as a possible template
for prospective legislation in the UK. Dr Nash had already been
aware from previous work of historic problems concerning the Code
and had already discussed them with the Executive Director before
the hearing. We therefore undertook to provide detailed evidence
on this very specialised but nevertheless highly relevant topic,
and are incorporated in the two attachments, both specifically
prepared for this submission at our request.
4. The first attachment is prepared by Dr
Nash and deals with historic difficulties, including telling evidence
concerning the British Government's rejection of proposals to
be incorporated into British law in the 1930s. The second attachment
was drawn up by the Executive Director of the International Humanist
and Ethical Union, who is himself an Indian. Mr Gogineni's deep
concern, bordering on incredulity, of the possibility of these
particular provisions being incorporated into UK law constitute
in our opinion a powerful testament. I will send you the attachments
shortly, after I have had a chance to do some minor editing and
considered the presentation.
CRIMINALISING OFFENCE
TO "FEELINGS"
5. The use of the criminal law to prohibit
offending the sensibilities or feelings of particular groups in
society is inherently problematic, creating as it does insurmountable
issues of legal uncertainty and imposing a major "chilling
effect" on free speech, in other words, self censorship.
The chequered history of the common law offence of blasphemous
libel illustrates this, and demonstrates the serious problems
that will arise in respect of any offence that is aimed at protecting
sensibilities. Much of the debate on blasphemy has centred on
the restriction of its scope to the beliefs of the Church of England:
however, the key problems with blasphemy stem directly from the
nature of the offence rather than its scope. Attempt to reform
blasphemous libel or the creation of a new offence of offending
religious feelings will just replicate and extend the corrosive
effects of the out-dated existing law, while failing to address
any of the tangible harms that have been cited in support of an
extended offence.
6. International human rights law has established
a general requirement that any law that curtails free speech has
to be proportionate, justified by compelling social needs and
provide a sufficient degree of legal certainty that will enable
those potentially affected by the law to be able to predict adequately
the consequences of their actions. The requirements of proportionality
and legal certainty are particularly important in that restrictions
on free speech may have a "chilling effect" out of all
proportion to the actual scope of the restriction in question.
These requirements are firmly established in the jurisprudence
of the European Court of Human Rights, the US Supreme Court, and
of other constitutional courts, as well as in the work of the
leading academic, legal and philosophical commentators on free
speech. While the European Court of Human Rights has upheld blasphemy
laws in Wingrove v UK[22]
and Otto-Preminger Institut v Austria[23],
both of these decisions relied upon the "margin of appreciation"
given to signatory states of the Convention in how they protect
morals. Whether the UK should protect religious feelings from
offence requires an analysis of the impact of such laws on free
speech that is not confined to the legal issue of whether such
laws are permitted under the Convention, which provides a floor
rather than a ceiling for human rights protection in the UK. The
United States Supreme Court has held that such laws violate free
speech. [24]
Justification
7. The impact and application of blasphemous
libel in English law has proved seriously damaging to free speech
in two interconnected aspects, both of which will similarly apply
to any offence founded on criminalising offence to "feelings".
Originally used to curtail free speech and critical inquiry, even
in its later use as a tool for protecting sensibilities blasphemy
has had a corrosive impact on free expression, by firstly disproportionately
restricting the use of particular forms and types of comment for
ill-defined reasons and in the absence of visible harm, while
secondly violating the requirements of legal certainty and thereby
casting a "chilling effect" over a wide range of expression
beyond the intended scope of the law.
8. As David Feldman, legal adviser to the
Joint Select Committee on Human Rights has noted[25],
blasphemy makes a distinction between "appeals to judgment"
carried on in a "sober and temperate and decent style"
in the words of Lord Denman CJ in R v Hetherington[26],
and appeals to raw feelings in the form of rhetoric, metaphor
or imagery, which are deemed to constitute blasphemy if they constitute
an "appeal to the wild and improper feelings of the human
mind", again in the words of Lord Denman. This is so even
if the metaphorical or rhetorical appeal to "wild . . . feelings"
are actually expressions of religious belief, as they were in
the case of the poem held to be blasphemous in R v Lemon[27].
As Feldman notes, this distinction between different forms of
argument is difficult to defend, and is based on nineteenth-century
notions of rationalist debate that have been decisively rejected
in other areas of the law. Any extension of blasphemy to encompass
outrage to religious feelings in general will preserve this distinction.
9. In addition, this distinction is designed
not to prevent any discernable form of harm to the rights of others,
as there is and can be no right not to be offended. In particular,
there is no link between any offence of offending feelings and
the protection of religious groups against incitement of hatred.
Legislation prohibiting harassment, incitement to hatred or the
breach of public order is entirely adequate for preventing the
use of rhetorical or metaphorical speech in the public sphere
from causing violence or breaches of public order. Maintaining
public order therefore cannot be a justification for this offence.
