Select Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill Minutes of Evidence


Examination of Witnesses (Questions 1960 - 1970)

TUESDAY 18 JANUARY 2005

DR DAVID COLE, BARONESS GREENGROSS MP, PROFESSOR RAYMOND TALLIS, DR GEORG BOSSHARD, and DR CAROLE DACOMBE

  Q1960  Bishop of St Albans: Of course, I would assume that any of us around this table would jump in or throw the life belt. We would do our utmost to save somebody in that situation. Which raises the question in my mind—and it is a totally open question, therefore—when somebody has exercised, in that case, as they have, their own personal autonomy, what is it about us that says there are other higher values—and I am not talking in a religious sense—values besides autonomy, to which we need to give attention? Would it be, for instance, unreconstructed paternalism to leap in and save him? I venture to suggest no. That is what any of us would morally wish to do.

  Professor Tallis: In different situations there are different principles that come to the fore. It seems to me that in this particular principle of the person jumping over the bridge it is totally appropriate and the principle of beneficence would rise above the principle of autonomy until you sort through what is going on. In the situation of a person who is terminally ill and has unbearable suffering, then I think autonomy starts to push into the front and some principled concept of beneficence which overrides what they want starts falling behind. All these principles are in competition and they are appropriate ahead or behind in different contexts.

  Bishop of St Albans: I was only trying to establish exactly that. That is exactly the problem, is it not?

  Q1961  Lord Joffe: To what extent do you feel that you and your team can form a judgment on competence?

  Dr Dacombe: Competence is a very large area. What we are essentially talking about here, and what I personally would feel comfortable to talk about, is the fact that an individual's capacity for decision-making, I believe, is "judgeable" at a moment in time. There are structures, check-lists, if you like, that you can use to help form that judgment, and that is to do with issues such as assessing whether a patient can hear information, take it on board, process it, repeat it and come out with a decision that clearly takes into account their circumstances and the information they have been given. That is a process that on occasions we do follow in quite a formal manner with patients. If you are uncertain about that, then clearly you would want to seek advice and support from colleagues, at consultant psychiatrist or consultant clinical psychologist level, to add to your assessment. In other words, if you have doubts, you would want to seek further support. I believe that at a moment in time it is possible. There is a very important issue to bear in mind which has been alluded to by Dr Cole, which is that clearly disease processes can change and the medication that they are on can change. Dr Cole referred previously to opioid-analgesia, for instance, the dose of which can obviously change, and, depending on the rate of change of that dose, it could clearly be affecting a patient's ability to be fully clear at any moment in time. The patient's capacity for decision-making can change over a period of time, but at a moment in time I believe it is possible for it to be assessed. Any of us could be doubtful after our own assessment, and we might clearly then want to refer to colleagues for assistance and back-up.

  Q1962  Lord Joffe: The patients to whom you referred with whom you have had these discussions about wishing to die, would you feel that they were competent?

  Dr Dacombe: I would. Certainly the discussions to which I have referred in my presentation have been discussions with patients whom I fully believed were competent.

  Q1963  Baroness Jay of Paddington: I realise it is late in the session but I really wanted to raise with you two questions which have come out of this extremely helpful discussion about the concepts you have used this morning, which I personally have found extremely helpful. One is this concept of "intractable distress" as not opposed to but a differentiation from the one which is in the Bill about "unbearable suffering". Intractable distress conveys to me, in the way that you have conveyed it, a great deal. The other was on the points which Professor Tallis raised about the "prognosis for improvement"—again, a broader concept than something which limited a definition of availability for this kind of end-of-life decision to a period of time. I wonder if I could get your reactions to that concept as well. Beyond that, there is the more mundane issue, on which perhaps Dr Dacombe or Baroness Greengross may be the most appropriate to reflect, which is the whole question about how the health service and the social services, as I understand it—particularly in relation to hospice funding—do have concepts of terminal disease in the availability of funding, which they use precisely to define the way in which they can support people who are already in hospice care or, indeed, have a definition of their terminal prognosis. That is a more practical, mundane issue, but I would be interested if you would explore that a little. On the broader conceptual point, I realise it is rather later in the session to get into that, and it may be that I just want to put it on the record.

