Memorandum by the All-Party Parliamentary
Pro-Life Group
SUMMARY
1. The All-Party Parliamentary Pro-life
Group upholds the sanctity of human life from conception until
natural death. Every human being, regardless of disability or
physical or mental health, possesses a fundamental worth and dignity
for as long as he or she is alive. Recognition of the fundamental
worth and dignity of every human being is the indispensable foundation
of justice in society.
2. The prohibition against intentional killing
is fundamental to our whole legal system. The 1993-94 House of
Lords Select Committee on Medical Ethics declared that this prohibition
is "the cornerstone of law and of social relationships.
" (Para 237)
3. The Assisted Dying for the Terminally
Ill Bill ("the Bill") would fatally undermine the prohibition.
Allowing doctors to help their patients to die corrupts the doctor-patient
relationship.
4. Rules in our moral and legal codes against
actively causing the death of another person are not isolated
fragments. They are threads in a fabric of rules that support
respect for human life. The more threads we remove, the weaker
the fabric becomes.
5. We do not propose to look in any detail
at the substance of the Bill. Tinkering with a Bill which seeks
to legalise euthanasia and assisted suicide will not spare society
from its disastrous consequences.
6. We propose to focus on three particular
issues; the conclusions of the House of Lords Select Committee
on Medical Ethics, ethical arguments against intentional killing
of the type envisaged by the Bill and practical arguments against
the Bill.
THE CONCLUSIONS
OF THE
HOUSE OF
LORDS SELECT
COMMITTEE ON
MEDICAL ETHICS
7. After extensive consideration the Committee's
Report unanimously recommended amongst others that: There should
be no change in law to permit euthanasia." (Para 278);
"We recommend no change in law on assisted suicide.
" (Para 295)
8. The conclusions of the Select Committee
on Medical Ethics are as pertinent now as they were nine years
ago. We ignore them at our peril. We fail to see what has happened
in society in the intervening decade that would lead your Select
Committee to endorse the Bill and thereby disagree with your predecessor's
unanimous conclusion. In particular, palliative care and the management
of pain have improved. "The Law in its present form needs
no change for comprehensive and effective management of distress
and agitation, including high doses of analgesia and sedation,
at any stage of disease, which is safe and effective if given
by personnel properly trained in Specialist Palliative Care. To
infer otherwise is misleading and mischievous. "[151]
9. Since 1994 there have been a number of
high profile cases that have sought to advance the argument for
euthanasia and assisted suicide. One cannot fail to be moved by
the tragic cases of individuals like Diane Pretty and Reginald
Crew. We recognise the suffering of patients with Motor Neurone
Disease and similarly debilitating diseases and acknowledge the
anguish of the families who care for loved ones with these conditions.
10. However, it is worth recalling the conclusions
of the Select Committee on Medical Ethics: "individual
cases cannot reasonably establish the foundation of a policy (the
legalisation of euthanasia) which would have such serious and
widespread repercussions . . . the issue of euthanasia is one
in which the interest of the individual cannot be separated from
the interest of society as a whole. " (Para 237)
11. As parliamentarians we recognise, as
no doubt you do, that we have a duty to legislate for society
as a whole, not for individual cases. Experience with abortion
legislation has taught us that no matter how well-intentioned
proponents of legislation may be, where the legalisation of intentional
killing is concerned it is impossible to introduce adequate safeguards
against abuse.
ETHICAL ARGUMENTS
AGAINST THE
ASSISTED DYING
FOR THE
TERMINALLY ILL
BILL
12. The Select Committee on Medical Ethics
correctly noted that the prohibition on intentional killing "protects
each one of us impartially, embodying the belief that all are
equal." (Para 237). They had no wish to see that protection
diminished.
13. There is wholeness to our human nature,
not a dualistic account of a biological life and a biographical
life with the latter taking precedence over the former. Human
beings share equally an intrinsic dignity and value by virtue
of our shared humanity.
14. Consequently, " [I]n sustaining
human bodily life, in however impaired a condition, one is sustaining
the person whose life it is. In refusing to choose to violate
it, one respects the person in the most fundamental and indispensable
way".[152]
15. It is in this context that the Select
Committee on Medical Ethics referred to the prohibition on the
killing of innocent human beings as providing the cornerstone
of whatever rights an individual may have.