Indeed, any offence modelled on the Indian law prohibiting giving
offence to religious feelings would for example permit a speaker
who painstakingly praised the virtues of the Muslim religion to
simultaneously castigate and incite hatred against the followers
of that religion, in the same way that some Nazi propaganda used
to distinguish between the Jewish religion and the "degenerate"
state of those who practiced this religion in modern times.
10. Offences based on hurt to religious
feelings or their absence also protect a particular type of sentiment,
while not protecting other forms of feelings or belief that if
attacked in an intemperate manner may cause similar levels of
hurt or indignation. For example, deeply held political beliefs
such as veneration for a particular political philosophy or leader,
or pride in one's nation, are not protected, and any legislation
that did protect these beliefs against intemperate and rhetorical
attacks would be plainly viewed as massively restrictive of free
speech. In addition, there is no requirement to show that intense
shock to deeply-held feelings was actually inflicted. As Geoffrey
Robertson QC noted in respect of the film held to be blasphemous
by the BBFC in the case of Wingrove v UK[28],
this decision protected certain religious groups from "self-induced
discomfort at the thought that some other adult would be able
to view it without being shocked".[29]
11. The protection of religious freedom
in Article 9 of the ECHR can of course as the ECrtHR noted in
Otto-Preminger be violated in extreme cases "where
the effect of particular methods of opposing or denying religious
beliefs can be such as to inhibit those who hold such beliefs
from exercising their freedom to hold and express them".[30]
However, offences involving hurt to religious feelings, including
blasphemy, do not require any element of inhibiting religious
belief: offence or outrage alone can trigger a conviction, which
is wildly disproportionate.
12. The justification for religious offence
laws with their considerable restraint on free speech is therefore
based on arbitrary distinctions and lacks a compelling rationale
which would justify such restraint: no basic rights or entitlements
are being violated. This remains equally true in respect of the
Indian legislation as it does of the current blasphemous laws
in the UK.
Legal Uncertainty and Chilling Effect
13. In addition, any offence of hurting
religious sensibilities will invariably have an uncertain ambit,
and consequently as with the blasphemous libel laws result in
a considerable "chilling effect" on free speech. As
noted above, the distinction between temperate and intemperate
criticism of religious beliefs is imprecise: hence there is no
satisfactory method of determining what speech will be deemed
blasphemous. Feldman notes that the actus reus of the crime
of blasphemy has been "expressed in so many different ways
that it is hard to know what conduct is caught by it", and
cites multiple and varying definitions of blasphemy. [31]There
appears for example to be no clear reason why the poem in R
v Lemon which was written from a religious perspective was
deemed to be offensive, whereas Nietzsche's assaults on Christianity
as a "slave religion" are regarded as central of controversial
features of the western philosophical tradition, and taught as
such in first-year university philosophy courses.
14. The Mens rea for blasphemous
libel is at present minimal: intention to cause shock and offence,
or even recklessness as to the possibility of causing shock is
not required. While the Indian legislation requires intent to
outrage religious feelings, whether or not such feelings will
be outraged at any given case is still dependant on the perception
by others of the nature of the speech acts in question. Nor is
there any clear distinction possible between challenging beliefs
and outraging those same beliefs, a crucial lack of clarity which
is reflected in the actual experience of the Indian legislation
(see accompanying documents). Under any form of offence to religious
feeling, the nature of the required actus reus and Mens
rea is uncertain to a degree perhaps unmatched in criminal
law.
15. The uncertainty prevents individuals
from being able to determine the consequences of their speech
acts to any reasonable degree. This both ensures an unacceptable
degree of legal uncertainty and casts a "chilling effect"
over a variety of speech acts, including any artistic or philosophical
works that use strong rhetoric or imagery to discuss religious
issues. The Irish Supreme Court, notwithstanding references in
the Irish Constitution to the central role of religious belief,
held in Corway v Independent Newspapers (Ireland) Ltd.
[32]that
the common law offence of blasphemous libel was too imprecise
to be compatible with the constitutional guarantee of due process
of law.
16. Any offence based on the notion of hurt
to religious feelings will therefore share the core defects of
blasphemy: a lack of legal uncertainty leading to a consequential
chilling effect, as well as a lack of justification for the artificial
distinctions imposed. Extending blasphemy will open up additional
areas of uncertainty and speech restraint, for no discernable
gain in terms of protecting vulnerable groups or basic rights.
In casting a shadow over any future Satanic Verses, extending
or preserving blasphemy is an unsustainable legislative option
if the core requirements for thriving free speech are to be maintained
in the context of religious debate.
ECCLESIASTICAL COURTS
JURISDICTION ACT
1860, SECTION 2
17. We would like to reinforce the opposition
we expressed at the hearing to the above. Because this legislation
is an example of religious privilege, we supported Peter Tatchell
in defending the case concerning Dr Carey giving an Easter sermon
at Canterbury Cathedral. The Committee may be surprised to learn
that there was deep unease among those concerned with justice
and human rights about the disproportionate severity of the potential
penalty and the potentially of partiality, and even religious
influence, over magistrates' court hearing. A large number of
prominent supporters decried the prosecution, in the form of a
letter to The Times, one of the signatories of which was
the former Scottish Primus, Dr Richard Holloway. Amnesty International
were sufficiently disturbed that, rather than simply express their
concern, they formally became involved in defending Tatchell as
they do prisoners of conscience. It was only after the application
of pressure by them and a number of QCs, one of which even felt
so strongly he offered his services free, that a stipendiary magistrate
from London took over the case, this being the best solution possible
under the law as it stands. We have already referred you to the
£18.60 fine imposed by the magistrate, appearing to give
a clearand as far as I'm aware unprecendentedsignal
of contempt for the law.
