Examination of Witnesses (Questions 1
- 19)
THURSDAY 9 SEPTEMBER 2004
PROFESSOR JOHN
HARRIS, PROFESSOR
SHEILA MCLEAN,
DR EVAN
HARRIS MP, MISS
DEBORAH ANNETTS
and MR TL BARCLAY
Q1 Chairman: Thank you all for coming.
This is a public session of the Select Committee on the Assisted
Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill. It is our purpose to hear the
oral representations from the Voluntary Euthanasia Society. I
would like the Chief Executive Officer of the Voluntary Euthanasia
Society to introduce herself, and then the individual members
of the team to introduce themselves. Then it is over to you as
to exactly how you wish to conduct the proceedings: you may either
make a single opening statement, or you may decide to have opening
statements from each witness. The point obviously is that the
more time that is taken up by that, the less time there is for
questioning; and it is for your judgment as to which bit of the
proceedings is more important from your point of view. The evidence
is recorded, and therefore it is clear that it would be a great
help if you can be so kind as to articulate as carefully and clearly
as you can, without of course unduly delaying the time of the
presentation that you want to make. The evidence will be submitted
in draft to the witnesses with an opportunity to point out any
corrections that are required to be made on the transcript. With
that introduction, Miss Annetts, would you like to proceed?
Miss Annetts: We welcome the decision of the
House of Lords to give time to this very important issue, and
I would also like to thank the Committee for asking the Voluntary
Euthanasia Society to give evidence in connection with Lord Joffe's
bill. I would like to introduce you to the witnesses who are here
today. We have asked them to attend because of their expertise
in their individual fields. They are not representatives of VES;
they are here because of their particular levels of experience.
I would now like to hand you over to Sheila, who will briefly
introduce herself and outline her background.
Professor McLean: Chairman, my name is Sheila
McLean. I am Professor of Law and Ethics in Medicine at the University
of Glasgow and, as Deborah said, not associated with the Voluntary
Euthanasia Society.
Professor Harris: I am John Harris, bio-ethicist
and philosopher at the University of Manchester, and I am also
not a member of the Voluntary Euthanasia Society nor otherwise
associated with it.
Mr Barclay: My name is Tom Barclay, and I am
here because the Voluntary Euthanasia Society asked me to come
in view of the fact that I have an incurable complaint.
Dr Harris: My name is Evan Harris. I am a Liberal
Democrat MP for Oxford West and Abingdon, and formerly a doctor,
and a member, like Sheila and John, of the British Medical Association
Medical Ethics Committee, though we do not speak for either the
BMA or indeed the Medical Ethics Committee. We are here in a personal
capacity. I was involved in a successful attempt to steerthrough
open debatea policy around doctor-assisted dying through
my own party conference just last spring.
Miss Annetts: There have been a number of very
significant changes over the last 10 years, which we have set
out in the VES submission. I would like to highlight four of the
most significant changes. There has been much speculation as to
what would happen if medically-assisted dying were permitted.
We no longer need to speculate. Medically-assisted dying is now
permitted under the law in Oregon. The Netherlands and Belgium.
Decriminalisation has made it possible for independent researchers
to examine all aspects of medically-assisted dying, particularly
in Oregon, where many academics, in conjunction with the Oregon
Hospice Association, have undertaken comprehensive research. The
second important point is that since 1996 there have been repeated
opinion polls, not least the British Social Attitudes Survey from
1996, which have found that 82 per cent of the public support
medically-assisted dying. Many UK doctors and nurses also support
a change in the law. We concur with the GMC and the BMA, which
have said that this is a matter for society. There is a clear
consensus amongst the majority of the public, who want to see
the law changed; and Lord Joffe's bill meets these wishes with
great clarity. The third point I wish to address is palliative
care. VES supports palliative care, and we would like to see increased
provision to meet the needs of patients who want it; and we welcome
the growing political commitment to realise this aim. However,
many have argued, including the BMA and Macmillan Cancer Relief,
that palliative care cannot meet the needs of all dying patients,
and this has been reinforced by research carried out over the
last 10 years. Lastly, we now have clear evidence that, irrespective
of what the law may say, doctors, nurses and relatives are being
asked by terminally ill people for help to die. We also have evidence
that doctors and relatives are breaking the law and giving this
help. Indeed, a recent UK survey found that 47 per cent of people
would be prepared to break the law to help a terminally ill loved
one to die. The law is clearly not working. It is not humane or
effective. Indeed, the Law Commission has found that the current
legal position is a blight on our law. Evidence from around the
world has shown that it is far better to regulate medical help
to die than to allow it to go unchecked and unregulated as an
underground medical practice. Many safeguards have been built
in to Lord Joffe's bill to protect the vulnerable, something that
the current law simply does not do, whilst at the same time providing
choice to dying patients and giving clear guidance to the medical
profession when faced with a request from a dying patient for
that help. I would now like to ask Mr Barclay to say a few words.
Mr Barclay: Thank you for allowing me the opportunity
to address you. I have been asked to tell you about my personal
circumstances. I was a consultant plastic surgeon for 30 years,
before retiring in 1989, and have been responsible for the treatment
of many patients with big head and neck malignancies, both the
resection and the reconstruction; and I am very familiar with
the situation in which I have to tell a patient that there is
nothing that I can do for them. I have been a member of the Voluntary
Euthanasia Society for 17 years. Two years ago, I developed fasciculation
of the muscles to my legs and arms, which are characteristic of
Motor Neurone Disease, which is bad news, invariably fatal, and
there is no cureand I well knew that. In January of this
year, because of wasting of my hand muscles, I consulted my neurological
colleague, and he confirmed the diagnosis with EMG tests. Since
then, my muscular wasting has steadily progressed, giving me some
degree of disability. This process will continue. The next thing
that will happen to me is that I shall get a dropped foot and
have to use a wheelchair. After that, I shall become too weak
in my arms to move the wheelchair, and I shall have to be carried
about. The end stage of Motor Neurone Disease is called bulbar
palsy, in which I shall be unable to swallow, and my speech will
become unintelligible. Finally, after several years, I shall die
of pneumonia caused by inhalation of saliva. This is all going
to happen. If, in the end stage of my illness, I wish to commit
suicide, I shall be physically unable to do so. I shall not be
able to hang or drown myself and I will not be able to swallow
the necessary pills if they are available. We all have to die.