16. Nowadays we hear so much talk of autonomy,
the right to do with one's life as one chooses. Autonomy is one
of the buzzwords of the pro-euthanasia lobby. Properly understood
the concept of autonomy, in particular the right to refuse medical
treatment, is designed not to give persons a right to decide whether
to live or die but to protect them from the unwanted interferences
of others. The concept is rooted in the notion of the intrinsic
value and dignity of the human person and thus can be overridden
when autonomy is exercised in ways which contravene this notion
or place other members of society at risk of harm.
17. A proper understanding of autonomy should
lead you to reject Lord Joffe's Bill. The Bill has the potential
to compromise the autonomy of some of the most vulnerable members
of society, not least the terminally ill, the disabled and the
elderly.
18. One must also consider the autonomy
of members of the medical profession. The Joint Committee on Human
Rights has declared the conscience clause in the Bill[153]
to be contrary to the European Convention on Human Rights under
Article 9(1), respect for the individual's right to freedom of
thought, conscience and religion.
19. It is a sad fact that there are now
very few gynaecologists practising in the United Kingdom who are
opposed to abortion. Abortion is such a standard gynaecological
practice that it is nigh impossible to specialise in that field
and refuse to carry out abortions. Doctors opposed to abortion
have been forced to specialise in other areas where no such ethical
conflict arises.
20. If euthanasia and assisted suicide were
legalised we would witness a similar phenomenon in geriatric care,
in palliative care and in the hospice movementregardless
of whether the legislation contained a conscience clause. Doctors
opposed to these practices would gradually be squeezed out.
PRACTICAL ARGUMENTS
AGAINST THE
ASSISTED DYING
FOR THE
TERMINALLY ILL
BILL
21. We believe that it is no coincidence
that the organisations representing those who would be affected
most by the Billthe elderly, the terminally ill, the disabled
and the medical professionare opposed to any change in
the law to allow euthanasia and assisted suicide.
22. The Disability Rights Commission does
not support the legalisation of voluntary euthanasia and assisted
suicide. It argues that "in the current climate of discrimination
against disabled people, where a lack of access to palliative
care and social support means that free choice does not really
exist, the threat to the lives of disabled people posed by such
legislation is real and significant." [154]
23. The British Medical Association is also
opposed. "The BMA has consistently opposed euthanasia
and physician assisted suicide . . . we believe that in the case
of euthanasia and assisted suicide, benefit for an individual
in terms of having their wishes respected, is only achievable
at too high a cost in terms of potential harm to society at large.
"[155]
24. Beverley Malone, General Secretary of
the Royal College of Nursing has declared that "The RCN
believes that the practice of euthanasia is contrary to the public
interest, to nursing and medical ethical principles as well as
patients' civil rights. The RCN is opposed to the introduction
of any legislation which would place responsibility on nurses
and other medical staff to respond to a demand for termination
of life from any patient . . . ".[156]
25. Bodies representing those working within
the Hospice Movement and the palliative care sector argue that
euthanasia, once accepted, "is uncontrollable for philosophical,
logical and practical reasons rather than slippery slopes of moral
laxity or idleness. Patients will almost certainly die without
and against their wishes if such legislation is introduced.
"[157]
26. The most recent independent UK survey
of doctors' opinions on this matter[158]
revealed that almost three out of four doctors (74 per cent) would
refuse to perform assisted suicide if it were legalised. A clear
majority (56 per cent) also considered that it would be impossible
to set safe bounds to euthanasia. To the question "As a doctor
do you agree with assisted suicide?" 25 per cent agreed,
60 per cent disagreed and 13 per cent were undecided. The number
who rejected euthanasia was higher61 per cent as compared
with 22 per cent in favour and 14 per cent undecided. Not one
palliative care doctor who responded to the survey would practice
either euthanasia or assisted suicide while 66 per cent of doctors
considered that the pressure for euthanasia would be lessened
if there were more resources for the hospice movement.
27. In the face of such overwhelming opposition
from those who would be affected most by the Bill it is impossible
to envisage how it could be practically implemented.
28. One must also consider what has happened
in those jurisdictions where euthanasia and/or assisted suicide
has been legalised.