  Professor Tallis: Why I prefer "intractable distress"—which is not my phrase but I think may be Sally's phrase—to unbearable suffering, is that it does show that it has both objective and subjective features. It seems to me you have to meet certain objective criteria first. If you do not have any obvious cause of suffering, then clearly it would be totally inappropriate even to consider somebody for assisted dying if they have not been through the whole process in terms of alleviation. You have to have objective criteria and then the person themselves says whether these objective criteria translate into something subjective: unbearable suffering. I do like the idea of intractable distress because it relates to attempts to alleviate it. On prognosis for improvement, there are, in a sense, two filters there as well. We have the filter: "Yes, somebody is very, very unlikely to live more than six months" or whatever the barrier is, but, in addition: "They are even less likely to get an improvement in these appalling symptoms which they cannot bear." It seems to me there are two filters built into the criteria for qualifying for assisted dying.

  Dr Dacombe: I am not sure exactly what you would like me to comment on.

  Q1964  Baroness Jay of Paddington: I was asking you a factual question because of my muddled remembrance of health and social care funding—which is very complex anyway. I thought I understood that there was—which you would know as a director of a hospice—a specific understandable objective criteria for funding which was used by the social and health services on a time-based arrangement.

  Dr Dacombe: Certainly, in terms of providing for the continuing care of patients who have a requirement for that, there is actually a cut-off point between health care and social service care which is set at the eight week mark in most areas. If a patient is to receive a package of care to support them in the community, in their own home, or is to be supported by the state in the funding of a placement in a nursing home, there is a point at which there is an expectation that the team in charge of their care—and specifically the doctor in charge of their care—will offer a judgment as to whether their prognosis is under or over eight weeks. Because the funding will come from a health source if it is under eight weeks and a social services support if it is over eight weeks.

  Q1965  Baroness Jay of Paddington: But it involves a prognosis involving time.

  Dr Dacombe: Which does involve a prognosis involving time, yes.

  Q1966  Chairman: I am very interested in what Professor Tallis said a moment ago in answer to the Bishop's parable, that the concept of suffering or intractable distress (whichever concept you use) pushes up the principle of autonomy into a more commanding position than it would have with the gentleman on the Westminster Bridge. The same sort of consideration arises in connection with the general attitude to the care of people who may be in distressing circumstances as, for example, when they go to prison, to protect them against committing suicide. I would find it useful to analyse a little further the concept that you have brought forward there, Professor Tallis, as to what it is that elevates the principle of autonomy and takes the decision out of the kind of range that would apply to people going to prison or somebody just standing on Westminster Bridge.

  Professor Tallis: I suppose the fundamental concept behind autonomy is that you respect the person's wishes, or the wishes that you believe they have. It seems to me that in the case of terminal illness, where you have tried absolutely everything to alleviate the suffering and the outcome is pretty certain, you have a pretty good idea of what the person's wishes are if they express the desire to have assistance in death. The chances of getting it wrong seem to be less. When it comes to the chap jumping over the bridge, clearly this might be a moment of sadness and he would regret it (or not live to regret it) subsequently, and, there, you have so much that is uncertain, you set default to being paternalistic and say, "Well, it is probably not in this chap's best interests and I am going to save him." So it is a different situation. It is partly a difference about knowledge. With a patient who has reached the stage of being considered for assisted dying, one knows an awful lot about the person themselves—what they have been through, what they can stand, what mental science can offer—so you have much more knowledge—which one does not have, of course, for the chap jumping over the bridge.

