Select Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 40 - 59)

TUESDAY 14 SEPTEMBER 2004

PROFESSOR JONATHAN GLOVER, PROFESSOR IRENE HIGGINSON and MS PENNEY LEWIS

  Q40  Lord Joffe: Even within a country there can be difference of views and different interpretations, would you agree?

  Professor Higginson: Yes.

  Q41  Baroness Finlay of Llandaff: My questions are really for Professor Glover, and possibly a bit for the other two presenters. When you were talking about autonomy and sanctity of life and respect for dignity, you spoke about the sanctity of life and fear of the physical. But you did not talk about issues around self-worth and your perceptions of self-worth and dignity coming from the way that you are behaved towards and treated, and I wonder if you had any comment on Kissane's work on demoralisation and demoralisation syndrome that occurs with people, depending on how they are treated by those who are providing care for them and around them?

  Professor Glover: I have not read that work, but I can well believe that how people think of themselves and value their lives is highly likely to be influenced by how they are treated, yes, I would accept that.

  Q42  Baroness Finlay of Llandaff: The other thing that came out in the paper you presented, and I think you alluded to, was this concept which—you did not use the term "double effect" but I think it has been termed "double effect"—about unforeseen consequences and the argument that there may not be a great difference. I just wanted to pursue that a little bit in terms of how often and how much evidence we have that that double effect, in the setting where somebody is dying of their disease, does actually occur, and whether that is different to the predictable but unwanted effects that you may see, for example, in someone with end-stage renal failure with an infection, where you will give them an antibiotic which is known to be toxic; you know that that is a risk, you hope that they will not go into end-stage renal failure because they have an infection, but some do and some will die. Do you feel philosophically and morally that there is a difference between that and the perceptions of using analgesics that you allude to in your presentation? Some might say that the misuse of analgesics is the thing that will result in life-shortening, but the evidence is that actually, when those drugs are used well, they may even be life-prolonging.

  Professor Glover: My comments were not really comments of fact about what the situation is or what the actual consequences of one medical policy or another are, because I am not an expert on that and I think you should ask Professor Higginson if that is what you want to know. My comments were really about whether the intent to reduce suffering, with the foreseen consequence that someone will die, is a principle that is morally acceptable, whereas it is not acceptable to intend to put someone out of suffering by means of death. I was really just reflecting the debate in ethics about this: some people think that that is a really important distinction, some people think it is not. I was really raising the question— is that really an important distinction, and if so why? I believe that part of the deep malaise of this debate is that people tend to divide into people who focus centrally on the consequences for the patient and say what really matters is— is the patient suffering? Is the patient alive or dead? people who might be called consequentialists; and the people on the other side, who say what really matters is what we do and what we intend to do, people who might be called deontologists. My belief is that one reason why these debates are so extraordinarily difficult, and perhaps one reason why they are often so passionate, is that actually most of us have some consequentialist inclinations and some deontological inclinations. Most of us both want best outcome for the patient and think that ought to be central, but also think it matters what sort of intentional actions we commit, and there is a tension between those two. I am sorry, I am not able to answer your factual questions about what actually happens; as I said, Professor Higginson is better qualified than I am.

  Q43  Baroness Finlay of Llandaff: Could I just pursue this a little further because you did not address issues of scope in terms of the effect of a decision on others, either on the rest of the family—particularly children in a family as relatives—or the impact of having what we might term an arbitrary barrier of an 18 year old, 18 years being the age limit as defined within the Bill, when we have got strong evidence coming from the medical literature that teenagers can actually be particularly difficult to achieve symptom control in, and that may be the physiology of the teenage changing state.