29. In Oregon, where assisted suicide was
legalised in October 1997, more than a third of the patients in
one study requested assistance in suicide because they perceived
themselves as a burden to others.[159]
Thankfully, only three of these patients received prescriptions
for lethal medications which suggests that physicians were reluctant
to accede to patients' requests for assistance with suicide.
30. Furthermore, there is little evidence
of any improvement in palliative care services in Oregon. According
to a recently published study by Oregon Health and Science University,[160]
half of the family members of dying patients surveyed between
2002 and 2002 said their loved ones' pain was moderate or severe
in the week before they died. Prior to 1997 when assisted suicide
was legalised in Oregon, only one-third of family members surveyed
rated the pain as moderate or severe.
31. The latest empirical evidence from the
Netherlands contained in the official report by Van der Wal and
Van der Maas[161]
notes that the frequency of ending of life without the patient's
explicit request has shown no decline over the years studied,
1990, 1995 and 2001. In 2001, the most recent year for statistics
are available, 900 out of 3,800 cases of euthanasia or assisted
suicide (approximately one-quarter) were without the patient's
explicit request.
32. The latest official report on euthanasia
in the Netherlands[162]
also shows that only 54 per cent of cases of euthanasia were reported
to the regulatory authority and "life terminating treatment
without explicit request of the patient is still seldom reported
(less than one per cent)." According to a press reports,
the low notification rate is because doctors wished to avoid the
"administrative hassle" of reporting a euthanasia
case and were concerned they might have breached the regulations.[163]
33. In a study published in the New England
Journal of Medicine in 2000 it was reported that one of the problems
most frequently reported with the performance of euthanasia and
physician assisted suicide in the Netherlands is a "longer
than expected interval between the administration of the lethal
drug . . . and the patient's death. "[164]
34. The following excerpt from this study
gives a chilling glimpse into the practical difficulties with
euthanasia and physician assisted suicide: "In most of
these cases, the patient did not die as soon as expected or awoke
from coma, and the physician felt compelled to administer a lethal
injection because of the anticipated failure of the assisted suicide.
In some cases, the physician administered a lethal injection because
the patient had difficulty swallowing the oral medication, vomited
after swallowing it, or became unconscious before swallowing all
of it." So much for death with dignity.
35. Empirical evidence from the Netherlands
reinforces the argument that it is impossible to set safe bounds
to euthanasia so as to ensure that only those who have expressed
a persistent, voluntary and well-considered request are put to
death. The Dutch experience contradicts the claim that legalisation
"brings euthanasia out of the closet" and subjects it
to regulation. It simply produces more euthanasia, not more control.
36. Those in favour of the Bill often allege
that euthanasia and physician assisted suicide are a widely known
fact of medical life, but are usually carried out at the doctor's
discretion or in secrecyhence the need for legislation
and proper regulation. Notwithstanding the Dutch experience where
legalisation has failed to introduce greater regulation, these
allegations are rarely substantiated. They are a slur on the medical
profession and should not be allowed to pass unchallenged.
37. The most recent survey of medical opinion
cited earlier[165]
explodes the idea that people are clamouring for euthanasia. In
response to a question asking how many patients had requested
euthanasia during the past three years nearly half (48 per cent)
of the doctors said not one; 37 per cent quoted less than five;
11 per cent gave numbers between five and 10 patients; only two
per cent gave figures of more than 10. In their comments doctors
said that in their experience requests for euthanasia were often
"cries for help that have been resolved with good symptom
control . . . they almost invariably want relief from distress".
38. The number of requests for euthanasia
from relatives was even lower than from patients themselves. 68
per cent of doctors said that none had approached them in the
last three years; 22 per cent quoted less than five such experiences;
five per cent quoted figures between five and 10 and one per cent
gave numbers of more than 10. Three per cent said they did not
know or that the question was not applicable to them.
39. Proponents of euthanasia and assisted
suicide also conflate these practices with perfectly legitimate
end of life care. Doctors are regularly called upon to decide
to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining treatment in the knowledge
that death will result. However, knowledge that a certain course
of conduct may bring about death does not automatically constitute
euthanasia. Intention or purpose is the key. If treatment is withheld
or withdrawn with the purpose of bringing about death this constitutes
euthanasia and is unethical. However, it is perfectly legitimate
to withhold or withdraw medical treatment when it is considered
that the burdens of such treatment outweigh the benefits, or where
the patient is dying and the treatment would be regarded as unduly
intrusive and inappropriate or where the risks of such treatment
would be excessive.