  Q1967  Chairman: In Oregon—I think you mentioned this yourself in your earlier narrative to us—quite a high proportion of the people who are given the medicine (if that is the right word for it) or the drug, in order to end their lives, do not in fact use it. In a sense, that focuses on the fact that even the decision that they are making to request it—because the doctor has to be pretty sure that they really do want it—is qualified somewhat by the possibility that they may reconsider and in fact not use the medication. It was put to us rather eloquently by one of those who were helping us in Oregon that the idea of having this medicine gives people a kind of insurance that if matters get really bad they will not have to continue, and in fact the experience has been in quite a number of cases that it never gets that bad that they want to use the medication. Is that an important factor, in your view, in considering what is a wise proposal to make here?

  Professor Tallis: It is, because it is not as if they have boarded a train they cannot get off. Obviously it is built into the Bill that you have a minimum period of consideration. It also relates to what the Bishop of St Albans was saying—I think it was about collateral—and it seems to me that this is a good example of collateral. Many more people are helped by having access to assisted dying than actually avail themselves of this particular facility. So the knowledge that there is a way out if you need it may make unbearable suffering—at least temporarily, anyway—more bearable.

  Q1968  Baroness Hayman: Could I come back like a terrier to this 38 per cent or 41 per cent of people in Oregon who feel a burden and quote that as one of the reasons for dying. Do you feel that it is possible in your experience of seeing patients for people to have very strong distaste for needing help, completely divorced from any pressure from others to give them a sense that they are being a burden? Obviously none of us would want people to undertake the important decision because others have made them feel that they should no longer continue. However, in observation—the Bishop has sanctioned the use of personal illustration—my husband had a slipped disc two years ago. He hated, absolutely hated, the situation and considered himself to be a burden. I really do not believe I was making him feel that way. I hope not! I use this as an illustration because of evidence we have had about personality type. Have you experienced, with other patients, a phenomenon of people who, without even the burdens of society making them feel that way, or relatives pressurising them to feel that way—indeed, relatives not wanting them to feel that way—still find that part of their personal makeup is a strong distaste for being in a situation where they need carers?

  Professor Tallis: I think that is a very good point. Being a burden is not always internalising external pressure, which I think is the essence of what you are saying.

  Q1969  Baroness Hayman: Much more eloquently than I did.

  Professor Tallis: It is absolutely right that one may not wish to feel a burden. Obviously, in your husband's case he did not mind feeling a burden, in the sense he knew there was some way out, and the suffering that was unbearable ultimately was going to end up all okay. It just seemed to me that in the context of an illness that has only one outcome, a multiplicity of unpleasant, unalleviated symptoms, then your own decision that you do not want to be a burden is not actually, as I say, internalising external pressures. Having said that, I thought I responded very badly to what Lord McColl said about the paper because I was racking my brain to remember the data which I half remembered. If I recall correctly, and I may have got this wrong—I think this is the Ganzini paper—the feeling of burden, although it may have affected X per cent, was, first of all, not the sole feeling or motivator for people who took assisted dying, even where they felt a burden. I may be wrong on that and it may have to be corrected.

  Q1970  Lord Joffe: You are right on that. Indeed what the report said and the Department of Health in Oregon also said was that it was one of several reasons. In rating the reasons, burden came a lot lower than loss of control, autonomy and independence.

  Professor Tallis: Yes. I thought that.

  Dr Dacombe: I would like to endorse Professor Tallis's remarks about this definition of burden not necessarily being an internalisation of external pressures. I do think people do define what being a burden is for themselves. Certainly I have encountered patients who would perceive their life and the prospect of living their life to the end to be a burden, whether it is a burden to them or a burden to others, and that is based on their definition, perhaps despite a very loving and supportive family, friends and all the services being available to them.

  Baroness Hayman: Thank you.

  Chairman: Thank you very much indeed. As I said, you will get a chance to review the transcript in due course in order to ensure that it says what you did say. We are very grateful to you for your help. I am sorry this session has run on rather longer than we had anticipated. That is a measure of the help you have been able to give us. Thank you very much.


 
previous page contents next page

House of Lords home page Parliament home page House of Commons home page search page enquiries index

© Parliamentary copyright 2005