I have been very fortunate in having had a worthwhile career,
good health, and a marvellous wife. I am not complaining about
anything except that anyone who assists me in my project, as the
law now stands, will be prosecuted. For the disease I have, no
palliation is possible. The sensory nerves are not involved; there
is no pain, only motor weakness. Nevertheless, I shall have what
my medical textbook calls "intolerable suffering for the
patient and his family caused by this terrible illness".
My life expectancy is still of several years' duration, of which
at least the last two are very likely to be end-stage helplessness,
dysphagia and anarthria. I do not believe that under all these
circumstances being medically helped to die at my instigation
and with my full understanding and approval would in any way undermine
the basis of modern caring medicine.
Professor Harris: I would like to make two points
in this very brief time that I have. The first concerns autonomy.
Respect for persons, something we all wish to show, requires us
to acknowledge the dignity and value of others and to treat them
as ends in themselves, not merely instrumentally. This means respecting
their autonomy. Autonomy is the ability to choose and the freedom
to choose between competing conceptions of how to live. It is
only by the exercise of autonomy that our lives become in any
real sense our own. The ending of our lives often determines life's
final shape and meaning, both for ourselves and in the eyes of
others. When we are denied control at the end of our lives, we
are denied autonomy. As Ronald Dworkin memorably put it, "making
someone die in a way others approve, but he believes a horrifying
contradiction of his life, is a devastating, odious form of tyranny".
Autonomy is the underlying rationale of laws that, I hope we all
accept, allow patients to refuse life-sustaining medication. To
permit this and to deny medically-assisted death is, I believe,
radically inconsistent. Next, I want to turn to vulnerability.
Many objectors to medically-assisted death emphasise their concern
to protect the vulnerable. There are two groups of vulnerable
people to whom we owe concern, respect and protection. One consists
of those who might be pressured into requesting death. The others
consist of those, like Dianne Pretty, who are cruelly denied the
death they seek. We are surely not entitled to abandon one group
of vulnerable people in favour of another group of vulnerable
people: we have somehow to protect both. Those seeking medically-assisted
death are the more vulnerable because it is they who are truly
coerced at the moment, absolutely prevented from obtaining the
remedy they seek. Those who might be encouraged to die are free
to refuse. They are not victims unless we permit them to be, or
unless they make themselves victims. Those who seek and are denied
death are the ones currently who are genuinely coerced, and who
are at the moment, I believe, victims of tyranny. Concern for
the vulnerable does not, as so many falsely believe, tell us that
we should forbid medically-assisted dying: on the contrary, it
tells us that we should permit it, with the safeguards such as
those in Lord Joffe's bill. In this way, we can protect both of
the groups of vulnerable people whom we owe our concern, our respect
and our protection. Thank you.
Professor McLean: If I may, I would like to
approach the question from a slightly different perspective, given
that my background is in law. It is not overstating things to
say that citizens can expect their laws to be cogent, clear and
consistent. I would suggest to you that for the moment the law
in respect of end-of-life decisions offers none of these characteristics.
I am happy to expand on this in questions if anyone would like
me to. I think, secondly, we should recognise that this is an
issue about human rights, not just those rights that are laid
down in the Convention of Human Rights or in the Human Rights
Act, but fundamental human rights. It is not a question of medical
practice pure and simple, as both the GMC and the BMA have recommended,
but our current legal regime relies on sophistry to allow assistance
in dying in a number of circumstances, but paradoxically precludes
this only where a competent individual contemporaneously requests
it, a situation which Lord Mustill in this House described as
the law being "intellectually misshapen" in the case
of Airedale NHS Trust v. Bland. I would also like to pick
up Professor Harris's point on the question of autonomy. There
are many principles that people use in the argument against legalising
assisted dying, the prime amongst which is the concept of the
sanctity of life. This is undoubtedly a principle to which we
would all subscribe, and one which clearly protects people who
wish to have their lives protected. However, in most of the cases
in respect of end-of-life decisions, the courts, up to the most
senior courts, have indicated that the principle of autonomy to
which Professor Harris referred, predominates over the principle
of the sanctity of life where an individual person is competent
in making a decision, as would be the case were Lord Joffe's bill
to become law. Finally, from a legal perspective, I am confident
that the protections that are placed in Lord Joffe's bill are
sufficient and appropriate to ensure both competence of decisions
that are made, the informed quality of decision-making, which
is so essential to the exercise of autonomy, including the need
for provision of information about alternatives to assisted dying.
In fact, it may be another paradox of the current legal situation
that Lord Joffe's bill would offer to those seeking assistance
in this way many more safeguards than are currently available
for those who at present can lawfully choose to die.
Dr Harris: It is my first time on this side
of the table, and I see a different perspective than usual, and
I rely on your Lordships' reputation of politeness to rescue me
from what I might have inflicted from that side! I have looked
at this from the public policy point of view in terms of seeking
to have this debate in public, and it seems to be from that, albeit
short, experience that the public requires that Parliament debates
this matter to a conclusion. In my short time in the elected house,
we have debated most ethical matters at the beginning of life
and around personal sexual morality, but this is one thing where
there has barely been any debate or consideration; and it is a
mystery to me why the political establishment, by which I mean
those in all parties who determine business in Parliament, particularly
in the House of Commons, should wish not to even debate this and
show no sign of being willing to. The parliamentarians should
not be let off the hook, and it is timely therefore that this
bill comes forward. Even if it were rejected, I think many people
would feel happy that at least Parliament had done its duty and
fully debated the matter, preferably in both Houses, obviously.