CONCLUSION
40. We urge your Committee to reject in
its entirety the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill.
41. The Bill would irrevocably and fatally
damage the practice of medicine in the United Kingdom. The most
vulnerable members in our society, the elderly, the terminally
ill and the disabled would be at greatest risk of premature death
if this Bill were implemented.
42. When there is a pressing need to tackle
the under-funding and regional disparities in palliative care
for the terminally ill and personal care packages for the elderly
and those with disabilities it is regrettable that parliamentary
time is being taken up with "assisted dying" legislation.
Of far greater use to the elderly, terminally ill and those with
disabilities would be some form of "assisted living"
legislation.
43. We would be happy to appear before your
Committee to give oral evidence.
Jim Dobbin MP
Chairman, All-Party Parliamentary Pro-life Group
Ann Winterton MP, Lord Stallard, Baroness Masham
of Ilton, Claire Curtis-Thomas MP, Rt Hon Ann Widdecombe MP
Vice-Chairmen, All-Party Parliamentary Pro-life Group
Joe Benton MP, Kerry Pollard MP
Honorary Secretaries, All-Party Parliamentary Pro-life
Group
Rev Martin Smyth MP, Andrew Selous MP
Honorary Treasurers, All-Party Parliamentary Pro-life
Group
August 2004
151 The Patient (Assisted Dying) Bill: A joint briefing
paper by the Association for Palliative Medicine and the National
Council for Hospice and Specialist Palliative Care Services-May
2003. Presented in the House of Lords on 3 June 2003. Back
152
Finnis, J M, "A philosophical case against euthanasia"
in Keown, J, (ed) Euthanasia Examined-Ethical, clinical and
legal perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1995) p 32. Back
153
Clause 7 of the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill. Back
154
Disability Rights Commission policy statement on voluntary euthanasia
and assisted suicide; http://www.drc-gb.org/uploaded_files/documents/10_444_181203_Euthanasia.doc. Back
155
BMA Briefing on the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill:
http://wvvw.bma.org.ulc/ap.nsf/Content/Assisteddying. Back
156
Hemmings, P, "Dying Wishes" Nursing Times 25
November 2003, Vol 99, No 47, p 20. Back
157
The Patient (Assisted Dying) Bill: A joint briefing paper by the
Association for Palliative Medicine and the National Council for
Hospice and Specialist Palliative Care Services-May 2003. Presented
in the House of Lords on 3 June 2003. Back
158
Survey on Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide Prepared for "Right
to Life" lobby group. Results from 986 interviews 26 March-9
April 2003. Opinion Research Business, 9-13 Cursitor Street, London,
EC4A ILL; www.opinion.co.uk. Back
159
Ganzini et al, "Physicians" Experiences with
the Oregon Death with Dignity Act', New England Journal of
Medicine, Vol 342, 2000, No 8, p 557. Back
160
Nowak, P, "Palliative Care for Elderly, Disabled, Worse Since
Assisted Suicide Legalised", http://www.lifenews.com/bio406.html. Back
161
Van der Wal and P Van der Maas, Chapter 19 of their report on
euthanasia, 2003. See also Dr Bregje D Onwuteaka-Phillipsen
et al, "Euthanasia and other end of life decisions
in the Netherlands in 1990, 1995 and 2001", The Lancet,
17 June 2003: http://image.thelancet.com/extras/03art3297web.pdf. Back
162
Ibid. Back
163
Report from the Expatica news website on 23 May 2003; www.expatica.com. Back
164
Groenewoud et al, "Clinical Problems With The Performance
Of Euthanasia And Physician-Assisted Suicide In The Netherlands",
New England Journal of Medicine, Vol 342, 2000, No 8, p
551. Back
165
Survey on Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide Prepared for "Right
to Life" lobby group. Results from 986 interviews 26 March-9
April 2003. Opinion Research Business, 9-13 Cursitor Street, London,
EC4A ILL; www.opinion.co.uk. Back
|