The statistics of convictions support our view
that there is no need for this privileged legislation, a throwback
to the time when the Church yielded draconian powerand
we appeal to the committee not to bend to their calls for the
legislation to be retained. Especially if, as we suggested, any
disturbances and funeralswhether or not religiousand
dealt with in the same way as those for public meetings, there
seem to be practically no instances where offences, such as sexual
acts, could not be prosecuted other legislation Examples such
as the pig's head being placed in a mosque are most unlikely to
take place without the commission of criminal damage or some other
offence. We hope that the widespread concern that we described
above will weigh more heavily with the committee and persuade
it to repeal Section 2 which seems to us alien in this age of
human rights. We have been advised this Section may be wide open
to challenge in future cases under Art. 6 ECHR (fair trial) on
account of the partial nature of the tribunal.
APPENDIX 1
THE INDIAN CRIMINAL CODE OF 1860 (REVISED
1927) SOME THOUGHTS UPON ITS PROVISIONS AND THEIR HISTORICAL CONTEXT
PREPARED BY DR DAVID NASH, HISTORIAN AND AUTHOR OF SEVERAL BOOKS
ON BLASPHEMY
PREAMBLE
1. In recent discussions around the issues
of blasphemy and religious hatred before the House of Lords Select
Committee on Religious Offences consideration of the provisions
of the Indian Criminal Code has been mentioned. In discussions
with the Clerk to the Committee it appears that the investigation
of this and its provisions is being considered as offering a possible
model for future legislation in this area of English law.
2. Thus we thought it may be helpful to
the Committee for me to re-visit my own researches in this area
and to offer my opinions upon the advisability or otherwise of
this course of action.
3. I presume that the two particular sections
of the Code envisaged as models are sections 295a and 298 the
text of these two provisions (according to the 1860 edition) is
as follows
4. 295-A Deliberate and malicious acts
intended to outrage religious feelings of any class by insulting
its religion or religious beliefs
5. Whoever, with deliberate and malicious
intention of outraging the religious feelings of any class or
citizens of India, by words, either spoken or written, or by signs
or by visible representations or otherwise, insults or attempts
to insult the religion or the religious beliefs of that class,
shall be punished with imprisonment of either description for
a term which may extend to three years, or with fine, or with
both.
and
6. 298 Uttering words, etc, with deliberate
intent to wound religious feelings.
7. Whoever, with the deliberate intention
of wounding the religious feelings of any person, utters any word
or makes any sound in the hearing of that person or makes any
gesture in the sight of that person or places any object in the
sight of that person, shall be punished with imprisonment of either
description for a term which may extend to one year, or with fine,
or with both.
8. As I will suggest below there are considerable
problems with taking the provisions of the Indian Criminal Code
as a reliable model on which to base prospective legislation.
In emphasising this I want to allude particularly to the historical
context of this because there are two overriding reasons why this
is especially relevant to this issue. Firstly the assumptions
behind the construction of the Indian Criminal Code itself do
need some consideration. More importantly the possible use of
the Indian Criminal Code as a Model for constructing new religious
offences has been considered before and the attitude of the Home
Office was to express great scepticism about its potential utility.
Many of the concerns offered in 1930 mirror concerns with an emphatically
contemporary resonance. Indeed the problems encountered in 1930
would now appear to be significantly amplified and have been joined
by new problems that were scarcely envisaged then. Many of the
problems already identified around a new offence of Incitement
to Religious Hatred also apply to an introduction of the provisions
of the Indian Criminal Code. Whilst the Code represents a law
that has been enacted and is on a statute book it is not by any
means a useful example to emulate or draw inspiration from.
CONTEXT OF
THE CODE'S
CONSTRUCTION
9. There is no escaping the fact that the
Indian Criminal Code was constructed in a clearly imperial context
by a ruling power intending to legislate for and actively govern
a subordinate possession and its population. Its construction
in 1860 came a mere three years after the Indian Mutiny and must
in some senses be seen as a response to some of the concerns raised
from this catastrophic incident. Nonetheless the Indian Criminal
Code has been seen by many as a far-sighted and, in the context
of the times, remarkably liberal document. [33]It
was constructed, in the main, by the Lawyer James Fitzjames Stephen,
an individual who had a significant legal reputation. [34]On
occasions Stephen could hold controversial views and he was later
to condemn the (Justice John Duke) Coleridge judgement in the
Foote case of 1883-84 and its attempts to make a blasphemy law
more "civilised" when it should, to his mind have been
abolished. [35]In
this he openly criticised Justice Coleridge's conduct of the Foote
case, and the resulting judgment. Such criticism of a serving
judge was, at that time, almost certainly unprecedented.