  Professor Glover: Yes. You raise two separate issues really. One is the effect of allowing or not allowing assisted dying on other members of the family, and again that is a factual question which feel I am the least qualified to answer. I assume that there are likely to be effects, either from having the knowledge that your parent, say, is slowly dying in agony and wishes that he or she was not, wishes to be dead and has that view overridden; or, alternatively, knowledge that someone has decided, in the family perhaps or the doctors, that it is acceptable to kill them. I can imagine either of those might have a traumatic effect on a child, for instance, but not being aware of the relevant psychological research I am not sure which of those is likely to be greater. The thing on the age thing—and I am very interested in what you say that there may be differences in control of symptoms, for instance, in teenagers—I would have thought that that is highly relevant. My own belief is that I am always slightly inclined to think that these lines that are drawn, say at 18 or wherever, seem to be a bit like the speed limit. There is no magic moment when you become an adult who is rationally competent to vote: we all know of some young teenagers who are much brighter at talking about politics than some people who are my contemporaries, and I am in my 60s. What we are trying to do is to ask, as it were, roughly where should the line be drawn, and for legal purposes it has to be sharp, so one takes an age limit. But I actually do agree that it may not always be exactly right in the individual case.

  Q44  Baroness Finlay of Llandaff: Might I ask Professor Higginson, do you know of any research that has been done into the effects on families?

  Professor Higginson: I am sorry, unfortunately I cannot think of anything at the moment, but there may be some I do not know.

  Q45  Lord McColl of Dulwich: Could I stay on the same theme about the question of relieving suffering by giving increasing doses of sedative? That was the situation in the old days, but it is not the situation now. So, when you talk about unintended but foreseen things going on, that was the situation 20, 30, 40 years ago, when in fact you only gave them morphine when they had the pain. There have been great advances in palliative care, and Dame Cicely Saunders found that, if you gave them a steady dose and kept the blood level up at an appropriate level, kept them out of pain, they required less and they were much more wide awake. I speak with some experience because I was associated with setting up the first hospice for people of dying of AIDS in Europe, in fact, so I am not unfamiliar with the subject. The fascinating thing was that, when a patient comes into the hospice, you may take a day or so to sort out what doses they need of the various drugs. But, when you have settled on a dose, by and large it tends to stay at that dose until they die. So this question of some doctors being described as hypocrites, because they are relieving pain but they know very well that they are going to kill the patient, does not obtain.

  Professor Glover: I am glad to hear it. What happens to people who are kept on the stable dose and are still dissatisfied with being alive and request to die? What happens to them?

  Q46  Lord McColl of Dulwich: Your colleagues will probably be in a better position to answer, but I am amazed how many people who do ask for euthanasia, once their symptoms are relieved, no longer do. I am also fascinated by the fact that some of those who ask for euthanasia—I remember one particular man coming into the hospice and he said "I want to die"—he had cancer in his bones—and they said "I am sorry, we do not do that." He asked the next day and the doctor suddenly remembered that his serum calcium—the level of calcium in his blood—was kept down to a safe level by him taking tablets. The doctor said "If you stop taking the tablets, you will be dead in 24 hours". He never stopped taking the tablets until he died.

  Professor Glover: I think that brings out very interestingly this point that there is a real question about how genuine, how deeply felt the euthanasia request is. I think one of the problems is that anecdotes like that influence us very powerfully. There may be many cases like that; there may also be some cases on the other side of the debate—Mrs Pretty's case for instance—which influence people very powerfully too. Much of the difficulty of this debate is that one needs to bring the advocates on both sides into connection with each other and see, as it were, if there is any way of doing justice to the response we have to these kinds of individual cases.

  Q47  Bishop of St Albans: I am very grateful, Professor Glover, for your fundamental moral principles. It seemed to me that lurking within them was something about the nature of the good, but at no point did you define what you thought the good was, either in terms of individuals or in terms of what might be called the common good. I am wondering whether that was a deliberate decision to omit it, or whether it is actually in any case unanswerable?