The letters I get, having clearly taken a relatively high-profile
role, come from both sides, but I do get more from older people
who are very worried that they will end up in the position of
Dianne Pretty, or indeed her husband. They are as moving letters
as one gets in other areas. I do not believe that in this sense
this matter is any different from some of the contentious issues,
like cloning and issues of sexual morality, that we have debated.
For a number of years now, since my medical student days, I have
been a participant and observer of the medical politics of this,
and it is true that the British Medical Association has failed
to support the change in the law at its annual representative
meeting and, most recently in 2000. I have asked myself the question:
"Why do doctors' leaders appear to be against this?"
I think that they find it politically one of the more difficult
issues, partly because they do not wish to be seen to be pressing
for this change; but in my view, having spoken to many who have
publicly stated that they do not wish to see a change, they would
not actually mind if society did decide, and they would certainly
go along with it unless they were conscientious objectors. Of
course, there is that provision within this bill. The doctor/patient
relationship has evolved, and often it has not been easy for doctorsmore
autonomy and choice for patients, and patients requiring and demanding
more openness on difficult subjects with doctors. This is one
of those areas that is the next to see an evolution in the doctor/patient
relationship. Even if doctors' leaders are not yet calling for
it, I believe that patients are, and those that represent patients
ought to be.
Chairman: That completes the presentations
and it is now my privilege to invite members of the Committee
to ask questions to any or all of those who have spoken.
Q2 Lord Taverne: I should like to
ask two questions, the first of Deborah Annetts. There is a lot
of evidence, you say, now from Oregon and The Netherlands. What
does this show in relation to the argument deployed against the
change, namely that there is a danger of the slippery slope? The
second question is one I should like to put to Professor Harris.
One of the most fundamental moral dilemmas involved in this seems
to me to be illustrated by the so-called policeman's dilemma,
which you refer to in your written evidence. Would you expand
on that particular aspect?
Miss Annetts: Thank you for asking that question.
It is a very important question because it has been raisedconcerns
about the slippery slope. We now have very clear data from Oregon
and from The Netherlands that this simply is not happening. If
anything, commentators have said that perhaps regulation is the
best way to stop a decline into the slippery slope[1].
That is an important point. The research from The Netherlands
has been led by Professor van der Wal, a very key researcher in
The Netherlands, and he has conclusively found no slippery slope
in terms of either an increase of people wanting to have assisted
dying or people from perhaps vulnerable groups making access of
these particular provisions under the law in The Netherlands.
Exactly the same has been found in work carried out by Linda Ganzini
in Oregon: there is no evidence whatsoever of the slippery slope.
Professor Harris: I will be as brief as I can,
but I think I should state what the so-called policeman's dilemma
is. This was a case first brought into the literature by Herbert
Hart, Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford, supposedly a real
case in America in which there was a motor accidenta lorry
driver was trapped in the cab of his burning lorry. The policeman
was on the scene and it was quite clear that the lorry driver
would be burnt alive before he could be extracted from the vehicle,
and he pleaded with the policeman, who, as American policeman
are, was armed, to shoot him in the head rather than allow him
to be burnt alive. Everybody would agree that the policeman did
the morally correct thing in shooting him in the head. This case
shows that there is no principled objection to euthanasia; the
rest is an argument about safeguards. I have not met a single
person who could look me in the eye and say that that policeman
did a wicked thing and did something that he should not have done.
If we concede this case, then we concede the principle of assisting
death in cases of extreme distress where the condition, as the
lorry driver's was, is clearly a terminal onethe very conditions
envisaged in Lord Joffe's bill.
Q3 Lord Patel: We have seen, in paragraph
2.8 on Page 4, evidence that doctors are already assisting their
patients to die. We have one of the authors here, Lord Chairman,
and I would like further expansion of that.
Professor McLean: The evidence to which you
refer was the result of a survey conducted as part of a study
into voluntary euthanasia and assisted suicide in 1996. We distributed
some 2,000 questionnaires to doctors and also to some pharmacistsgiven
that, where assisted death had been regulated by way of physician-assisted
suicide, then they clearly would be implicated in the final decision.
We had a 50 per cent response rate, so we had about 1,000 responses
to our questionnaire. Fifty-four per cent of the respondents indicated
that they would welcome a change in the law to permit assistance
in dying. At the same time, I coerced BBC Scotland into conducting
an opinion poll of the Scottish public, and they surveyed some
1,000 people of whom 72 per cent agreed that there should be a
change in the law to permit assistance in dying. Of the professionals
who responded to us, something like 4 per cent said they had helped
a patient to die, which is, interestingly, significantly lower
than similar work done in the United States, but 11 per cent knew
a man who had, so it was obviously not entirely lacking in being
fairly widespread. Is that the evidence you were referring to?
Lord Patel: Yes.
Q4 Earl of Arran: If palliative care
were available for all the terminally ill, do you still see a
need for this Bill?
Miss Annetts: A lot of professional organisations,
like the BMA and Macmillan Cancer Relief, have said that palliative
care cannot meet the needs of all patients, and I think that is
backed up by the evidence from Oregon, which has shown that 93
per cent of people are in receipt of palliative care who actually
ask for and receive help to die. They are actually in a hospice
when they are making the request, and then have that request accepted
by their attending physician in Oregon. That clearly demonstrates
that palliative care, for those particular people, has not met
all of their needs. Palliative care is obviously something that
is central to the dying process, and we absolutely endorse that
view. That is why we are very pleased that Lord Joffe has included
in Section 3 of his bill something called the "palliative
care filter"; that, if somebody asks for medical help to
die, then a palliative care specialist is required to attend that
patient to explore whether palliative care can meet their needs
better. We are absolutely behind that particular provision.