PREVIOUS CONSIDERATION
IN 1930
10. Since the Foote case there has been
regular lobbying to repeal the blasphemy statutes and Common Law
of blasphemous libel. This has generally taken the form of petitions
to the Home Secretary, sometimes leading to a private member's
bill in parliament. Since the 1890s such lobbying took place regularly,
becoming especially potent during the 1920s, and culminating in
a campaign in 1929-30. This resulted in the Home Office giving
serious consideration to blasphemy repeal and extension, as well
as allied issues.
11. When a repeal bill was introduced in
1929, the Home Secretary J R Clynes received a deputation which
called for the abolition of the blasphemy laws as contrary to
the "spirit of the age".
12. The deputation insisted the application
of the law was muddled, inconsistent and capable of almost arbitrary
interpretation. One member of the deputation, Graham Wallas, suggested
that the way forward would be for parliament to frame and enact
laws relating to public peace that could be used to protect all
religions. In reply the Home Secretary Clynes admitted that he
was sympathetic to the cause of reform but closed the door to
any government involvement in the issue. Instead he hoped that
a private member's bill would be the answer since the composition
of the Commons may have allowed the proposal to stand a decent
chance. Although Clynes had pleaded that lack of parliamentary
time prevented the government from taking any action he was nonetheless
advised strongly against further legislation by officials in the
Home Office. In their briefing document to Clynes for the meeting
he was advised that repealing the statutes against blasphemy was
an irrelevance whilst the operation of the Common Law offence
could safely be left to the sound judgement and practice embodied
in the Coleridge judgement and the case law that it subsequently
influenced. The Home Office here demonstrated that it was particularly
concerned with the public order implications and was most anxious
that these were preserved. Whilst the old statutory provisions,
it was admitted, would remove grievances concerning the one-sidedness
of the law this course should only be followed "provided
the law against speech or action tending to breach of the peace
is safeguarded."[36]
13. With a Labour Victory the previous year
1930 saw the bill considered in Cabinet as well as receive a second
reading during which the labour member for Bermondsey, Alfred
Salter, spoke movingly of the penalties meted out to his Quaker
ancestors. [37]By
this stage Clynes was echoing the advice of his department in
recommending that the bill be amended in committee so as to ensure
that breaches of the peace could still be encompassed by the law,
and said as much in Parliament. [38]Subsequent
advice from the Home Office also saw alteration of the law as
inevitably linked to dangers inherent in the "spirit of the
age" argument. If this were acknowledged then the law should
protect all forms of religious beliefa rhetorical suggestion
in Home Office memos which was clearly intended to convey their
position which was that blanket protection was unreasonable. [39]
14. In addressing the numerous problems
posed by the Bill, the Home Office advised that it be amended.
Various suggestions were offered, any of which would have considerably
reduced the bill's attempt to deal with grievances. The route
of amendment involved either safeguarding the power to prosecute
in cases where a breach of the peace occurred or creating a new
offence of penalising attacks upon all religious feeling backed
up by the power to imprison rather than merely fine offenders.
To lend weight to these suggestions passages from the Indian Penal
Code (section 295 a and section 298) the Metropolitan Police Act
of 1839 (Section 54: 12 and 13) and elements within the Good Rule
and Government Byelaws[40]
which covered indecent and threatening language were offered as
potential models and useful areas of guidance. From this discussion
two amendments emerged: one appending a proviso requiring actual
breach of the peace and another intended to protect religious
feelings by prohibiting the use of language, drawing, gesture
or representation intended to insult or wound and "calculated
to cause a breach of the peace." [41]Advice
from the Director of Public Prosecutions was firmly against the
second course of action and the dangers inherent in the creation
of a new offence which would have had considerable civil liberties
repercussions. Moreover the DPP anticipated trouble in the provisions
which sought to protect religion of any kind, although it was
not made clear whether this objection related to the extension
to non-Christian faiths, or whether it would also have applied
were the law only to be extended to other Christian denominations.
[42]
15. The DPP, J A Stainton, offered the Home
Office three suggested versions of the amendment for consideration.
The least liberal sought to define the expression of blasphemy
to include words writing and publishing content which would outrage
and provoke breaches of the peace. The more liberal versions,
however, sought to distinguish between attacking and impugning
religious convictions and merely impugning them in the course
of potential breaches of the peace[43]
These three clauses appeared to have embraced different aspects
of the Indian Code solution without following through its logic
of universal protection for all religions. The first identified
explicitly, in the manner of the Indian Code, the methods by which
offensive matter could enter the public domain yet required a
proof of calculated intention on the part of the blasphemer to
"outrage the religious convictions of any persons and thus
to provoke a breach of the peace". The two others ignored
the catalogue of means in favour of a more generalised statement
which aimed at protecting the religious convictions from any assault
upon them regardless of the intention of offender and, arguably,
the behaviour of the offender against. This in truth was an ill
fitting attempt to adapt the Indian Code to English conditions.