  Professor Glover: I was brought up in the Oxford philosophy of the early 1960s, in which almost the whole of our philosophy was about the meanings of words like good, right, ought, duty. I like to think that one of the contributions that my generation of philosophers tried to make is to shift discussion towards practical issues of the kind we are discussing today. That is not intended, please, as a put-down of the question you have asked, because obviously there are real questions about what is a good life for a person, what makes life worthwhile; and it would take a very long time for you and I to debate those issues. My inclination is to feel that in practice what one has to do is take the view that it takes all sorts to make a world and all sorts have all sorts of different perceptions of what a good life is, so what we need to do, with any individual patient, whether they are medical or cancer and so on, is try to elicit what that person's deepest values are. They may not be the same as yours and they may not be the same as mine, but really respecting other people seems to me to be a matter to trying to implement for them—so long as it does not conflict with other people's interests—what their perception of the good life is. You also mentioned the good of society, and one dimension of the debate is, if we are doing the right thing for this person, if the slippery slope argument turns out to be right we may be causing worse things down the line, so one needs to take both of those into account. I have not even begun to answer your question but I think I have gestured at some points.

  Bishop of St Albans: I would like to go on, but there are other members.

  Chairman: Earl of Arran.

  Q48  Earl of Arran: Whilst the arguments, the passion and the persuasion sway to and fro amongst the professionals, do you agree that at the end of the day it is for society as a whole to make up its mind on this— whether the law should be changed or not?

  Professor Glover: We live in a democracy and so, ultimately, there is a sense in which all decisions—even as to whether to go to war in Iraq—ought to be in some sense democratic decisions, but as we know we do not take a referendum on every issue. What I feel I am doing in casting my vote for a Member of Parliament is voting for someone who, I hope, has judgement that I can trust. Of course public opinion is a dimension to consider, but I think I would be worried if the implication of your question was that perhaps the whole thing should be decided, either by referendum or focus groups.

  Q49  Earl of Arran: It is in no way an answer of course to create august bodies of professional advisers. But at the end of the day, if there is no agreement amongst professionals, which normally there is not, probably in particular on this Bill, society should as a whole be included in the decision.

  Professor Glover: What does that mean—society should be included in the decision?

  Q50  Earl of Arran: The general public as a whole— the wish of the public as an entirety in itself—obviously accepting professional advice at the same time.

  Professor Glover: How does one measure the wish of the public?

  Q51  Earl of Arran: It is very difficult to know, it is probably for the government of the day to decide upon that.

  Professor Glover: I suppose that, while I am a democrat in spirit, I am also someone who is very glad that capital punishment was abolished, despite the fact that at that time there was a strong majority in favour of it. I do not think I am a majoritarian who thinks that whatever the majority opinion is must be right. For instance, if we lived in a society where there was a racist majority, we might nonetheless be likely to have to have legislators who would not reflect that particular aspect of opinion.

  Q52  Baroness Thomas of Walliswood: I wonder if you, Professor Glover, have had any thought about the differences, from a moral or ethical point of view, between the fact that a patient may refuse treatment and the fact that patients may be unresuscitated without being told that, and the fact that now we are thinking about allowing a patient to request to have her/his own life ended. What are the moral differences between all those things? They seem to be very close together in that they are different approaches to things that are actually quite similar. I am asking the question because I think we have all been approached on the subject of the slippery slope, and what I , I suppose, want you to tell me—you are not going to, I know that—is, if we pull that last thread, the thread that is representing this Bill, are we going to suddenly find a whole decoulage of things collapsing because we have taken that one step which is essentially different from the other steps we take in approach to the end of life?

  Professor Glover: I will not discuss that after such a brief acquaintance. You have sussed me out so well as to know that I am not going to tell you the answer. I suppose what I want to say is that there are two different types of issues here; one is, is there a logical distinction that can be brought between these different kinds of actions or failures to act; and the other is, whether or not there is logical distinction, will introducing one kind of thing lead causally to another? I defer to Penney on the factual question, which is one reason why I am not going to answer this question, because she has studied the effects in different places of bringing in legislation of one kind or another and I have not; so I am not going to pontificate on the factual side. I simply say that I think one can draw logical distinctions, but I take it that the central distinction is between acts of euthanasia that result from respecting the person's autonomy—and that involves thoroughly investigating what their deep wishes are and not some immediate fleeting request—and those that are taken by someone else in what are taken to be the person's interests. I think that is a distinction which in logic can be maintained; it seems to me a socially very important one to maintain, but whether there actually is going to be an empirical side is a matter for Penney rather than me.