Professor McLean: One other piece of research
that might be of interest is that there is a certain amount of
evidence now, certainly from the United States, that patients
who are receiving good palliative care are more rather than less
likely to ask for control at the end of their life; the very fact
that they are adequately informed about the alternatives, and
that they are palliated to the stage at which they are competent
to ask these questions, they are more likely than less to ask
for control at the end of their lives.
Q5 Baroness Finlay of Llandaff: Can
I thank you, Mr Barclay particularly, for having come to speak
to us and explaining what is clearly a very difficult situation
to be in. I am not certain from the evidence that you have submitted
why you feel that it must be doctors that do this, given that
we have had evidence from doctors who have said that they would
not want to be involved in any way in a process of ending patients'
lives"killing patients" is the phrase they useand
why you have not proposed some kind of scientology service that
would be separate and outside, in terms of bringing about the
same end for the patient but without impinging on the conscientious
ability of a doctor to take a decision because in the bill
there is also provision that, whilst someone may object, they
have a duty to refer, and therefore they have to be part of the
process however deep their personal objections may be.
Miss Annetts: Lord Joffe has noted concerns
around Section 7 and may well be putting in an amendment to Section
7 in relation to the obligation to refer on to another medical
practitioner. However, if you look at the evidence from Oregon
and from the general public in the UK, they see the medical practitioners
as the person they want to help them at this critical time, and
that marries up with the evidence from Timothy Quill, who is a
palliative care consultant in the States. He said it is very important
for the medical profession, for the doctor, not to abandon the
patient at the end of life. There is a concern that, if the doctor
almost sub-contracts this role, and if that were the provision
in the bill, then the patient might feel a sense of real abandonment.
Notwithstanding that, of course, the conscientious objection clause
is absolutely vital.
Dr Harris: To add to that, the problem you cite
is not a new dilemma for doctorsfor example, the abortion
procedures they are faced with, having to refer to someone else
if they have a conscientious objection. There will always be areas
of practice where doctors need to refer because they are opposed
to participating in the process. If the process is lawful, then
I think we have a right to expect doctors to make the onward referral,
even if, as this bill does, it provides a conscientious objection,
which is well recognised as something that is reasonable to do.
My understanding is that this has not been a major problem in
other jurisdictions where this has been made possible. The other
point I would make is that it is always useful to make the comparison
with the more passive situation where a patient refuses treatment
that is life-saving, and they do not need even to be suffering
from unbearable suffering, however that is defined, or even have
a terminal illness, because if they have the capacity they are
entitled to make that decision. Some doctors, I am sure, would
find that even more distressing because they know there is a life-saving
or ameliorating treatment that a patient, for whatever reason,
is rejecting. Again, that is not a new dilemma, and I suspect,
based on my own career, that all doctors have seen situations
that they are not entirely happy with but they recognise that,
when it is a question of patient autonomy, that has to override
their unwillingness and unhappiness about referring this case,
or participating if they are not a conscientious objector.
Mr Barclay: Speaking personally, if my request
for suicide help were medically approved by people whom I knew,
that would satisfy me perfectly well. I would not want my own
practitioner necessarily to do the final injection.
Q6 Chairman: Mr Barclay, it is rather
a delicate question, but have you any idea from the point of view
of your own condition how much time of life would be stopped if
you were able to ask for medical help to have suicide in your
situation?
Mr Barclay: According to my reading and the
people I have asked, the process can last a very long time or
not a very long time. My medical textbook, on which I rely, suggests
that a terminal period of two to four years in a helpless state
is to be expected, but it may be less. It is very unlikely to
be more. That is what one would have to anticipate when one were
making the request. I believe that, when I get to the stage when
I cannot swallow, I shall ask for it then.
Q7 Baroness Hayman: I wonder if I
could explore with our witnesses the issue about the evidence
of who it is who most supports or asks for assisted dying in the
experience that we have from abroad. You mentioned that it was
those who had perhaps best experience of palliative care who still
wished to be in control, and I read in the evidence from Oregon
that there seemed to be a bias in terms of educational standards
and perhaps social class of those who asked for assisted dying.
Do you have any comment on that phenomenon, and how do you explain
it? Do you have any thoughts or concerns about that? Would that
be an issue for you were it to be replicated, in the terms that
we address other issues of equality of access? Is that something
that your organisation would consider was a concern; or would
you simply say it was reflective of?
Miss Annetts: Again, on the Oregon statement,
the Department of Human Services and Linda Ganzini have been researching
into the types of people who access this particular provision.
They have found that people who pursue the request through and
have help to die are people who have a particular need for control
and autonomy but who also may be suffering from quite a high level
of existential sufferingloss of dignity, loss of bodily
functions, et cetera. There is a combination here of what
their suffering is, and what their suffering means to them personally.
Interestingly, a much higher percentage of people actually request
a prescription but do not use it, and we think that is because
they are using it like an insurance policy "if it
gets too bad, I have control, but I will not use it until I get
to that point". In the words of some of the Motor Neurone
Disease sufferers from Oregon, they have said, "this has
enabled me to live a better life because I do not have to worry
about the future". There seem to be two different things
going on there, one the insurance policy aspect and the other
the illness combined with the personality type. In terms of accessand
I can only express a personal viewit comes back to personal
autonomy and who this person is. It is clear from Oregon that
people from a higher socio-economic group seem to be using this
particular provision, although interestingly people who make the
request may come from a lower socio-economic group; so there may
be a whole variety of things going on there. I am not sure we
would want to start advocating on the basis of access actually.
I think it is very much a personal thing; it is how you want your
death to be at the end of your life, and I do not think VES should
be involved in that.