In its way it perhaps represents a recognition that religion needed
protection as an aspect of personal conviction rather than as
a widely accepted social ideology. However it was also designed
to close the door to total abolition of the laws related to religious
opinion which the bill represented and constituted an attempt
to liberalise the law without conceding the case for a pluralisation
of its application. [44]
16. The Home Office itself was by now convinced
that the solution was to, as far as possible, "allow the
bill to die". Thus it hoped that amendments would perform
this unenviable task while the Home Office continued in its round
of canvassing opinion and gathering evidence so that it would
influence any course the bill and its proceedings might take.
However advice from the Committee stage of the bill was less than
helpful. It recommended amending the bill to prevent the actions
of an individual "outraging the religious convictions of
any other person." This was modelled on the revised Indian
Code of 1927 which had substituted the public order influenced
notion of "outrage" for the previously introspective
notion of "wounding". The logic of recourse to the Indian
Code was also stated as a recommended amendmentthat the
protection of all religions should be strongly linked to the question
of breach of the peace. This however could not be done, so advice
argued, without sweeping away all existing lawsecclesiastical,
common or statute related to blasphemy.
17. This restatement, or redefinition, of
the offence itself opened a whole new can of worms which the Parliamentary
Committee had considered at length. The phrases "religion"
or "religious convictions" were clearly an essential
part of the offence and the Committee admitted that this "...has
no very precise meaning. Is it for instance to be an offence to
attack Mormonism or the Agapemonities?" [45]
18. The Committee, aware of the Gordian
knot it tied, offered a way out of the problem. Clearly any attempt
to define the word religious was farcicalas the Committee
itself pithily stated "The draftsman by a stroke of the pen
would have to solve a question which has been the subject to theological
controversy for centuries." Citing religions by name was
a dangerous strategy which would cause endless debate about which
religions to include or exclude. The impossibility of reaching
such decisions was manifest and indeed the suggestion that such
decisions might be rescinded in the light of scholarship was clearly
hinted at in the example cited of a recent work which argued that
Hinduism was "hardly worthy of the name religion". Moreover
this whole state of affairs would make the law a perpetual movable
feast and would do nothing to settle the matter once and for all,
an element that was clearly uppermost in the mind of those at
the Home Office. If the blasphemy laws were to be altered at all
this should only be done if a satisfactory long term resolution
could be had. The solution that the parliamentary Committee suggested
would be to leave the definition of "religion" out of
the measure. This was an outcome that must have greatly pleased
those at the Home Office since this served to keep the sovereignty
of public opinion, in the shape of juries, untouched. The Parliamentary
committee however pointed out that such juries would be pronouncing
on the vexed question that theologians had previously baulked
at. Moreover there was also an inherent problem of identifying
words which appropriately drew the line between "fair criticism"
and "outrageous attack". Simply put, this objection
uttered concerns that legislation would prevent temperate criticism
which would have no universal measure of outrageous other than
the sensibilities of the religious adherent so attacked and the
predilections of the jury. The Indian Code emphasis on intention
was no help here either sinceas the Home Office emphasised:
19. "The ordinary law is that a man
is held to intend the natural consequences of his acts. Any clause
requiring a jury to look beyond the natural consequences of the
acts proved in evidence, and to look into the mind of the prisoner
would be considerable departure from the present law and would
lead to great difficulty in its application." [46]
20. The analogy of the law of libel was
similarly considered and rejected. In this instance a successful
defence that the words complained of were true and publication
was in the public interest was unworkable when brought to the
example of blasphemy. Visions of courtroom attempts to prove the
truth or otherwise of words spoken against various deities had
an air of farce and the committee wisely suggested that such protracted
proceedings would clearly offend believers far more than any potentially
blasphemous publication or utterance was likely to. The committee
saw the only way out in a proposal which asserted that the matter
published "must not only be calculated to provoke a breach
of the Peace but, must also be in its nature grossly offensive."
Once again the Committee admitted that there were problems even
here not least in the definition of the central words used in
the new offence. The definition of "scurrilous", garnered
from the OED was taken to mean, somewhat unhelpfully, "using
such language as only the license of a buffoon can warrant; characterised
by coarseness or indecency of language, in jesting or invective;
grossly opprobrious or jocular." Such a definition of the
law would clearly have inflamed any cases conducted under its
auspicesonly a small leap of imagination is necessary to
envisage what (albeit in very different ways) George Jacob Holyoake
in the 1840s, George William Foote in the 1880s or John William
Gott in the 1920s would have said in court and the press about
such a law. The Committee was rather happier with its formulation
of the notion of outrage which, again courtesy of the OED, was
taken to mean "to do violence to; to subject to outrage;
to wrong grossly, treat with gross violence or indignity."