  Q53  Baroness Hayman: Can I follow that up and ask you whether you feel there is an ethical divide? One of the issues that troubles me most is between the would-be suicide patient who has the physical capacity to end their own life and is able so to do and some of the most difficult and troubling cases which, as we have heard, do not often receive the palliative care that they need—palliative care is not always available and palliative care is very difficult to tailor—particularly in cases of degenerative disease. Do you feel that ethically as a society there is an issue about allowing the situation to continue where autonomy is available to one group and not to the other, simply by virtue of disability or the nature of their terminal disease?

  Professor Glover: I have a couple of things to say about that. One is that it seems to me discriminatory and objectionable that somebody who is capable of committing suicide is able to do that, but somebody who happens to lack the physical capacity to do that is denied it. That seems to me a case of those who have the physical ability having more rights than people who do not, and I think that is harsh and unjust. On the other hand, the question of degenerative diseases seems to me an extremely difficult one, because part of the problem with something like Dementia is that as, you get into the position where you might rationally prefer to be dead, you may at the same time become not competent to make the request. That seems to me to be a very, very difficult area.

  Q54  Baroness Hayman: Motor Neurone Disease is perhaps an easier example than Dementia to deal with in that area .

  Professor Glover: Yes.

  Q55  Baroness Hayman: One other philosophical question. You said you were not a majoritarian. Can I ask you about minorities and the protection of minority rights here. Do you think there is a philosophical issue or do you think perhaps that in legal terms it is important for us to understand— even if this is a desire or popular with a very small minority of those who will be actually affected, should that sway our judgment as legislators? Even if the 3 per cent who do not have the will to live come down to 1 per cent and actually wish to avail themselves, is it important that it is 1 per cent or 10 per cent or 20 per cent? What weight should we give to that?

  Professor Glover: It seems to me not hugely important because under this proposed Bill or legislation broadly of this type no one who does not want to have access to assisted dying is going to be made to do so, so the question of respecting the rights—if that is the correct terminology—of the minority— whether it is three per cent, one per cent or whatever— who do feel that they want this control over their lives, do want to be able to make this request and have some chance of it being acted on, is covered; and even if it is a small minority that still does not seem to me to matter. If I may again use the analogy of capital punishment, one of the arguments against capital punishment is the fact that sometimes innocent people might have been executed and, whereas you could make some sort of redress if someone is wrongly convicted and sent to prison you cannot do anything if you have already executed a person. I am still worried about that, even if it is only one person; and, if there is one person who desperately wants to avoid incontinence and misery and is denied that, that seems to me serious and much more serious than the fact that other people may not agree that they should have the right.

  Q56  Baroness Hayman: How would we ever know if there was one person who availed themselves of the right to assisted dying who would have changed their mind about it the next day?

  Professor Glover: You are absolutely right— there are risks in both things. In the status quo there is the risk that people who really do have a long-term desire, for serious reasons, reflecting their deepest values, who want to die are denied that; on the other hand, if we bring in the Bill, on the other side of course there is the risk that people are going to take a decision which they think is serious, and we are going to sometimes fail probably to pick up the fact that it is a temporary mood of depression. There are risks both ways.

  Q57  Lord Patel: I have a question for Dr Lewis. I think in your presentation, if I understood it correctly, you put particular emphasis on the need for there to be a doctor/patient relationship to exist in society for there to be such legislation. Can you enlarge on that?