Q8 Baroness Jay of Paddington: I
would like to follow up more specifically one of the general points
that Lord Taverne asked about in relation to the argument of the
slippery slope. One of the issues that is often raisedand
it has come up in some of the responses made to questions that
have already been posedis that there is a particular difficulty
for the medical profession in terms of the potential loss of trust.
We are all familiar in this country where that has been a specific
problem. Have you done any work on that, or has anybody for example
in The Netherlands and OregonI saw it referred to briefly
in your written evidence, but is there something you can expand
there on the potential loss of trust?
Miss Annetts: Again, we have to go to Oregon
and The Netherlands to see what the evidence is there. There have
been a number of pieces of research done which are either on the
point or adjacent to it. Firstly, there is a piece of research
by Graber in the States who looked at this issue and found that
there had been no reduction in trust whatsoever. Secondly, there
was a piece of research conducted in 2002 which found that the
Dutch trusted their doctors more than any other nation, including
doctors in the UK, which is a very interesting finding. That may
relate to the fact that, again, the six-country European study
from 2003 found that there was the highest level of discussion
between doctor and patient in The Netherlands around end-of-life
decisions, so trust seems to have something to do with that whole
discussion process between doctor and patient, which is very important.
Professor Harris: I have no empirical evidence,
but intuitively it would seem to me that this would be a trust-promoting
measure. The patients will know that they can trust doctors to
do precisely what the patient believes is in their best interests,
and is necessary to protect them. Knowing that the doctors are
able and willing to do that would promote trust rather than reduce
it.
Q9 Baroness Jay of Paddington: Do
I understand that the VES position is not that there is what one
might jargonistically call competition with palliative care in
this whole areabecause sometimes the argument is expressed
that it is palliative care versus assisted dying? That is not
your position?
Miss Annetts: Absolutely not, no. The two work
hand-in-hand. Indeed, the Oregon Hospice Association has come
up with a very useful leaflet, which it delivers to everybody
who has been diagnosed with a terminal illness, which goes through
all the different options: refusal of treatment, withdrawal of
treatment, palliative care, pain relief, also medical assistance
to die. The whole thing is a package from which the patient can
take what they want.
Dr Harris: Baroness Jay, I happen to agree with
Professor Harris that it would be a healthier and more trusting
relationship if the patients were aware that their autonomy would
be respected and be paramount. But even if you do not accept that
argumentand some people do notI would say that it
is not a particularly healthy relationship, and it is rather old-fashioned,
for patients to be in a position to say, "whatever you say,
doctor; I trust you explicitly; I do not even have to think about
this; I am going to go with whatever you say". I think the
relationship has evolved, and it is a good thing that it has become
more equal. It has a long way to go in my opinion. With respect
to the palliative care point, clearly at the end some people do
argue that, if everyone had the maximum amount of palliative care,
they would not want this assistance. However, we do know of cases;
there is no question that Dianne Pretty had access to palliative
care, and that many other people often will haveand I am
sure that Mr Barclay would have access to that; but I do not think
it is proper palliative care for people involved in palliative
care to say, "you are wrong about your wishes at the end
of life because here we are giving you palliative care; how dare
you then request help to die because of dignity and things that
are personal to you". Palliative care in some cases does
meet some people's every need but in some cases it clearly will
not, and it has to be a subjective matter.
Q10 Baroness Thomas of Walliswood:
Dr Evan Harris spoke of the benefit of discussing the subject
even if they are not successful or it still never comes to anything.
Like many people, I take the argument in favour of autonomy as
a very strong argument, but many of the people who have written
to us have associated this Bill and what they know of it with
a fear that they will be, to put it vulgarly, bumped off by somebody
else. They do not see the Bill, perhaps because they do not understand
it, as an effort to give autonomy, and they see it in quite the
reverse, as a threat to what could happen to disabled people or
people with mental difficulties and so on. I would like you to
comment on that and how that relates to what has been drawn to
my attentionthat "do not resuscitate" messages
can be put on a file without the patient being aware of it. That
might give people, as it were, reason to suppose that we are moving
towards a state, not of increasing autonomy, but decreasing autonomy?
Dr Harris: The "do not attempt resuscitation"
notice, as it should be properly known, is an example of what
the present poor practice is, where the matter has not been discussed.
Patients with capacity ought to have that discussed, and there
should be a duty on doctors to discuss that situation in appropriate
cases. One instinctively says that it is terrible to discuss that
sort of thing with patients as they enter hospital, but there
is a real risk that patients, many of whom do die in hospital,
run the risk of having resuscitation attempted inappropriately.
So the danger you cite, where people feel that they might be bumped
off, is something we must be vigilant around now, and in the future,
whatever the state of play of the law. I am certainly aware from
my own practice of patients who have had heavy strokes, for example,
being put on sedation, diamorphine pumps; and for no good reason,
because they had such a dense stroke that they were not in pain,
but it was just the way that their end of life was seen off. I
think that is inappropriate and in other jurisdictions this sort
of legislation has been brought in in a climate of regulation
in an attempt to tackle the abuses that are occurring in order
to reduce them. I have been able to persuade people who have contacted
me, maybe because I have taken a public position, that they will
be in an environment where there would be more safeguards against
non-voluntary acts if the law were changed.
Professor Harris: This is clearly a real issue,
but if the fear that people will be bumped off, as you put it,
is ill-founded and can be met with clear safeguards, then one
of the answers to this is education. But an important point is
that we, you, Parliament, we the society, should not condemn others
to a terrible death because of the ill-founded fears of another
group. All we have to do with those fears is show that they are
ill-founded and make sure that the safeguards are in place so
that people can clearly see that they are ill-founded; and I believe
that that is what Lord Joffe's bill does.