21. The use of the word "publication"
was also given consideration. Despite the apparent wish of some
to extend the law to cover actions and conduct, the Committee
swiftly agreed that this would represent an inadvisable extension
of the laws. Clearly the Parliamentary Committee realised the
express need to minimise potential grievances and to limit the
potential use of the law as far as possible. The Committee also
recognised that the government were also clearly intending to
exclude Northern Ireland from such legislation since the Government
of Ireland Act gave Stormont powers to legislate for such matters
and any interference from Westminster would amount to "constitutional
impropriety" on the part of the Imperial Parliament. The
situation in Scotland was slightly different since its exclusion
from such an Act was on the grounds that the Lord Advocate's powers
represented sufficient discretion to regulate the law.
22. Some of the arguments advanced by repealers
and those opposed to the laws as they currently stood were themselves
on occasions not calculated to make the decision for government
easier. In my opinion, the suggestion that the Indian Code might
form the basis of a solution unhelpfully complicated the debate.
Once the whole question of extending the laws beyond Christianity
came on the agenda it was no surprise to find civil servants and
senior government figures baulking at problems associated with
finding a working definition of religion.
23. A second problem which highlighted this
conception of the law as a potential anachronism was the accusation
that the existing law and the system which regulated it defended
only Christianity and visibly the Anglican branch of it. The second
half of this accusation is more easily dealt with. The attacks
made upon religious sensibilities made by Gott were considered
beyond most measure of the proprieties of debate making the case
against him clear cut. The fact that such cases were now considered
primarily on the manner of the statement involved further served
to distance consideration of the precise doctrine or religious
text attacked. When we also consider the more ecumenical attitude
that began to prevail within, for example, the English Catholic
hierarchy from the turn of the century onwards a tacitly agreed
version of Christian fundamentals served to iron out the doctrinal
inconsistencies that had served defendants so well in the years
before the Coleridge dictum. At this period this blending of sacred
doctrines into a language and rhetoric of religious feelings was,
on the face of it, an advance in religious tolerance. As we shall
see however this was to have a significant and unforeseen impact
at the end of the 20th century. However, the accusation that the
regulation of opinion had not kept pace with the increasing plurality
of society was rather more difficult to refute. Public opinion
and the opinion of local officials was mobilised solely in the
defence of the Christian religion. Although the Indian Code solution
was frequently mentioned, and this clamour heightened from the
Edwardian period onwards, enthusiasm for its adoption in administrative
circles was minimal.
CONCLUSIONS
24. The Indian Criminal Code does not solve
any of the inherent problems associated with defining religion.
It only appears to do so because it was constructed by a ruling
power over a religious landscape it considered with a degree of
condescension. Moreover, such a solution was to all intents and
purposes imposed and was not required to pass the sanction of
consultation. The definition of religion was "forced"
upon the ethnic and religious groups of India as the law saw them
in 1860. That the Code has survived owes more to the forbearance
of such groups than to the utility of the law.
25. It is not even as if the difficulties
over the precise role of "intention" (and Mens Rea)
is solved by recourse to this solution. In the complex situations
in which such a law would be likely to be applied, establishing
a "deliberate intention to wound" would be very onerous
indeed. Even with the most honourable intentions, it would be
very difficult for an individual speaking or writing to gauge
in advance the effect of his (her) utterance or text. A speech
may be commenced with the worthiest of motives only to receive
an entirely unexpected "wounded" response, yet the perception
of being wounded might be palpably unreasonable. The wounded response
might perhaps have resulted from the attention of a wholly unexpected
audience (and these individuals may even attend with the expectation
of being wounded), or that some of the audience were intoxicated.
While the objective of legislation in this area will be defending
religious minorities confronted by hate crime, the law must take
care not to obstruct temperate criticism of religious practices,
texts, evangelising or recruitment policies. Each of these could
arguably fall into the remit of this law.
26. Such a formulation assumed that the
ability to wound religious feelings is an objective constant that
an external authority can regulate upon and to which it can provide
definitive answers. The context of the introduction of the law
is, in our opinion relevant. It was introduced by a governing
power overseeing a colony. We consider that it is doubtful that
such an overbearing regulating power would command popular support
in the UKa modern Western plural society, but most importantly,
one that is continually diversifying.
27. The alternative is to require counsel
for the "victim" to demonstrate how far such ideas "wound".
Were this route to be taken it would in our opinion lead to the
litigious bringing large numbers of cases to the courts inviting
the formulation of unsavoury ideas into religious idioms. The
cases would also be time-consuming and, as has happened in India,
the judiciary would be under intense pressure not to acquit, as
doing so may offend a vociferous minority. We are also very worried
indeed that, once passed, such legislation would in practical
political terms, be capable of being repealed, however overbearing
it turned out to be in practice.
28. There is also a note of extreme caution
to be sounded around the Indian Code's two clauses which both
use the words "religious feelings". In the context of
the Code's construction these words carry a note of condescension.
Whilst Christianity was considered a religious "belief"
the gap between this and more obviously indigenous religions was
emphasised through the use of the word "feelings". Whilst
this might appear to be of merely historical interest the continuation
of the words "religious feelings" into any construction
of a modern offence would have extremely serious implications.