  Ms Lewis: I think that is one of the big distinctions between The Netherlands and other jurisdictions, in particular Oregon, and I think that is one of the reasons why the Dutch have sometimes said that you should be careful about translating their experience, for example, into the US context, partly because they have a very different healthcare system where everyone is entitled to healthcare, unlike the US, but also they do have a system where people tend to have very long-standing relationships with their general practitioners, and it tends to be the general practitioner who would provide euthanasia. I think both in terms of generally knowing their patients and knowing what kind of person they are, having a long-standing relationship helps with that, particularly when you look at the criteria for the request— that it has to be competent and it has to be voluntary and well-informed. I think as a professional—and the evidence bears this out—it is much easier to assess competence if you can do it over a series of visits. One of the concerns that has been raised in the literature on Oregon is that often there are very, very short relationships and people are being asked to evaluate competence in half an hour, and even if there is a referral it is still only one meeting. Those issues about whether we are getting it right that Jonathan was just speaking about— the dangers of missing a depression diagnosis etc—are more serious if you are in a situation where there is not a longstanding physician/patient relationship. Particularly, I think, if you look at Oregon, there is quite a lot of evidence—interestingly, halfway through the Oregon period they stopped collecting some of this evidence, which I found worrying—that more than half of the people who obtained a prescription did not get it from the first doctor they asked, which makes it even more likely that they are getting it from someone that they have never met before or that they have only met very, very briefly. If you look at the evidence that they are still collecting, which is on how long was their doctor/patient relationship, the median over the last six years has been 13 weeks. There is not directly comparable data in The Netherlands, but there certainly is a lot of data that suggests that the GP relationship is the one that most often produces a euthanasia discussion and sometimes an act of euthanasia, but that tends to be many years in length. I think that that is a concern, both in terms of evaluating the translatability of evidence from one jurisdiction to another but also, I would say, it is something that we might want to consider when deciding what kind of doctor should be able to participate in this, whether we would want some sort of requirement that it be evaluated by someone who has at least known me for some period of time, whether that person be a GP or, if there has been a diagnosis of illness that has gone on for some time, that person could be a consultant specialist. What we might want to avoid is the situation in Oregon where, to put it in quite blunt language, I think there is some evidence of doctor-shopping— in other words, you ask one doctor and, if that doctor says no, maybe because that doctor has some concern about your competence and your voluntariness or the durability of your request etc, you go and find another doctor. I think our healthcare system would probably prevent that for the most part, but there is not an explicit safeguard about that in the Bill and it is something that is worth considering, because it is what distinguishes The Netherlands from other jurisdictions.

  Q58  Lord Patel: If we take the example of The Netherlands, at the time when they were at the same stage as we are— of discussing the issue whether to legislate or not, we have heard the same issue turned the other way round— that it is the very relationship that the general practitioner may have with the patient's family that would make them an unlikely candidate to assist. This is something that was different.

  Ms Lewis: You mean a general feeling that, in this country, general practitioners would be reluctant to assist?

  Q59  Lord Patel: Yes.

  Ms Lewis: I do not think you can say when The Netherlands were in the same position as we are, because they never were. There was never a big conversation in The Netherlands 25 years ago saying "Should we have a law?" They developed their law through a series of judicial decisions and eventually a set of prosecutorial guidelines, which were incorporated in a regulatory manner. So they did have a big discussion but it was not the same kind of discussion; it was not a discussion about "Here is a law". Eventually they had some discussions about passing draft laws, but it was many years after euthanasia had become very well established in The Netherlands. Your question is interesting about why is it that GPs in The Netherlands seem to be willing to do this but maybe some GPs over here would not be. And I do not think that there is any evidence that really explains that, except that there are some discussions in the Dutch literature about the Dutch character generally and why it makes sense, given the Dutch character and Dutch history etc, that this has developed in The Netherlands. But that discussion in the literature is not really at all specific as to why Dutch GPs are more favourable than GPs in this country. They certainly do not in any way force doctors to participate in euthanasia in The Netherlands and there are many doctors who do not, but they are actually quite a small proportion in comparison with what I would expect would be the case here. One of the concerns about doctor-shopping is that, if you end up in a situation where only a small number of doctors are willing to perform euthanasia, you do of course have a higher risk that the doctor who performs it does not know the patient very well, because if those doctors who do know the patient very well are not willing to participate—and I think that may be what is happening in Oregon—then people in the community, your patients, will talk and they will find out who is going to be willing to write a prescription, then they go and see that person.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Lords home page Parliament home page House of Commons home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005