Professor McLean: A longer version of what I
am about to say here is in the written evidence that I submitted
to the Committee, but which you may not yet have seen. I support
what Dr Harris was saying. One of the difficulties in the current
legal regime is that there is scope for fear because people are
not actively engaged in the kinds of decisions that are being
taken about the end of their lives. One of the benefits of Lord
Joffe's bill is that it introduces safeguards for a person in
this situation that do not exist in any other areas. It is possible
for clinicians to make decisions on behalf of incompetent people
about the moment that their lives should be ended. To come back
to the earlier question about doctors not wanting to be involved
in this, I think it was a mistake to suggest that merely because
the doctor's involvement is characterised by withdrawing or withholding
treatment, for example from a patient in a permanent vegetative
state, it is a mistake to suggest that they are not involved in
the death of that particular patient. Clinicians already are involved.
One of the problems is that they tend to be involved in circumstances
where the individual concerned is not in a position to make a
request. What Lord Joffe is doing in a sense is putting people
who require active assistance on a par with those who have a treatment
that they could otherwise refuse. If I happen to have a condition
that has a life-saving treatment, I am legally entitled to refuse
that treatment, and my clinician cannot interfere. The only group
of people where that decision cannot be made are those who are
competently saying the same thing with the same intention, seeking
the same outcome, but who require active rather than passive assistance.
In my view, the distinction between acts and omissions, and active
and passive, certainly within the context of a doctor/patient
relationship, where there is a duty of care, is a distinction
without a difference.
Q11 Lord Taverne: Mr Chairman, can
I follow up the question of the fear of being "bumped off"?
It is sometimes said that people have a lot of fears that their
relatives will put a lot of pressure on them to give their consent
because it causes a lot of inconvenience to the relatives, and
they may be forced, as it were, by moral pressure, into giving
their consent, which otherwise they would not give. That is a
fairly widespread fear from the correspondence we have had. Can
you deal with that?
Miss Annetts: We have not seen any research
to that effect. We have undertaken a huge search of literature
in relation to all these issues which relate to end-of-life decision-making.
However, what we have found from Oregon is that there is some
research to the effect that sometimes a patient will hold off
going through the final act of having help to die for a few days
as a result of their relatives putting pressure on them not to
do so; so it is the other way round.
Professor Harris: To follow Sheila McLean's
point, as far as we know there is no evidence that people are
refusing treatment in droves because of the pressure put on them
by their relatives, but if that was a real fear you would expect
it to apply as much to refusals of treatment as it would to positive
assistance.
Q12 Earl of Arran: If, as would seem
to be the case at the moment, assisted-patient-dying is gaining
force or credibility, call it what you will, in western Europe,
are there signs in Oregon that the neighbouring states are beginning
to take some interest?
Miss Annetts: There has been some interest in
other states. What is interesting about Oregon is that the legislation
came into being as a result of a citizens' initiative, so it was
a push from society at a very grass roots level that brought about
the Oregon Death With Dignity Act. I cannot assist any more.
Q13 Baroness Finlay of Llandaff:
In relation to the boundaries that you have proposedand
you talk about the need for open discussion with patients about
what is happening, with which I completely concurthis debate
has been healthy for people who are ill in empowering them to
talk. However, the evidence that I see from Holland suggests that
approximately one in five patients' lives are being ended using
euthanasia, without their explicit consent, despite the law having
been changed there for some time. I wonder why you therefore feel
that the safeguards that you propose would be law, because 20
per cent without consent seems to be quite a high number.
Miss Annetts: The law came into being formally
in The Netherlands in 2002, so the statistics you are referring
to are pre the legislation coming into effect, and during that
time doctors were working on the basis of guidelines coming out
from the case law rather than actual statute. Having said that,
the research in other countries, Belgium and Australiaand
those are the only other two places where we have specific percentages
of assistance or of end of life decisions without the explicit
request of the patientshows much higher levels. In The
Netherlands it is 0.7 per cent, in Belgium it is 3.2 per cent
and in Australia it is 3.5 per cent. Going back to that 0.7 per
cent, yes, that is a concern and the Dutch absolutely recognise
it and they have been working very hard to try and put in better
provisionsif you like, better medical practiceshave
in order to deal with that issue. What is noticeable, though,
looking at the 900 deaths which occurred, without explicit request,
is that most of those patients will have made a request to the
doctor; they may not have gone through the formal process but
they will have gone through an informal discussion[2].
The latest figures from The Netherlands show that in virtually
all those cases there will have been a discussion, if not with
the patient themselves then with the relative or a colleague.
But, of course, in the UK we have no statistics whatsoever; we
do not know the extent to which this particular medical practice
goes on within our own hospitals.
Q14 Baroness Finlay of Llandaff:
I want to ask Professor McLean whether you have done any research,
looking at the case notes, where doctors had said that they had
done something to suddenly end a patient's life? Looking as to
whether it was that they had not understood the action of opiates
or whether this had been a cessation of futileif I can
use that word looselytreatment or whether in fact it had
been an administering of a lethal dose of something like barbiturates
and kurari, which is what we have been talking about?
Professor McLean: I do not, in fact, have that
information; I have not done research on that. But I can tell
you that, of the doctors who responded to my survey, the question
was quite specifically about active assistance on request from
patients, so it would be precisely the situation that you envisaged.
In that survey, as I say, it was only something like 4 per cent,
with another 11 or 12 per cent who were able to say that they
knew that this was happening with colleagues.
Miss Annetts: To go back on the Dutch experience,
I suspect that Professor Van der Wal, who has done most of the
research in this area and sponsored by the government, would be
able to assist the Committee much further in relation to looking
at those cases and the approach which the Dutch government would
take in relation to regulating end of life decision making, with
reference to those medical practices. There is also a piece which
appeared in The Lancet in 1993, which we could certainly
let you have, which goes into those deaths in more detail, and
perhaps can provide you with the information that you seek[3].
Q15 Lord McColl of Dulwich: You said
that Dutch doctors were more trusted than British. What is the
basis for that research? As somebody who works with Dutch doctors
and Dutch nurses, communication is sometimes a little difficult,
and I wondered how the comparison was made?