Religious "feelings" are not the same as religious "beliefs".
Religious "beliefs" can be demonstrated, subjected to
measures of quantity, quality, orthodoxy and apostasy. Indeed
the English legal system used to do this regularly. The Test Acts
(which prescribed that undergraduates at Oxford and Cambridge
universities were required to be communicants of the Church of
England is one example as is the requirement of subscription to
the 39 Articles in other, related, contexts. Laws existed against
Anti-Trinitarian views until the early years of the 19th century
and disabilities existed against Catholics until 1829, some indeed
persisted beyond this date. Similarly, parliamentary and courtroom
oaths were governed by a religious requirement until these were
both altered through the machinations of Charles Bradlaugh in
the second half of the 19th century.
29. A major stumbling block of adopting
in the UK some variation of the Indian code is that we cannot
see how hurt to religious feelings can be satisfactorily measured
in an objective way by the courts. Given that religion itself
is so difficult to define, then defining hurt to religious feelings
is still more demanding. It would of course be dangerous were
the definition to be so loose as to encompass "anything individuals
feel deeply enough about", or "anything individuals
feel to be greater than themselves" or other amorphous "feelings"
about anything from soap opera to football. It is not as irrelevant
as it may as first appear to refer at this point to the individual
who appeared on a jury in the United States wearing a uniform
from the science fiction television programme Star Trek. When
questioned, the individual concerned outlined that the programme
embodied his own morality and outlook on life and that he was
proud to display this allegiance publicly. In a wider context,
we should also remember that the work of a number of sociologists
and (particularly post-modern) theologians, is redefining the
nature of the sacred with an intention of sweeping more into this
definition. Such changes are not confined to the margins; well-known
Anglican Don Cuppitt and the Sea of Faith have been moving in
this direction for decades.
30. Lastly, it should be noted that the
wording of the two clauses of the Indian Criminal Code do not
necessarily rule out proceedings for blasphemy and could arguably
be seen as a positive extension of such laws. This is particularly
worrying if the "intention to wound" formulation is
the basis of this law and its use. Whilst the same issues around
intention and Mens Rea apply, the issue of "wounded
feelings" put the issue firmly in the hands of the offended
individual and the interpretation of such a law would presumably
turn on demonstrating the capacity of texts and utterances to
wound. Such proceedings could be profoundly damaging for belief
systemsboth those proceeding in this way and those proceeded
against. Moreover as with so many other aspects of this potential
legislation the loopholes available for the dangerous and unscrupulous
are numerous.
16 October 2002
APPENDIX 2
STATEMENT BY BABU GOGINENI (AN INDIAN HIMSELF)
MY BACKGROUND
I am an Indian involved in Human Rights and
Humanist activism. Before I became Executive Director of the (London-based)
International Humanist and Ethical Union a number of years ago,
I was founder secretary general of South Asian Humanist Network
and Rationalist Association of India; Trustee of the Indian Renaissance
Institute, and Joint-Secretary of the Indian Radical Humanist
Association.
I am appalled that legislators in the UK may
be seeking inspiration from Indian legislation as regards the
issues of blasphemy and religious hatred.
Provisions of Section 295 of the Indian Penal
Code are obviously far less virulent than those of Section 295
of the Pakistan Penal Code (and 295 of Bangladesh Criminal Code),
but all relate to issues of blasphemy and or religious hatred,
and equally open to misuse. It is true that in some aspects Indian
legislation is far more advanced than the UK's: for example, in
India all citizens are treated equally before law; whereas in
Pakistan and in the UK the state religions have various protections
and privileges which are in fact an affront to the concepts of
equal protection and treatment of all citizens under law. Religious
discrimination is not illegal in the UK. In this respect it is
right to seek inspiration from Indian legislation that is more
in tune with the universal standards of human rights relating
to religious privilege.
(India has an exemplary legislation preventing
the use and appeal to religious sentiment during electoral campaigning
(how it is implemented is a matter of political will in India's
context!), but that may not be relevant here).
But as the material I previously forwarded to
you will showthe case of d'Avoigne, the persecution of
painter MF Hussain, the harassment of the editor of Vijaya Viharam,
the threats being received by Mr Srini Pattathanam from Home Ministry
officials in Kerala as a result of his exposure of the sordid
doings of a God woman Amruthanandamayee, the serious problems
faced by the Rationalists as they try to expose Satya Sai Baba
(for info on Sai Baba, see my article Sex Lies and Video tapeRetelling
the Satya Sai Story hosted on many Websites)Section 295
is the culprit whose dangerous provisions are open to clear abuse.
The whole world is seized of the sordid affair of the death penalty
awarded to Dr Shaikh in Pakistan; Taslima Nasrin (the well known
author) was hounded out of Bangladesh after section 25 was invoked
in Bangladesh*. In India, the presence of 295 and 298 on the Statute
Book has unquestionably resulted in infringements of the rights
of citizens as regards the free exercise of their freedom of expressionmany
books have been banned under this or related provisions; playwrights
harassed and films censored. Some of the people who have been
victims of this law are respected academics.