Miss Annetts: I suspect the best thing to do
is to let you have a copy of the entirety of that research; I
think it did cover most European countries[4].
Dr Harris: I do not know the specific research,
and some of these qualitative studies, I think we both recognise,
are limited. I think it is a point to make that there does not
appear to have been detected a problem, even despite the climate
and legislation in The Netherlands, of loss of trust. Indeed,
if anything, we should expect empirically, in my view, that doctors
who are prepared to overcome the British reticence to talk about
death, which pervades all parts of society, may well engender
more trust these days from their patients because they are putting
everything on the table. That is a personal and empirical view
but I have not seen any evidence against it.
Q16 Lord Turnberg: I have found your
presentations enormously helpful and valuable, and I am very grateful
to you for coming to talk to us. As you are probably aware, we
have been getting enormous amounts of letters and submissions,
not all of which say the same thing as you do. There are a number
of fears that come up, and we need your responses to them. One
relates to Professor McLean's comment regarding the relationship
between sanctity of life and autonomywhich has precedence,
which is secondary to which and whether they are of equal weight,
and so on. The other relates to John Harris's comments about,
once we have got through the ethical view, we are then into how
to determine the safeguards, and I think that is where most fears
have been coming throughto me at least. How do we ensure
that there are sufficient safeguards to satisfy us and the public
that dangers will not ensue? I think that is an extraordinarily
difficult area, and you may pass that over, but I wondered what
your comments were?
Professor Harris: Can I start with that last
point? As far as I know, in no realm of human life is it possible
to have absolute safety, an absolute guarantee that there will
be no errors or nothing will go wrong. But against the possibility
of a safeguard failure we have to set the fact that without assisted
dying many people are going to terrible deaths, which they need
not go to and from which assisted dying would save them. So we
are not entitled to expose that group to certain danger because
we can never be sure that there are absolutely foolproof safeguards
in any human endeavour. We have to take a balanced view, it seems
to me, but that balanced view should not be at the expense of
one group always in order to offer absolute protection to another
group.
Professor McLean: Can I add to that that? There
was an editorial in the New England Journal of Medicine
a number of years agoand it was in fact written by the
editor, I thinkin which it was noted that the fastest growing
group of suicides in the United States at that time were amongst
the elderly. The reason given for that was that they feared being
inappropriately kept alive in circumstances where they would have
preferred not to be. So there is another side to that particular
issue. On the question of the law's approach to autonomy and sanctity
of life, I think, from reading any of the judgments, perhaps in
the last 15 or 20 years, from the House of Lords down, that the
attitude of the courts has been to adopt a sanctity of life principle
which is, if I can describe it this way, a secular sanctity of
life principle; in other words, the presumption is that people's
lives must be safeguarded by the State. Indeed, as you know, there
are requirements under the Human Rights Act that that is done.
But the secular nature of it is that it is not taken to be an
obligation to live, which is entirely in line with removing the
prohibition or the criminality of suicide, for example. So what
the courts have said, very senior Judges have said, is that, when
there is a tension between the State's underpinning commitment
to preserving the sanctity of life and the autonomous decision
of a competent person that they no longer wish to have their life
protected by the State, the function of autonomy or the value
of autonomy is more significant than any adherence to sanctity
of life. That has been the judgment in any number of cases in
all sorts of different arenas, covering cases in which people
have actually had a diagnosed mental illness to pregnant women
making decisions about whether or not they should undergo Caesarean
sections to deliver a healthy foetus. So it is now very much ingrained
in the way in which the law approaches these issues.
Miss Annetts: May I come back on one final point
in relation to safeguards? There is plenty of evidence to show,
I think, both in the UK and overseas, that medical assistance
to die is happening; it is happening now, irrespective of what
the law may say, and it is happening without any safeguards, without
any stringent tests, without a waiting period, without checking
on the patient's competence, without an exploration of palliative
care. That is what is happening. There is an underground of medical
assistance to die, which has been documented, for example, in
the work of Professor Magnusson and Professor Emanuel. So it is
not a question of prohibition or not prohibition; it is a question
of coming up with the best regulation.
Dr Harris: On the question of sanctity of life,
may I say I feel very strongly that the comparison needs to be
made with decisions to refuse treatment. If sanctity of life as
a priority were any basis for regulation, then we would seek to
prevent competent patients from refusing life-saving medical treatment.
We do not. I do not even believe it is controversial that we allow
competent patients, even who are not suffering from a terminal
illness, even who are not suffering unbearably, both of which
are safeguards for the active case in Lord Joffe's Bill, from
refusing life-saving treatment, despite the view that the sanctity
of life is an issue. So for those patients who require help I
cannot see ethically, as John Harris has said, that there is any
difference, except in this Bill there are additional safeguards
requiring there to be a terminal illness and requiring there to
be unbearable suffering in the context of that. So it is an even
more rational decision, and the autonomy is in fact bounded by
those requirements.
Q17 Baroness Jay of Paddington: You
said at the beginning, Deborah Annetts, that you felt that things
had changed in the last decade, and obviously you have cited changes
in the law of the countries that we have talked about this afternoon,
and Professor McLean has just spoken about the change because
of the Human Rights Act and encapsulating in law matters like
autonomy and so on, which were not, at least in British law, extant
before that. We have also had in your written evidence the necessary
reference to the Law Commission's Report on the Homicide Act,
talking about the issues which have just been raised, about driving
this kind of procedure underground. Do you think that there has
been a cultural change in which all of these issues are embraced,
which makes you feel that there has been much greater openness,
perhaps much greater public support, as you have measured it,
for matters of this kind? What exactly is it, do you feel, that
is happening in our society which makes this something that is
more readily addressed? We have mentioned the factors of the law;
we have mentioned changing the legal framework from the statutory
point of view, and perhaps the more cultural one. Can you in any
sense draw these threads together? Or do you think that these
are things which have just happened, not necessarily in parallel
but just at the same time?
Miss Annetts: I think it is a very interesting
question to try to work out what is going on. I think they may
all be impacting on one another. I think there is something very
organic going on from the grass roots up, if you like; that most
people will have experienced personally a bad death in their family.
They know what the law is and they also know that they cannot
ask a doctor for help to die without getting the doctor into trouble.
So there are discussions amongst family members "What
do we do?" I think what the case of Dianne Pretty did was
to give people the opportunity to start to talk publicly and really
voice their concerns, and of course that is also underscored by
the rise in the principle of autonomy, which of course is a thread
going through the Human Rights legislation.
Professor McLean: I have only limited reasons
for saying this, but I have a large Masters programme in the University,
which is primarily addressed to doctors and other healthcare professionals,
and in the last 10 yearsperhaps fivesomething like
50 per cent to 60 per cent of those clinicians choose to write
their dissertation on end of life issues, and 99.8 per cent of
themthat is probably an accurate figureare now arguing
in favour of legalisation of assisted suicide or voluntary euthanasia.
The reason I mention this is that one of the other things that
has been happening is that people have become better educated
about the issues that surround it and a new generation in particular
of hospital doctors and other doctors and nurses are increasingly
seeing the relationship between healthcare providers and patients
as a more balanced relationship, which leads to more openness,
which allows people to learn more about the sensations that people
on both sides are feeling. Certainly my experience is that with
a certain amount of openness people's minds do change very easily,
and I think the new emphasis in medicineif I can call it
new, Lord McColl might disagree with meon sharing and what
Harvey Teff called a therapeutical alliance means that there is
also the incentive within that for people to respect other people's
views more.
Q18 Baroness Finlay of Llandaff:
Can I go for a moment to the research that has come out on the
reasons that people ask for death? Amongst those there is a fear
of the future being worse than it is today, and a fear of what
might happen. One of the reasons commonly cited is a fear of being
a burden. I wondered how you felt patients will respond in the
current climate where we now have less general practitioners available
out of hours, often no district nursing at night available at
home, and the family are increasingly having to pay for care and
to provide that care themselves. I wondered what you felt about
this increasing load that is being put on the individual and on
their family in terms of that background to the request that has
occurred, when people talk about their fears of the future?
Miss Annetts: Can I start by answering that
question with reference to the Oregon research, which comes out
year on year and, as you rightly point out, has been plotting
the reasons why people have been asking for help to die? As you
have explained, one of those reasons which has been coming up
is burden but, in fact, burden is quite a long way down the list
and comes after losing autonomy, being less able to engage in
activities making life enjoyable, loss of dignity and loss of
bodily functions. So it does come some way down the list. Secondly,
burden has been found to be quite complex and is often linked
to a sense of hopelessness or indeed a feeling of loss of autonomy.
So in Oregon "burden" is not burden to care givers.
It is not what this is about[5].
The research from The Netherlands shows that, if somebody has
made a request for that reason, being a burden to care givers,
it is most likely that that request will be turned down. So, again,
we have to unwrap what "burden" may mean and be quite
careful in looking at that. Obviously I take your point in relation
to burden and that is why Section 3 of the Bill is so important.
Dr Harris: I draw a comparison with the refusal
of treatment. If there is a problem with potential coercion, whether
it be active or just a feeling of burden, then that is likely
to apply in cases of refusal of treatment, which are common now
and lawful at present. The safeguards in this Bill, which require
effectively two doctors and a solicitor with a duty to explore
issues of whether those are feelings or whether there indeed has
been coercion, will, in my view, because of the way this Bill
has been constructed and the safeguards in it, act to deal with
that problem, if it is a problem, unlike those cases where it
is a question of refusal of treatment. And obviously people who
are terminally ill often go through phases where they require
treatment to stay alive during their terminal phasetreatment
of infection, for example. So if that is a concern, the safeguards
in this Bill provide additional safeguards compared to the refusal
of treatment situation.
Q19 Baroness Finlay of Llandaff:
I was not thinking about treatment so much as about social care
issues, which are a huge problem for people. As you know, with
people who have a disability and are at home, their physical care
can actually be extremely difficult for the family.
Dr Harris: I did understand the point you are
making. Let me try to explain what I meant, because I do not think
I made my position clear. Someone who has a terminal illness and
is cared for at home and the care is provided largely by the family,
as you said, they may get an infection and at the moment they
are perfectly entitled to reject treatment for that infection,
and it may well be, if your concerns are correct, that it may
be because they feel a burden. In contrast, the safeguards around
this Bill, for circumstances which may run simultaneously with
those episodes where they require life prolonging treatment, actually
enable those issues to be explored, with the consulting physician,
in the Bill and, of course, if it reaches that stage, with the
solicitor.
1 Note by witness: Lee, DE "Physician
Assisted Suicide": a conservative critique of intervention,
The Hastings Center Report 2003: 33 (1) : 17. Back
2
Note by witness: Van der Maas et al, 1991 (The
first Dutch Government report). Back
3
Note by witness: Pijnenberg, L; van der Maas, PJ; van
Delden, JJ; and Looman, CW. "Life termination acts without
explicit request of patient", Lancet 1993; 341: 1196-1199. Back
4
Note by witness: Graber, MA; Levy, BI; Weir, RF: Opplinger,
RA "Patients' views about physician participation in assisted
suicide and euthanasia", J Gen Int Med 1996; 11: 71-76, also
Kmietovicz, Z "R.E.S.P.E.C.T"-why doctors are still
getting enough of it", BMJ 2002; 324 (7328): 11-14. Back
5
Note by witness: Third Oregon Report by Department of
Human Services, February 2001. Back
|