I am at a loss to understand why would the UK
seek to emulate India's backward laws rather than look to the
provisions of Article 18 of the UDHR and the UN Declaration on
Freedom of Religion etc of 1981.
Babu Gogineni
Executive Director
IHEU
10 October 2002
*Taslima Nasreen has been the subject of further
litigation in her home state according to the BBC. She has been
sentenced to one year in jail in Bangla Desh in absentia for criticising
Islam (James Palmer 14 October 2002)
http://news.independent.co.uk/world/asiachina/story.jsp?story=342458
I append an article relating to blasphemy law
in the sub-continent.
Blasphemy in Pakistan
By Babu Gogineni, Executive Director, IHEU
The Blasphemy law in Pakistan is a shameful
relic of the British Raj's 1860 Criminal Law. It was modified
in 1926 before Pakistan was born, and again as recently as in
1986 and in 1991 when criminal law was Islamicised by the then
dictatorship. How, under the regime of Islamic punishments, the
evidence required is "at least two Muslim adult male witnesses
who are supposed to be truthful persons who abstain from major
sins". It is required at the trial that the Presiding officer
must be a Muslim. Islamic law of evidence declares that the evidence
recorded by minorities and women has a status inferior to that
of Muslim men.
In the case of Blasphemy, very often the accused
is murdered either in police custody or even in the court room
itself by blood thirsty zealots. So few cases are even brought
to fruition. General Pervez Musharraf's recent attempts to improve
the law has been met with vehement opposition from the clerics,
and he immediately climbed down, in deference to the Islamic fundamentalists.
The law remains as barbaric as it was. And so is the mob. Pakistan's
minorities, 3% of Pakistan's 140 million citizens, are non-Muslims;
and there are at least 20 million Shiites, a minority Islamic
sect in Pakistan. The situation for these minorities is desperate.
The main victims of Pakistan's discriminatory and repressive legislation
so far has been the Ahmadias, the Christians and the Hindusand
the most victimized are the Christians and Ahmadias. Their evidence
is not accepted, their rights to freedom of religion or belief
not protected, they are not allowed high-positions in the Army
or in the bureaucracy, and they are forced to vote under the separate
electorate system, where non-Muslims vote for non-Muslims.
But the main concern of Pakistan's Human Rights
activists are the Blasphemy laws. Blasphemy of Islam is punished
differently and much more severely than Blasphemy of other religions.
There is no Freedom of Religion or Belief in Pakistan. Bishop
John Joseph, Roman Catholic Bishop of Faizalabad even killed himself
in protest in front of the sessions court of Sahiwal, on 5 May,
1998. But even this ultimate sacrifice did not move the administration
or the legislature.
Pressure must mount from all quarters to enable
the law to change, and to protect the victims. Pakistan's theocracy
is depriving many honest citizens of their liberty and their life.
22 (1996) 24 EHRR1. Back
23
(1994) 19 EHRR 34. Back
24
Cantwell v Connecticut 310 US 296 (1940). Back
25
D Feldman, Civil liberties and Human Rights in England and
Wales, 2nd ed. (Oxford: OUP, 2002), 913. Back
26
(1840) St Tr (NS) 563 at 590. Back
27
(1979) AC 617 HL. Back
28
(1996) 24 EHRR1. Back
29
See G Robertson, Freedom, the Individual and the Law 7th
ed. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993) 254. Back
30
See n.2 above, paras 47-48. Back
31
Feldman, at p 917-18 Back
32
(2000) ILRM 426. Back
33
Radzinowicz, L (1957). Sir James Fitzjames Stephen 1829-94. Back
34
But See Colaiaco, J (1983). James Fitzjames Stephen and the Crisis
of Victorian Thought which suggests that Stephen was also capable
of thought which would today be described as "orientalist". Back
35
Stephen, J F (1882). Offences against Religion. The History of
Criminal Law; Stephen J F (1884). The Law on Blasphemy and Blasphemous
Libel. Fortnightly Review. 35: 289-318. Back
36
HO 45 24619 217459. Notes prepared for Home Secretary as briefing
for above meeting document date 6 November 1929 words underlined
in original. Back
37
Hansard 24 January 1930. Back
38
HO 45 24619 217459/33, Hansard 24 January 1930. Back
39
HO 45 24619 217459/34 Memo from A L 11 February 1930. Back
40
The Good Rule and Government Byelaws were a means of supplementing
the provisions of the Town Police Clauses Act of 1848 and represented
local regulatory power in such matters. Back
41
Ibid. Letter from CR to Home Office 11 February 1930. Back
42
HO 45 24619 217459/42 Memo from DPP to USS Home Office. Back
43
HO 45 24619 217459/42 Letter 13 February 1930 J A Stainton to
Sir John Anderson GCB Home Office. Back
44
Ibid. Back
45
Ibid. Report on Committee Stage of the Bill to Amend the Blasphemy
Laws 1930. Back
46
Ibid. Notes on the Blasphemy Law Amendment Bill. Back
|